Brickfields Asia College
Transcription
Brickfields Asia College
Issue 2 April - June 2012 BRICKFIELDS LAW REVIEW Parliamentary Sovereignty An Illusion or Reality? Commission Agent Theory Reconciling Wright J in Montgomerie’s case John Austin Is Hart’s Criticism Against Austin’s Command Theory Fair? Section 114(1)(d) Criminal Justice Act 2003 A Discussion on the Discretion of a Judge in Respect of Admitting Hearsay Evidence Pursuant to the Safety Valve Exception RM12.90 KDN PP 17639/01/2013(031585) In collaboration with R R w w w . b a c . e d u . m y THE NATION’S #1 LAW SCHOOL Mallal’s Criminal Procedure Ha ISB rd Co N 9 ver 78 -96 7-4 00 -07 6-9 Seventh Edition Updated by Noor Azman bin Adnan & James Selladurai Thanjong Tuan Order Now! RM520 only Over a period of fifty-five years, Dr Bashir Mallal’s progressive editions of Mallal’s Criminal Procedure have established an enviable and respected tradition. This Seventh Edition continues Dr Mallal’s aims of providing the legal profession with an authoritative and practical guide to the criminal procedure and practice of both the Superior and Subordinate Courts in Malaysia. This work serve to simplify the arduous task of research into its vast area of law, and make transparent the often complex process of the administration of criminal justice and procedure in Malaysia. Mallal’s Criminal Procedure contains detailed annotations to all the sections of the Criminal Procedure Code. These annotations, supported by relevant authorities, explain and analyse important aspects of criminal procedure as well as provide useful information such as the history of each section and similarities, if any, to the Indian Criminal Procedure Code 1973 and the Singapore Criminal Procedure Code 2010. They facilitate a better understanding of criminal procedure and serve as signposts for further research. The annotations to each section have been organised according to the following: (1) Scope (or synopsis) of section; (2) Cross-references to statutes, encyclopedias and textbooks; (3) Amendments; and (4) Annotations Other important contents of this edition include the Comparative Table and the full updated text of the Evidence Act 1950 and the Penal Code. Key Features • Extensive references to a selection of scholarly works of up to 2012. • Includes comparative references to key legislations of other jurisdictions. For example, the Singapore Criminal Procedure Code 2010 and the Indian Criminal Procedure Code 1973. • Addresses key provisions of the Indian Criminal Procedure Code 1973 that have been fairly recently substituted, inserted or omitted by the Indian Criminal Procedure Code (Amendment) Act 2005 and the Indian Code of Criminal Procedure (Amendment) Act 2008. Foreword by Tan Sri Edgar Joseph Jr, Former Judge of the Federal Court of Malaysia “Need I say that it is for me, a pleasure to warmly welcome this Seventh Edition of Mallal’s Criminal Procedure. This book worthily carries on the Dr Mallal tradition. To state the obvious, it provides the reader with a model of succinct exposition, combining clarity, thoroughness, and compression. It has been written with the convenience to busy Judges, Legal Practitioners, and Prosecutors; therefore will command a wide readership. The authors deserve to be congratulated with all my heart.” Key Cases • PP v Dato’ Seri Anwar bin Ibrahim [2012] 3 MLJ 353 • Terengganu Forest Products Sdn Bhd v Cosco Container Lines Co Ltd & Anor and other applications [2011] 1 MLJ 25 (FC) • Borhan bin Hj Daud v Abd Malek bin Hussin [2010] 6 MLJ 329 (CA) • Junaidi bin Bambang v PP [2011] 3 MLJ 141 (CA) • Shahril bin Yahya v PP [2011] 8 MLJ 320 • PP v Dato’ Seri Anwar bin Ibrahim [2010] 2 MLJ 353 (CA) • Dato’ Seri Anwar bin Ibrahim v PP [2010] 2 MLJ 312 (FC) • Magendran a/l Mohan v PP [2010] 6 MLJ 619 (CA) • PP v Vincent Jude a/l Xavier [2010] 9 MLJ 269 • Chian Swee Ong v PP [2010] 4 MLJ 737 (FC) • Mohd Azri bin Abdul Samad v PP [2010] 9 MLJ 211 • Munawar Ahmad Anees v PP [2010] 3 MLJ 285 (FC) • Jambri bin Abd Hamid v Pendakwa Raya [2009] 9 MLJ 683 • PP v Chin Chan Leong & Anor [2009] 8 MLJ 231 • Retnasara a/l Annarasa v PP [2008] 8 MLJ 608 • PP v Chan Wai Heng [2008] 5 MLJ 798 (CA) • Seah Ah Chiew v PP [2007] 1 MLJ 377 • Md Yunus bin Ali v PP [2007] 8 MLJ 330 • Sathiyamurthi v Penguasa/Komandan, Pusat Pemulihan Karangan, Kedah [2006] 6 MLJ 593 (FC) • Balachandran v PP [2005] 2 MLJ 301 (FC) • Bachik bin Abdul Rahman v PP [2004] 2 MLJ 534 (CA) • Murugayah v PP [2004] 2 MLJ 545 (CA) Order Now! via our eBookstore @ www.lexisnexis.com/store/my To purchase, please contact our Helpdesk at Tel: 1800-88-88LN (56) or Email: help.my@lexisnexis.com or Twitter (Helpdesk): @HelpLNMY http://twitter.com/LexisNexisMY/ http://facebook.com/LexisNexisMalaysia/ P Contents 49 Editor in Chief: Raja Singham Editor: Sabah Carrim Sub Editors: Farid Jalil Marketing Manager: Adrian Thomas Publications Manager: Nirmitha Govindaraju Subscriptions: Faceberry Publications Sdn Bhd 68-2 Jalan Tun Sambanthan, 50470 Brickfields, Kuala Lumpur, Malaysia Email: blr@bac.edu.my Tel: (603) 2274 4165 / Fax: (603) 2274 4174 For Advertising & Promotion: Faceberry Communications Sdn Bhd Email: info@faceberry.com.my Tel: (603)2274 4165 / Fax: (603)2274 4174 Contributions and enquiries may be directed to: blr@bac.edu.my Publishing Consultant: LexisNexis Malaysia Sdn Bhd T1-6, Jaya 33, 3, Jalan Semangat Seksyen 13, 46100 Petaling Jaya Selangor Darul Ehsan Malaysia Tel: (603) 7882 3500 / Fax: (603) 7882 3506 Contract Publishing Manager: Ivan Yap Min Kee Design & Production: Ryan Yee Marketing & Advertising: Hasnizam Mohamad Criminal Division 2 Common Law Reasoning & Institutions 4 Public Law 6 Commercial Law 8 Law of Contract 10 Law of Tort 12 Law of Trusts 14 Land Law 16 Evidence 20 Jurisprudence 24 Company Law 28 Conflict of Laws 29 Succession 30 Family Law 32 EU Law 34 Law & Literature 36 Supreme Court – Case Digest: Assange v Swedish Prosecution Authority The Right to Reform Trial by Jury – Michael Zander Parliamentary Sovereignty: An Illusion or Reality? – Kevin Arasu Commission Agent Theory: Reconciling Wright J in Mongomerie’s case – Shantini Sharon Sukumaran ave the Courts Interpreted the Law or gone beyond the Intention H of the Parliament in relation to the Quantum of Damages for Sec 2(1) of Misrepresentation Act 1967? – Murali Kandasamy ourt of Appeal – Case Digest: R (on the application of LE C (Jamaica)) v Secretary of State for the Home Department Chancery Division – Case Digest: Brudenell-Bruce, Earl of Cardigan v Moore and another Printer: Vivar Printing Sdn Bhd (125107-D) A Nightmare for Students? – Nalina Nadarajah Brickfields Law Review is the official publication of Brickfields Asia College, published quarterly in collaboration with Lexis Nexis Malaysia Sdn Bhd, for circulation to students and faculty of Brickfields Asia College as well as major book stores in Malaysia. Section 114(1)(d) Criminal Justice Act 2003- A Discussion on the Discretion of a Judge in Respect of Admitting Hearsay Evidence Pursuant to the Safety Valve Exception – Puvanal Sri Brickfields Asia College and its authorised authors and designers of Brickfields Law Review accept no liability for any loss arising from the use of or reliance on Brickfields Law Review. Brickfields Asia College does not warrant the accuracy of the contents thereof or any statement made by the contributors, writers or advertisers herein, and does not accept responsibility or liability in relation thereto. Statements by contributors, writers or advertisers herein represent their personal views and do not necessarily reflect the views of Brickfields Asia College nor LexisNexis. All users are permitted to view the content of Brickfields Law Review, without prejudice to the intellectual property rights belonging to Brickfields Asia College and LexisNexis. However, any unauthorised reproduction, duplication, transmission or alteration, in any form or by any means, whether in part or in whole, of Brickfields Law Review or LexisNexis is strictly prohibited. Brickfields Asia College also prohibits the use of Brickfields Law Review and all or any of its contents herein, for commercial and/or personal gain, profit or sale. Faceberry Publications Sdn Bhd is the official and exclusive distributor of the Brickfields Law Review. Article Contributions may be e-mailed to: blr@bac.edu.my John Austin: Is Hart’s Criticism Against Austin’s Command Theory Fair? – Puviyal Sri Queen’s Bench Division, Commercial Court – Case Digest: Enercon GmbH and another company v Enercon (India) Ltd Queen’s Bench Division, Commercial Court – Case Digest: West Tankers INC v Allianz SpA (formerly known as Riunione Adriatica Sicurta) and another Outer House, Court of Session – Case Digest: Turner v Turner and others Family: The After-shock – Anna Heenan Through the Back Door? – Trevor Tayleur War Criminals in Kangaroo Courts – Sabah Carrim 2 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Criminal Division Supreme Court Assange v Swedish Prosecution Authority [2012] All ER (D) 232 (May); [2012] UKSC 22/ Before: Lord Phillips, P, Lord Walker, Lady Hale, Lord Brown, Lord Mance, Lord Kerr and Lord Dyson SCJJ 30 May 2012 On 2 December 2010, the respondent Swedish Prosecution Authority issued a European arrest warrant (the “warrant”) requesting the arrest and surrender of the appellant. The appellant was at that time in England, where he remained at the time of the instant hearing. The offences of which he was accused and in respect of which his surrender was sought, were alleged to have been committed in Stockholm against two women in August 2010. They included sexual molestation and, in one case, rape. At the extradition hearing before the senior district Judge, and subsequently on appeal to the Divisional Court, he challenged the validity of the warrant on a number of grounds. One of the grounds was that the warrant had been issued by a public prosecutor who was not a “judicial authority” as required by art 6 of the Council of the European Union Framework Decision on the European arrest warrant and surrender procedures between Member States of the European Union 2002/584/ JHA (the “Framework Decision”) and by ss 2(2) and 66 of the Extradition Act 2003. He argued that a “judicial authority” had to be impartial and independent both of the executive and of the parties, and as prosecutors, were parties in the criminal process, so they could not be independent and impartial. If, contrary to that argument, prosecutors could issue warrants under the Framework Decision, then the appellant contended that they fell outside the definition in the Act, as it was clear that Parliament had intended to restrict the power to issue warrants to a Judge or Court. Following his unsuccessful challenge, the appellant appealed to the Supreme Court. The issue was whether a warrant issued by a public prosecutor was a valid warrant issued by a judicial authority within the meaning of ss 2(2) and 66 of the 2003 Act. The respondent submitted, inter alia, that the phrase “judicial authority” in the context of the Framework Decision and other European instruments bore a broad and autonomous meaning. It described any person or body authorised to play a part in the judicial process. The term embraced a variety of bodies, some of which had the qualities of impartiality and independence and some of which did not. In some parts of the Framework Decision, the term “judicial authority” described one type, in other parts, another. A prosecutor properly fell within the description “judicial authority” and was capable of being the judicial authority competent to issue a warrant under art 6 of the Framework Decision if the law of the state so provided. “Judicial authority” had to be given the same meaning in the 2003 Act as it bore in the Framework Decision. Consideration was given to the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969. The appeal would be dismissed (Lady Hale and Lord Mance dissenting). “Judicial Authority” in Pt 1 of the Act should be accorded the same meaning as it bore in the Framework Decision and that term was properly to be understood as including public prosecutors. The purpose of the Framework decision was to introduce a system of surrender between judicial authorities for those accused or convicted of serious criminal offences, which required each of the member states to give a uniform interpretation of the phrase “judicial authority”. Article 31.3(b) of the 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties permitted recourse as an aid to interpretation to “any subsequent practice in the application of the treaty which established the agreement of the parties regarding its interpretation”. When one considered the daft September Framework Decision, it was beyond doubt that “judicial authority” was a term that embraced both a Court and a public prosecutor. Although the precise definition of “judicial authority” was removed from the final draft, the overall scheme of the warrant did not change from that proposed in the September draft. In particular, there remained a requirement for an antecedent process before the issue of the warrant. Article 2, under the heading Scope of the European Arrest Warrant set out the offences in respect of which a warrant could be issued. Article 8 specified the content of the warrant, which included “(c) evidence of an enforceable judgment, an arrest warrant or any other enforceable judicial decision having the same effect, coming within the scope of articles 1 and 2”. There could be two possible reasons for removing the precise definition of “judicial authority” that had been included in the September draft. The first was to restrict the meaning by excluding from its ambit the public prosecutor. The second was to broaden the meaning so that it was not restricted to a Judge or a public prosecutor. The second explanation was the more probable. Further, there was a strong presumption in favour of interpreting an English statute in a way which did not place the UK in breach of its international obligations In the instant case, the respondent judicial authority who had issued the warrant had been a “judicial authority” within the meaning of that phrase in s 2 of the 2003 Act and, therefore, the appellant’s challenge to the validity of the warrant failed. © LexisNexis 4 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Common Law Reasoning & Institutions The Right to Reform Trial by Jury by Michael Zander Michael Zander considers the prospects for the government’s plans The heading “Right to Jury Trial Faces Axe in Post-riot Reforms” was a front page story in The Times on January 16. Frances Gibb, the paper’s legal editor, reported that a White Paper to be published this month would include a proposal to abolish the right to trial by jury in minor either-way offences. Louise Casey, who advises the government on dealing with the aftermath of the riots, had said that if even half the 70,000 cases heard by the Crown Court were heard instead in Magistrates Court, the savings would amount to £30m. Transferring minor cases to Magistrates Courts would also permit major cases to be heard more quickly. (Ms Casey was quoted: “We should not view the right to a jury trial as being so sacrosanct that its exercise should be at the cost of victims of serious crime. It is known that waiting for a criminal trial often means that victims put their lives on hold: bereaved families of murder victims cannot grieve until the trial.”) Concern for victims is no doubt important, but it is perhaps not unduly cynical to suppose that the government’s thinking is likely to be even more influenced by the potential saving of many millions of pounds. My own chief reaction on reading Frances Gibb’s story was, “here we go again.” Government after government has tried to reduce costs by shifting cases from the Crown Court to the Magistrates Court and over and over again it has been thwarted. The defendant’s right to choose jury trial goes back not - as some maintain - to the Magna Carta, but only to the mid 19th century. The Administration of Criminal Justice Act 1855 gave Magistrates jurisdiction to try simple larceny cases involving sums of under five shillings, but only if the defendant consented. The Summary Jurisdiction Act 1879 gave defendants the right to claim trial by jury for all offences carrying a maximum sentence of more than three months. Today, that right applies to all eitherway offences. There are two ways of shifting cases down to the Magistrates Courts: re-classify them as summary-only or take away the defendant’s right to elect jury trial, leaving the decision as to mode of trial in either-way cases to the Magistrates. The former has sometimes been done successfully; the latter has been tried, but so far, unsuccessfully. In 1975, the James Committee recommended that drink-driving offences, theft cases involving amounts under £20 and criminal damage cases where the damage did not exceed £100 should all become summary-only offences. The government adopted that proposal in the Bill to implement the report. But while the recommendation regarding motoring offences became part of the Criminal Law Act 1977, the proposal to make small theft and small criminal damage cases summary-only was dropped from the Bill after meeting massive opposition. Despite this, in 1980, criminal damage cases involving amounts under £200 became triable only summarily. The Criminal Justice Act 1988 raised the figure to £2,000. The Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 raised it again, to £5,000. In 1986, a Home Office consultation paper canvassed various options for having small theft cases tried in the Magistrates Court. The government included in the Criminal Law Bill a proposal that theft cases involving less than £75 should become summary-only, but again, the proposal was dropped before the Bill became the Criminal Law Act 1988. In 1993, the Runciman Royal Commission on Criminal Justice recommended a radically different approach. The defendant should no longer have a right to demand trial in the Crown Court. It should instead be only a right to ask for trial at the higher level. If the prosecution agreed, that would be sufficient. If the prosecution did not agree, the matter would be decided by the Magistrates Court after hearing representations from both sides. The Court’s decision would be guided by statutory indications as to what factors should be taken into account. These should include the gravity of the offence, the defendant’s prior record, if any, the complexity of the case, the likely sentence, and the likely effect of a conviction on that defendant. 1. The Royal Commission, of which the writer was a member, was unanimous in making this recommendation. The most important of its reasons were: defendants often chose trial by jury believing that it gave them a better chance of an acquittal but it was as wrong to allow this as to give the defendant the choice of a more lenient Judge. 2. Around 70 per cent of those who opted for trial in the Crown Court ended by pleading guilty so that all the time and cost of lawyers, experts and lay witnesses preparing and actually coming for trial was wasted. 3. The number of last minute guilty pleas (“cracked trials”) also caused significant difficulties in running the Courts. The Royal Commission made 352 recommendations. This proved to be by far the most controversial. Critics included the Bar, the Law Society and, crucially, the Lord Chief Justice, Lord Taylor. It has not been implemented. In July 1995, a Home Office consultation paper canvassed three options: (i) adopt the Runciman Royal Commission’s proposal; April - June 2012 (ii) reclassify more either-way offences as summary-only; and (iii) require defendants to enter their plea at the Magistrates Court which would enable many more cases to be disposed of at the lower level. The Criminal Procedure and Investigations Act 1996 adopted a modified version of the third option – inviting rather than requiring a plea before venue. In 1997, Martin Narey, then a senior Home Office official, in his report, Review of Delay in the Criminal Justice System, recommended, like the Royal Commission, that the defendant’s right to demand trial by jury should be abolished. He was even more robust than the Royal Commission. In his view, the question should always be decided by the Court and not be open to agreement between prosecution and defence. In November 1999, the Blair Government introduced the Criminal Justice (Mode of Trial) Bill providing, as recommended by Martin Narey, that mode of trial should be determined only by the Court, after it had heard representations from the parties. The Bill ran into great opposition – especially the provision that the effect of a conviction on the defendant’s reputation and his livelihood would be amongst the factors to be taken into account. Such a provision, it was argued, could create a “two-tier” justice system with magistrates discriminating against the poor in favour of defendants with a higher economic or social status. The Bill, which started in the Lords, suffered a succession of defeats. Removal of the defendant’s right to elect jury trial was defeated on January 20, 2000 by 222 to 126. That was the end of that Bill Undaunted, in February 2000, the Labour Government tried again with its Criminal Justice (Mode of Trial) (No.2) Bill. This time the Bill was introduced in the Commons. But when it reached the Lords it was again defeated and was withdrawn after the second reading debate on September 28. The main difference between the No.1 and the No.2 Bill was the removal of all but one of the factors the Court was permitted to take into account. These were reduced to “the nature of the case” and “the circumstances of the offence (but not of the accused)”. In particular, reference to previous convictions or the effect of a conviction on the accused was no longer to be permitted. (The writer’s comment at the time was entitled “Why Jack Straw’s Jury Reform has Lost the Plot” (NLJ, March 10, 2000, p 366).) Brickfields Law Review In October 2001, Lord Justice Auld in his Review of the Criminal Courts System (pp 197-200) agreed with Runciman and Narey that the decision as to mode of trial in either-way cases should be made not by the defendant but by the Court – after hearing representations from both sides and with a right of appeal to the Crown Court. Some cases by their nature justified the facilities and more searching pre-trial and trial procedures than could be provided by Magistrates Courts. Equally, some cases did not merit the more so elaborate, costly and time-taking procedures of the Crown Court. It was a policy decision, according to the nature and seriousness of the offence, and in the light of the public interest. I hold the same view as I did when I was a member of the Runciman Royal Commission. I believe that the case for removing the defendant’s right to elect jury trial is overwhelming. As a matter of principle, it should be determined on the basis of objective considerations, not on the basis of the accused’s perception of his self-interest, and all the more so since the defendant usually ends by pleading guilty. But that does not translate into optimism that the Coalition Government will be any more successful than previous governments in achieving this reform. Lord Justice Auld said in his report that those opposed at that time included the majority of legal practitioners undertaking criminal work, major civil liberties organisations and ethnic minority groups. Sure enough, Frances Gibb in her article of January 16 quoted Max Hill QC, chairman of the Criminal Bar Association, reacting to the news of the government’s intentions: “So-called minor cases may not lead to prison, but can have a major impact upon the individual and prospects of employment, credit and general livelihood. Yet again, the Government seeks to cut corners on justice, this time by reducing the citizen’s right to trial by jury.” No doubt the Law Society, Liberty and organisations representing ethnic minorities will take up the same cry. The government will pray in aid the riots as justification for trying yet again to shift a significant number of small theft cases to the quicker and cheaper form of trial in Magistrates Court. It would be surprising if that, or indeed any other argument, will persuade their Lordships House. If I were a betting man I would wager that any such proposal will suffer the same fate as before. © LexisNexis 5 6 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Public Law Parliamentary Sovereignty: An Illusion or Reality? by Kevin Arasu In this article, the writer tackles the oft debated issue of the sovereignty of Parliament in the UK, in light of UK’s membership in the European Union and the European Union Act 2011. Through this analysis, the writer hopes to present the reader a succinct picture of the current state of Westminster’s sovereignty. Is the UK Parliament still sovereign? A question that has gripped the minds of many, time and time again. A major stimulus for a debate of this kind lies in the UK’s accession and continued membership, initially in the European Communities (“EC”) and then the European Union (“EU”) for close to 40 years now. In order to fully grasp the impact of the UK’s membership in the EU on Parliamentary sovereignty, it is imperative, first and foremost, that the concept of Parliamentary sovereignty be appreciated to its fullest. The Doctrine and its Theoretical Exposition Parliamentary sovereignty is a distinctive feature of the UK’s unique unwritten constitution and reflects the might and will of the general masses throughout the ages. Through this doctrine, Parliament in Westminster is a mirror of the electorate of the UK and their wishes are given effect through legislation passed therein. Simply put, it embodies the view that Parliament is the most authoritative law-making body, in that it has the absolute right to make and unmake any law in any subject matter whatsoever and that an Act of Parliament is the most supreme of laws in the realm. Bearing in mind such a status, another important exposition of the doctrine is that no person or body, including the Courts, has the right to override or nullify legislation passed by Parliament. Judicial interference towards legislation is deemed unacceptable and taboo under this doctrine. Another pivotal aspect of the doctrine is that Parliament is illimitable, meaning that none of the laws passed by Parliament can be entrenched or in other words, made to last forever. This aspect of the doctrine is made possible through the doctrine of implied repeal, wherein it is the Courts’ duty to give effect to the latest will of Parliament. The preceding theoretical exposition of the doctrine represents an orthodoxical understanding of Parliamentary sovereignty which has been a cornerstone of the British constitution ever since the inception of the Bill of Rights in 1689. Professor Albert Venn Dicey in the introductory notes in ‘An Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution’, expounds that “Purely as a legal doctrine it is too late to question the supremacy of Parliament”. He then goes on to state in chapter 1 of his book, “My aim in this chapter is, in the first place, to explain the nature of Parliamentary sovereignty and to show that its existence is a legal fact, fully recognised by the law of England; in the next place to prove that none of the alleged legal limitations on the sovereignty of Parliament have any existence; and, lastly to state and meet certain speculative difficulties which hinder the ready admission of the doctrine that Parliament is, under the British constitution, an absolutely sovereign legislature”. It has to be noted that times have changed considerably since 1885, the year in which Prof Dicey wrote his book. The orthodoxical understanding of the doctrine has been put to test through various developments of constitutional importance in the UK, the most significant being, for the purposes of this article, the UK’s entry into and continued membership in the EU, which imposes an obligation on the UK to give effect to EU laws, sometimes even at the expense of Acts of Parliament, whenever there is a conflict between the two. Another important jurisprudence of joining the EU is the overarching position of the European Court of Justice (“ECJ”), wherein the decisions of the ECJ are binding on all the member states of the EU. This supremacy of EU laws reflects one of the means through which European integration and supranationalism can be achieved. The Rise of Nationalism in Europe, World War II and European Integration It has been observed that the rise of high nationalist sentiments and the idea of discrete national identities in Europe in the early parts of the 20th century and a growing economic disparity amongst European countries were major catalysts of World War II. Therefore, to avoid a recurrence and the atrocities of a war of such magnitude, European integration and supranational prosperity and security were seen as obvious solutions. With these solutions in mind, six countries, commonly known as the Inner Six, namely, Belgium, The Netherlands, Luxembourg, France, West Germany and Italy formed the EC which was comprised of the European Economic Communities, European Coal and Steel Community and the European Atomic Energy Community, which were later absorbed into the EU, which now has 27 members. A new New Legal Order was sought to be achieved in Europe with common interest and prosperity in mind, in tandem with European integration. These aims are reflected in the treaties that created the EC and then later the EU. A “New Legal Order”: ECJ’s Jurisprudence The ECJ has been instrumental in establishing a New Legal Order in Europe through the upholding of the supremacy of April - June 2012 Brickfields Law Review EU laws over its member states by consistently affirming and reminding member states that the jurisprudence of signing the treaties that formed the EC and later the EU is the surrendering of part of their sovereignty. This “shackling” of sovereignty is seen to be necessary for the attainment of economic uniformity and European integration which are the very essence of the New Legal Order. Every attempt to challenge the supremacy of EU laws was strongly “shot down” by the ECJ which could remarkably be seen in the cases of Van Gend en Loos [1963] CMLR 105, Costa v ENEL [1964] CMLR 425, Internationale Handelsgesellschaft [1972] CMLR 255 and Simmenthal [1978] ECR 629. The core reasoning adopted in all the preceding decisions is that “the entry of member states into the EC by the signing of the treaties carries with it a permanent limitation of their sovereign rights”. It was also stressed through these decisions that EC laws reign supreme over conflicting domestic legislation, both subsequent and prior to the entry of a member state into EU and even over conflicting provisions found in a written constitution of a member state. cases generally represent the view that the UK’s compliance with EU laws, sometimes at the expense of domestic laws, is as a result of the ECA 1972 and not the treaties that were signed. This could naturally mean that if Parliament were to repeal the ECA 1972, which is possible, as no Act of Parliament could be perpetual, the UK Courts would stop applying EU laws. In other words, the UK Courts purely give effect to EU laws because they have been “told” to do so by Westminster. This then brings us to the next question; will the ECA 1972 ever be repealed? It can be said that even though such a possibility remains, its repercussions may be dire, which may put off Parliament from doing so. Therefore, this begs the question as to whether the UK Courts are in denial that EU laws already form an integral part of UK laws and have been deeply entrenched within the legal systems in the UK and that they have no choice but to follow them. The question which then arises is how could the notion of Parliamentary sovereignty, which stresses the supremacy of UK laws, be reconciled with the New Legal Order, which compels the supremacy of EU laws. The European Union Act 2011 (“the Act”) reflects the current administration’s standpoint on the sovereignty of the UK in relation to the EU. One of the provisions therein which purports to reiterate the sovereignty of Westminster is s 18 which is classified as “Status of EU law dependent on continuing statutory basis” and states as follows: British Defiance or Denial? The accession of the UK into the EC in 1973 was marked by the passing of the European Communities Act 1972 (“ECA 1972”), which saw the reception of EC laws into the UK. Two main provisions of the ECA 1972 are ss 2(1) and (4) which require the Courts to give effect to EU laws even at the expense of domestic Acts of Parliament and for the Courts to interpret Acts of Parliament in a way which avoids conflict with EU laws. This naturally poses the question as to whether the UK Parliament has lost part of its sovereignty. In order to appreciate this question, the views of the UK Courts as reflected in cases both before and after the passing of the ECA 1972 must be observed. Decisions before the passing of the ECA 1972 such as R v Secretary of State for the Home Department ex parte McWhirter [1969] TLR and Blackburn v AG [1971] 2 All ER 1380 reflect the standpoint adopted by the UK Courts that the signing of the treaty carries no legal effect until it is implemented through an Act of Parliament and also that the powers of the Crown rest in the Bill of Rights and remains so even after the treaty is signed. The underlying principle of the two decisions above is that Westminster’s sovereignty can never be removed by any means whatsoever, in this scenario, the EC treaties. The standpoint of the UK Courts after the passing of the ECA 1972, which remains similar to the earlier decisions, could be said to represent a remarkable act of defiance towards ECJ’s standpoint. The jurisprudence of the cases after the passing of the ECA 1972, most importantly, Macarthys v Smith C-129/79; [1981] QB 180 and the series of Factortame The European Union Act 2011: A Renewal of Sovereignty? Directly applicable or directly effective EU law (that is, the rights, powers, liabilities, obligations, restrictions, remedies and procedures referred to in section 2(1) of the European Communities Act 1972) falls to be recognised and available in law in the United Kingdom only by virtue of that Act or where it is required to be recognised and available in law by virtue of any other Act. (Emphasis added). The preceding provision represents a reiteration and codification of the various judgments of the UK Courts as seen earlier in this analysis and has been famously known as the “sovereignty clause”. Two other major provisions that must be highlighted are ss 2 and 5 of the Act, wherein before any treaty is signed with regard to the EU, a referendum shall be held and a statement relating to that treaty is presented in Parliament before the treaty is ratified. It is observed that the general spirit of the Act is to clarify the position that the UK Parliament is still sovereign in relation to the EU and that the current administration aims to whittle down any question of Westminster’s sovereignty. Perhaps, the very fact that the UK administration is able to come up with such an Act demonstrates the essence of Parliamentary sovereignty: the ability to pass laws on its own accord. 7 8 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Commercial Law Commission Agent Theory: Reconciling Wright J in Montgomerie’s case by Shantini Sharon Sukumaran The jurisprudential struggle to define law continues to be evidenced in the difficulties envisaged by various academicians in defining the concept of agency. Thus far, the broadly accepted definition of the law of agency is that of G.H Treitel who stated “Agency is a relationship which arises when one person, called the principal, authorises another, called the agent, to act on his behalf, and that other agrees to do so. Generally, the relationship arises out of an agreement between the principal and agent. Its most important effect, for the purposes of this book, is that it enables the agent to make a contract between his principal and a third party”. Lord Scarman in Yeung Kai Yung V Hong Kong and Shanghai Banking Corporation enunciated the general rule of law for a contractual relationship where a person is liable for his own contracts, even when made on behalf of another. However, the law of agency poses an exception to this rule. As Wright J had stated in Montgomerie v United Kingdom Mutual Steamship Association, “where a person contracts as agent for a principal, the contract is that of the principal, and not that of the agent; and prima facie, at common law the only person who may sue is the principal, and the only person who can be sued is the principal”. Therefore, although on face value the contract is that of an agent, he conveniently “drops out” of the picture and bears no liability. As Professor Reynolds noted, the agent here is a mere intermediary or conduit pipe, thus would defy logic to hold him liable. To this extent, Wright J’s concept of liability in a disclosed principal situation is accurate. However, the possibility envisaged by the law of agency to hold an agent accountable in a disclosed principal situation and the very concept of an undisclosed principal whereby the existence of the principal is unknown on face value, appears to defeat Wright J’s statement above. The accuracy of His Lordship’s statement is in question although it was a design in perfection of the essence of the law of agency. The question remains as to how one would maintain the balance between the concept of privity of contract and the law of agency without making the latter redundant. In a disclosed principal situation, the existence of an agency relationship and the principal is usually identified. As such, a privity of contract exists between the principal and the third party provided the agent acts intra vires and lawful in which case the principal can sue or be sued as noted in Resolute Maritime v Nippon Kaisi Kyokai. As such, the agent becomes a stranger to the contract. To this extent, Wright J’s statement is accurate. However, there are circumstances in disclosed principal situations where the agent is caught liable for the transaction he engineered. Such is the consequence of an agent’s fraudulent action where he subsequently finds himself personally liable in deceit as envisaged in Noel v Poland or even jointly in addition to the principal as that which occurred in Standard Chartered v Pakistan National Shipping. Although the contract is not his, it is right for the agent to remain liable for his fraudulent actions, which have unduly prejudiced the principal’s position. As such, this exception is a fair compromise to Wright J’s illustration in Montgomerie’s case. An agent could also be liable if such was the intention of the parties as that found in Short v Spackman either manifested by the terms of the contract as in Higgins v Senior or by the fact that the agent executed a deed personally as in Pickering’s Case. Where the intentions are not clear the Courts have to examine the surrounding circumstances and context to determine the objective intentions of the parties. In The Swan the Court held that the objective intention between the parties with regards to the agent’s liability (Mr Rodger) was gathered based on the fact that Mr Rodger obtained the benefit of the repairs and although the repairers sent the bill to the company, it was still reasonable to expect Mr Rodger, as the owner of the boat, to be liable unless he made it clear that this was not to be the case, which he failed on the facts. As such, the principal (company) and the agent (Mr Rodger) were held jointly liable. However, in The Santa Carina, the Courts held there was no objective intention between the parties to hold the agent liable simply because the claimants knew the defendant brokers were only agents and not intended to be liable. The third party’s knowledge of the principal’s existence made the contract purely that of the principal in support of Wright J’s statement in question. An agent may also be liable based on the manner of presentation ie, the relevant formalities or processes in the contract, which in construction makes the agent liable. For example, where the agent signs in his name, he may be personally liable as noted in Gadd v Houghton. Where the terms of the contract include phrases such as “on behalf of ” as found in Newborne v Sensolid or “as agents” in Universal Steam Navigation v James Mc Kelrie, the agent will not be personally liable. However in contrast, Brandon J in The Swan opined such terms do not relieve agents of their personal liability, which in essence ensures the agent is accountable for his actions to the principal. In fact, a term may be implied by custom which subsequently holds the agent personally liable as that evidenced in Fleet v Murton. Where the agent acts ultra vires, he could be liable for breach of contractual and fiduciary duty to the principal and breach of warranty of authority towards the third party as noted in Yonge v Toynbee whilst the principal incurs no liability to the third party as evidenced in Comerford v Britanic Assurance Co Ltd. An agent could also be liable under the law of tort where he voluntarily assumes responsibility for the contract entered into as seen in Hedley Byrne v Heller and Partners. An agent also incurs personal liability where he acts on behalf of unincorporated or fictitious company. Kelner v Baxter is authority that in such cases they are not in fact an agent, rather they are promoters of a company which did not have legal entity yet and as such, these actions are also not rectifiable pursuant to s 36C(1) April - June 2012 Companies Act 1985. Hence, these agents remain personally liable. Even if exclusion clauses were to be used, Phonogram Ltd v Lane requires it to be explicit. Previously, the agents of foreign principals were presumed personally liable but following Teheran –Europe Ltd v St Belton (Tractors), such a presumption has been rebutted. As such, despite all the exceptions to the general rule, the circumstances recognised by the law of agency as far as a disclosed principal situation is concerned, does not in any way unduly compromise the concept of privity of contract nor cast any doubt on Wright J’s statement in Montgomerie’s case. However, the undisclosed principal concept makes Wright J’s statement redundant. Here, the existence of a principal is unknown to the third party, thus the contract cannot be one of the principal. Instead, it would be a contract of the agent. Yet this does not relieve the undisclosed principal from liability as the principal can nevertheless sue or be sued where his identity is revealed, and provided the agent acts intra vires as evidenced in Sin Yin Kuan v Eastern Insurance. Further, as Lord Lindley in Keighley Maxtead & Co v Durant had stated, “it is a matter of indifference to either party whether there is an undisclosed principal or not”. Though the existence of a principal is clear in a disclosed principal situation, the principal in an undisclosed principal situation may also be subject to liability where his existence is revealed. However in Watteau v Fenwick – a rather exceptional case – the third party was allowed to enforce the contract against the undisclosed principal upon discovery of existence even though the agent acted ultra vires. Here, rather surprisingly, the Courts treated the contract as one between a principal and agent when in reality it was not. Lloyd LJ justified the decision on the basis that it catered for commercial convenience ie, the need to alert rivals, control price and the fact that identity should not matter. It being an exceptional case was rarely applied as precedent in future cases as this is a decision unique to its own facts and remains good law despite the disapproval in the Canadian case of Sign-O-Lite Plastics Ltd v Metropolitan Life Insurance. Perhaps, if we were to treat this case as an estoppel by conduct, we will reconcile the case with orthodoxy. In a nutshell, as Sir Federick Pollock opined, this situation indicates that the very concept of undisclosed principal makes the concept of privity of contract redundant as those indirectly affected by the contract are given the chance to sue and be sued. Thus far, it appears that the concept of disclosed principal and its exceptions can still reconcile with the concept of privity of contract and Wright J’s statement in Montgomerie’s case but the same cannot be said for an undisclosed principal situation. Perhaps, if the concept of undisclosed principal were to be replaced with commission agent theory ie, where A is an agent to the principal and also the principal to a third party, this would reconcile the law of agency and the concept of privity of contract as Wright J stated in Montgomerie’s case as the contract in such an instant remains that of the principal. Brickfields Law Review References G.H.L Fridman, Law of Agency (6th Edition, Butterworths, 1990). Boustead & Reynolds on Agency (16th Edition, 1996). G.H Treitel, Law of Contract (9th Edition, Sweet & Maxwell, 1995). L Sealey & R Hooley, Text and Materials in Commercial Law, Chapter 5: “Relations with Third Parties”, pp 147-57. Notes 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 Montgomerie v United Kingdom Mutual Steamship Association [1891] 1 QB 370. Yeung Kai Yung v Hong Kong and Shanghai Banking Corpn [1981] AC 787 at 795. ResoluteMaritime Inc v Nippon Kaiji Kyokai (The ‘Skopas’) [1983] 1 WLR 857. Hedley Byrne & Co Ltd v Heller & Partners Ltd [1964] AC 465. Vlassopulos (N & T) Ltd v Ney Shipping Ltd: The Santa Carina [1977] 1 Lloyd’s Rep 478. Universal Steam Navigation Co Ltd v James McKelvie & Co [1923] AC 492. Bridges & Salmon Ltd v The ‘Swan’ (Owner) [1968] 1 Lloyd’s Rep 5. Fleet v Murton [1871] LR 7 QB 126. Kelner v Baxter [1866] LR 2 CP 174. Phonogram Ltd v Lane [1982] QB 938. Yonge v Toynbee [1910]1 KB 215. Keighley, Maxsted & Co v Durant [1901] AC 240. Siu Yin Kwan v Eastern Insurance Co Ltd [1994] 2 AC 199. Teheran-Europe Co Ltd v ST Belton(Tractors) Ltd [1968] 2 QB 545. Yonge v Toynbee [1910]1 KB 215. Teheran-Europe Co Ltd v ST Belton(Tractors) Ltd [1968] 2 QB 545. Noel v Poland and another - [2001] All ER (D) 145. Standard Chartered Bank v Pakistan National Shipping Corp (No 2) [2003] 1 All. ER 173. Short v. Spackman, 2 B. & Ad. 962. Higgins v. Senior, 8 Mees. & W. 834. Re: E. Pickering International Contract Co. UK. Gadd v. Houghton (1876) 1 Ex. D. 357 (C.A.). Newborne v Sensolid (GB) Ltd [1954] 1 QB 45. Comerford v Britannic Assurance Co Ltd (1908) 24 TLR 593. Watteau V Fenwick 1893 Queen’s Bench 346 (QBD 1892). Sign-O-Lite Ltd v Metropolitan Life Insurance Co’ (1991) 70 Canadian Bar Review 329. s.36C(1), Companies Act 1985 (inserted by s 130, Companies Act 1989). 9 10 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Law of Contract Have the Courts Interpreted the Law or gone beyond the Intention of the Parliament in relation to the Quantum of Damages for Section 2(1) of Misrepresentation Act 1967? Royscott v Rogerson [1991] 2 QB 297 Court of Appeal1 by Murali Kandasamy Maidenhead Honda Centre Ltd (“the Dealer”) is a motor-car dealer. In May 1987, the first defendant Mr Andrew Jeffrey Rogerson (“the Customer”) agreed with the Dealer to buy on hirepurchase a second-hand Honda Prelude for the price of £7,600, of which a deposit of £1200 was to be paid, leaving a balance of £6,400. The plaintiff and the respondent to this appeal, Royscot Trust Ltd (“the Finance Company”) is a company which finances hire-purchase sales. The Finance Company has a policy that it will not accept a hire-purchase transaction unless the deposit paid represents at least 20 per cent of the total cash price. The Dealer represented to the Finance Company that the total cash price payable was £8,000 and that a deposit of £1600 had been paid by the Customer. It will be observed that the balance under these figures – £6,400 – is the same as that which was truly payable by the Customer. It is common ground that this was a misrepresentation and that in reliance, the Finance Company entered into a hire-purchase agreement with the Customer. The Finance Company did not claim the Dealer was acting fraudulently. Accordingly the Finance Company relies on misrepresentation under s 2(1) of the Misrepresentation Act 1967. The Finance Company issued proceedings against both the Customer and the Dealer, and on 23rd November 1989 entered judgment in default against both defendants for damages to be assessed. It was that assessment of damages which came before Judge Barr on 22nd February 1990. The Finance Company submitted that its loss was the difference between the sum of £6,400 which it paid to the Dealer and the sum of £2,774.76 paid by the Customer, viz. £3,625.24. Counsel for the Dealer submitted that the Finance Company had suffered no loss since they had acquired title to a motor-car worth at least £6,400. The Judge accepted neither submission. The issue on this appeal which the Dealer submits raises a pure point of law: • Where a motor dealer innocently misrepresents to a finance company the amount of the sale price of, and the deposit paid by the intended purchaser of, the car • The finance company is thereby induced to enter into a hirepurchase agreement with the purchaser which it would not have done if it had known the true facts • The purchaser thereafter dishonestly disposes of the car and defaults on the hire-purchase agreement; can the finance company recover all or part of its losses on the hire-purchase agreement from the motor dealer? The third bullet point will be the highlight of this article. What is the basis of awarding damages under s 2(1) of the Misrepresentation Act 1967. It is worth noting the contents of the provision before we could proceed further. Section 2(1)2 states: Where a person has entered into a contract after a misrepresentation has been made to him by another party thereto and as a result thereof he has suffered loss, then, if the person making the misrepresentation would be liable to damages in respect thereof had the misrepresentation been made fraudulently, that person shall be so liable notwithstanding that the misrepresentation was not made fraudulently... (Emphasis added). Judge Barr held that if the figures on the hire-purchase agreement had shown a deposit of £1200 and a cash price of £6,000, then the Finance Company would have paid £4,800 to the Dealer and would have had no recourse against it since the deposit would have been correctly shown as £1200. The statute seems to suggest that the representor will be liable for damages as though the misrepresentation was made fraudulently even if the misrepresentation was not made fraudulently. Since the Finance Company was induced to pay an extra £1600, it was argued that that is the relevant loss suffered by the Finance Company. The Courts in previous cases had some views ranging from a measure in contract to that of negligence. Let’s see some of the views put forward by these cases. What should be the interpretation that should be adopted here? April - June 2012 In two cases in the Court of Appeal, Gosling v Anderson3 and Jarvis v Swans Tours4 and the decision at first instance in Watts v Spence,5 there was some doubt whether the measure of damages for an innocent misrepresentation giving rise to a cause of action under the 1967 Act was the tortious measure, [so as to put the representee in the position in which he would have been if he had never entered into the contract], or the contractual measure, [so as to put the representee in the position in which he would have been if the misrepresentation had been true], and thus in some cases give rise to a claim for damages for loss of bargain. Watts v Spence was disapproved in Sharneyford Supplies Ltd v Edge.6 It is now clear that the tortious measure of damages should be adopted. These decisions are at first instance and will be found in Chitty on Contract,7 and in McGregor on Damages8and Chesneau v Interhome Ltd.9 Is the measure where the tort is that of fraudulent misrepresentation, or is it the measure where the tort is negligence at common law? The wording of the subsection is clear: “the person making the innocent misrepresentation shall be ‘so liable’ ie, liable to damages as if the representation had been made fraudulently”. This was the conclusion to which Walton J. came in F & B Entertainments Ltd v Leisure Enterprises Ltd 10and McNally v Welltrade International Ltd.11 In each of these cases the Judge held that the basis for the assessment of damages under s 2(1) of the 1967 Act is that established in Doyle v Olby. This is also the effect of the judgment of Eveleigh L.J. in Chesneau v Interhome Ltd: “By ‘so liable’ means liable as he would be if the misrepresentation had been made fraudulently”. Atiyah in an article on the 1967 Act 12 says: The measure of damages in the statutory action will apparently be that in an action of deceit ... But more probably the damages recoverable in the new action are the same as those recoverable in an action of deceit. Treitel13 says: Where the action is brought under section 2(1) of the Misrepresentation Act, one possible view is that the deceit rule will be applied by virtue of the fiction of fraud. But the preferable view is that the severity of the deceit rule can only be justified in cases of actual fraud and that remoteness under section 2(1) should depend, as in actions based on negligence, on the test of foreseeability. It seems that to suggest that if a different measure of damage is applied to an action under the section than that which applies to an action for fraudulent misrepresentation (deceit) at common law, then we will totally ignore the plain words of the subsection and this is inconsistent with the cases to which was referred.14 Brickfields Law Review The only authority cited in support of the “preferable” view15 is Shepheard v Broome,16 a case under s 38 of the Companies Act 1867, which provided that in certain circumstances a company director, although not in fact fraudulent, should be “deemed fraudulent”. As Lord Lindley said:17 To be compelled by Act of Parliament to treat an honest man as if he were fraudulent is at all times painful”, but he went on to say: “but the repugnance which is naturally felt against being compelled to do so will not justify your Lordships in refusing to hold the appellant responsible for acts for which an Act of Parliament clearly declares he is to be held liable. It is, therefore, clear that the quantum of damages to be awarded under s 2(1) of the Misrepresentation Act should be based on tort of deceit. Hence what is the legal outcome of this case? When a claimant sues the defendant for misrepresentation, the quantum of damages recoverable seems to surpass that of breach of contract. After this decision, a representer can be made liable for the following losses: loss profits, expenses incurred, the difference in price between the contract and the actual market value and non-financial losses. This direction has been approved and applied in the case of East of Maurer[1990] EWCA Civ 6, which was decided after Royscott v Rogerson. As a result, the question arises whether the Courts have gone beyond what the Parliament has intended. In this article, we have explored what the Courts have done. It is clear that they have opted to interpret the law and avoided the making of the laws. It can be stated to be correct but producing harsh consequences. Should the Courts, therefore, avoid these consequences? We will explore in the next article what are the criticisms levied against this finding. Notes 1 www.bailii.org extracted on 7 May 2012. 2 Extract from Misrepresentation Act 1967. 3 [1972] E.G.D. 709. 4 [1973] Q.B. 233, 237. 5 [1976] Ch. 165. 6 [1987] Ch. 305, 323. 7 (26th ed.) para. 439. 8 (15th ed.) para. 1745. 9 (1983) 134 N.L.J. 341. 10 (1976) 240 E.G. 455, 461. 11 [1978] I.R.L.R. 497. 12 30 M.L.R. 13 Law of Contract (7th ed.) at p 278. 14 Ibid page 2. 15 Ibid page 3. 16 [1904] A.C. 342. 17 Shepheard v Broome at p 346. 11 12 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Law of Tort Court of Appeal R (on the application of LE (Jamaica)) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2012] EWCA Civ 597, [2012] All ER (D) 92 (May) Before: Maurice Kay, Richards and Kitchin LJJ 9 May 2012 The claimant was born in Jamaica and had been granted indefinite leave to remain in the UK as the husband of a British citizen. The marriage broke down and the claimant was subsequently charged with drug offences. He had breached the conditions of his bail and attempted to flee the country on a false passport. He was diagnosed as a paranoid schizophrenic and a hospital order was made against him. After being discharged from hospital he was convicted of conspiracy to kidnap and conspiracy to blackmail, and was sentenced to imprisonment. The defendant Secretary of State made a deportation order against him. Upon being released from prison, the claimant was detained under sch 3 to the Immigration Act 1971 (the 1971 Act) and removal directions were set. In the meantime, the claimant had lodged an application to the European Court of Human Rights. There had been some difficulties in securing the claimant’s travel documentation, and the Jamaican High Commission had refused to validate the documentation on the grounds that the claimant had had an outstanding human rights application. The claimant was thereafter granted bail and he issued proceedings challenging his detention. The claimant’s case had been that detention was contrary to the Secretary of State’s policy concerning the use of immigration detention (the “policy”) because the reason for detention was simply that removal was thought to be imminent, which had not been an adequate reason under the policy. Further, he claimed that he had fallen within para 38.10 of the policy by reason of his mental illness and there had not been “very exceptional circumstances”, as provided under the policy, to justify his detention. The Judge found that the decision to detain the claimant had been rational, both in terms of the risk of absconding, in addition to the imminent deportation, and on the ground that the claimant’s mental illness had not engaged para 38.10 of the policy. The claimant appealed. The claimant submitted: (i) that the Judge had been wrong to have analysed the matter in terms of the rationality of the decision to detain; that the Court had not been limited to applying the reasonableness test set out in Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation ([1947] 2 All ER 680) (“Wednesbury”), but had been required to act as primary decisionmaker in deciding on the evidence before it, whether detention had been in accordance with the policy; and (ii) no consideration had been given to whether very exceptional circumstances had existed so as to render the claimant as suitable for detention under the policy; the mere existence of a diagnosable mental illness was sufficient to bring a person within the scope of the policy and to require the existence of very exceptional circumstances to have justified detention. Consideration was given to R v Governor of Durham Prison, ex p Singh ([1984] 1 All ER 983). The appeal would be dismissed. 1. If the claimant’s initial detention or continued detention had been in material breach of the policy, it had not been only unlawful in public law terms, but had also constituted the tort of false imprisonment; but he would be entitled only to nominal damages if he could and would have been detained in any event on the lawful application of the policy. The exercise of the power of detention was also subject to the principles set out in R v Governor of Durham Prison, ex p Singh ([1984] 1 All ER 983) (the “Hardial Singh principles”). Subject to the limits imposed by the Hardial Singh principles, the power to detain was discretionary, and the decision whether to detain a person in the particular circumstances of the case had involved a true exercise of discretion. That discretion was vested by the 1971 Act in the Secretary of State, not in the Court. The role of the Court was supervisory, not that of a primary decision-maker. The Court was required to review the decision in accordance with the ordinary principles of public law, including Wednesbury principles, in order to determine whether the decision-maker had acted within the limits of the discretionary power conferred on him by the statute. In submitting that it was for the Court to determine as primary decision-maker whether detention had been in accordance with the policy, the claimant had elided the question whether the decision-maker had directed himself correctly as to the meaning of the policy, and the question whether, if so, the decision-maker had acted within the limits of his discretion when applying the policy to the facts of the case. The first question was a matter of which the Court was the ultimate decision-maker, and the latter was a matter in relation to which a Wednesbury test had applied. In the instant case, however, it had made no difference on the particular facts whether the Court adopted a Wednesbury test or made its own independent assessment of the justification for detention. Had the Judge found it necessary to have decided for himself whether the claimant’s detention was justified in light of the policy, it had been clear that he would have found that it was. The Judge had been right to find that the decision was rational, and also that if it had been necessary to decide, that the detention had been justified. 2. It was difficult to see why special provisions requiring detention to be justified by very exceptional circumstances should have been made for those with a mental illness that could be satisfactorily April - June 2012 Brickfields Law Review managed in detention so that the illness was not significantly affected by detention and did not make detention significantly more burdensome. engaged on the particular facts of the case. The decision taken by the Secretary of State that the policy had not been engaged had been rational. There had been nothing wrong with the Judge’s conclusion. He had followed authority as regards the construction of the policy and had reached a lawful conclusion that the policy had not been The initial detention of the claimant was accordingly lawful. © LexisNexis Case History Annotations Case Name Citations Court Date -- R (on the application of LE (Jamaica)) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2012] EWCA Civ 597, [2012] All ER (D) 92 (May) CA 09/05/2012 Affirming R (on the application of LE (Jamaica)) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2007] EWHC 2980 (Admin), [2007] All ER (D) 209 (Dec) Admin Ct 14/12/2007 Cases considered by this case Annotations: All CasesCourt: ALL COURTS Sort by: Judgment Date (Latest First) Treatment Case Name Citations Court Date Considered R (on the application of OM acting by her litigation friend, the Official Solicitor) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2011] EWCA Civ 909, [2011] All ER (D) 02 (Aug) CA 28/07/2011 Considered [2011] UKSC 23, [2011] 4 All ER 975, R (on the application of [2011] 1 WLR 1299, [2011] 23 LS Gaz R Kambadzi) v Secretary of State for 18, (2011) Times, 10 June, [2011] All ER the Home Department (D) 244 (May) SC 25/05/2011 Considered R (on the application of Lumba) v Secretary of State for the Home Department; R (on the application of Mighty) v same [2011] UKSC 12, [2012] AC 245, [2011] 4 All ER 1, [2011] 2 WLR 671, [2011] 14 LS SC Gaz R 20, (2011) Times, 24 March, 155 Sol Jo (no 12) 30, [2011] All ER (D) 262 (Mar) 23/03/2011 Considered Anam v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2010] EWCA Civ 1140, [2010] NLJR 1492, [2010] All ER (D) 179 (Oct) CA 19/10/2010 Approved R (on the application of Anam) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2009] EWHC 2496 (Admin), [2009] All ER (D) 127 (Oct) Admin Ct 13/10/2009 Considered R (on the application of Hussain) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2007] EWHC 2134 (Admin), 151 Sol Jo LB 1228, [2007] All ER (D) 36 (Sep) Admin Ct 07/09/2007 Considered R v Governor of Durham Prison, ex p Singh [1984] 1 All ER 983, [1984] 1 WLR 704, [1983] Imm AR 198, 128 Sol Jo 349, [1981] LS Gaz R 1764 CO 13/12/1983 13 14 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Law of Trusts Chancery Division Brudenell-Bruce, Earl of Cardigan v Moore and another [2012] EWHC 1024 (Ch), [2012] AU ER (D) 108 (Apr) Before: Newey J 20 April 2012 The claimant was the Earl of Cardigan. He inherited an estate (the “estate”), which had been owned by his family for about a thousand years. The estate included a valuable collection of paintings, which were mainly of the claimant’s ancestors. The instant proceedings concerned the ownership of the paintings. The defendants (the “trustees”) were the trustees of the claimant’s family trusts. In 1951, a partnership agreement was entered into by the claimant’s father and grandfather and the estate was conveyed by deed (the “1951 Conveyance”) to them to be held on trust for sale as part of their partnership property. An agreement entered into in 1963 subsequently provided that the partnership was in future to be carried on by the claimant’s father and trustees for the claimant. In 1987, there was a further generational shift. The partnership share held on trust for the claimant was appointed to him absolutely and his father assigned his share in the partnership to S and B on trusts for the claimant’s children (the “1987 trust”). In 1994, B retired as a trustee of the 1987 trust and the claimant was appointed in his place. Accordingly, the claimant and S became the only trustees of both the 1987 trust and the trusts affecting the estate. A new partnership agreement was entered into reflecting the change of trustee. The claimant and S consented to the grant of a lease dated 16 March 1999 (the “lease”), of Savernake Lodge, one of the houses on the estate, to the claimant for a 20-year term at a peppercorn rent. Under cl 1 of the lease, Savernake Lodge was demised to the claimant together with, inter alia, “the use of all the Landlords’ furniture, fixtures and fittings in or on the premises”. The trustees subsequently wished to sell some of the paintings which formed part of the estate, having taken the view that financial pressures on the estate made it necessary. They relied on a Tomlin Order made in 2008 which had provided, inter alia, for the claimant and one other, F, as the then trustees of the estate, to be replaced by the trustees and following which two deeds, including a deed of retirement and appointment of trustees (the “2008 deed”) had been executed which provided that: it was “intended that the property now in the Trusts” was to be transferred to or under the control of the trustees. One of the recitals of the 2008 deed stated that “the Assets of the Trusts are identified in the Second Schedule”, which included “the pictures” and “paintings”. The claimant brought the instant proceedings seeking a declaration that the trustees had no power to sell the paintings. The trustees counterclaimed, alleging that the lease was invalid under the “self-dealing rule”. Issues arose as to whether: (i) the family’s collection of paintings still belonged to the partnership carried on under the terms of the 1951 partnership agreement (as amended) (the “partnership”); (ii) the lease extended to such of the paintings as were in Savernake Lodge; and (iii) the trustees were entitled to have the lease set aside on the ground of the “self-dealing” rule. The claimant contended that the trustees were not legally entitled to sell the paintings without his consent. The paintings belonged to a partnership of which he was a partner and in any case, many of them had been leased to him in 1999. The claimant further submitted that given the lapse of time, the trustees were precluded by laches or acquiescence from invoking the selfdealing rule. The trustees sought to have the lease set aside on the basis that the “self-dealing rule” applied. They contended that the 2008 deed served to vest the paintings in the trustees. It was common ground that when considering whether a chattel had become a fixture, regard had to be had to: (i) the degree to which the chattel had become annexed to the land; and (ii) the purpose of such annexation. The Court ruled: 1. It was settled law that a statement in a deed was capable of giving rise to an estoppel. If a recital contained a statement, which a party to the deed was to be taken to have agreed to admit as true, the statement was binding on him. The interpretation of a document involved looking at the meaning that it would convey to a reasonable person having all the background knowledge which would reasonably have been available to the parties. In the instant case, one of the recitals of the 2008 deed stated that “the Assets of the Trusts are identified in the Second Schedule”. Further, the claimant was to be taken to have agreed to admit the truth of the recital. It could be inferred that the recital was intended to settle whether the items listed in the second schedule were to be considered to be “Assets of the Trusts”. It followed that the claimant was estopped from arguing otherwise and from contending that the paintings were partnership property. In any case, as a matter of construction, the 2008 deed served to transfer the paintings to the trustees. The paintings were held by the trustees and were no longer partnership property. Greer v Kettle [1937] 4 All ER 396 applied; Mannai Investment Co Ltd v Eagle Star Life Assurance Co Ltd [1997] 3 All ER 352 applied. 2. Artwork displayed on a room’s walls would not normally be regarded as furniture. It was settled law that what was annexed to the land became part of it. However, the question of what constituted an annexation sufficient for that purpose had to depend on the circumstances of each case; in particular the degree of annexation and the object of annexation. It was further settled law that if the purpose of the annexation was for the better enjoyment of the object itself, it might remain a chattel, notwithstanding a high degree of physical annexation. Framed paintings did not usually constitute fixtures. April - June 2012 In all the circumstances, the lease did not extend to any of the paintings. They did not fall within the words “furniture fixtures and fittings”, as those words had been used in the lease. The paintings were housed in Savernake Lodge. They never became part of the building. Further, the paintings did not represent “fittings”. The word “fitted” would not naturally apply to the paintings, which were hung rather than “fitted”. The value of the paintings was of significance. Had the parties intended the lease to extend to such valuable items, they might have been expected to refer to them specifically in the lease. The word “fastenings” was not obviously apt to refer to the paintings but referred more naturally to an attachment than to the thing attached. Accordingly, the chains used to secure the paintings might be fastenings but the paintings themselves would not be. The lease did not extend to the paintings. Berkley v Poulett [1977] 1 EGLR 86 applied. 3. In respect of the “self-dealing rule”, it was settled law that if a trustee sold the trust property to himself, the sale was voidable by any beneficiary ex debito justitiae however fair the transaction. The rule was a severe one which applied however honest the circumstances, even though the price was fair and irrespective of whether any profit was made by the trustee. The self-dealing rule could apply where trustees merely concurred in a transaction. Brickfields Law Review Further, it was settled law that trustees’ acts could be voidable if, in breach of duty, they had failed to take relevant matters into account. The rule extended, moreover, to the grant of leases. In the instant case, the trustees of the 1987 Trust, namely, the claimant and S, had consented to the grant of a lease, not to a limited company, but to one of themselves. In those circumstances, it seemed entirely appropriate that the self-dealing rule should apply. As both the prospective lessee and a trustee of the 1987 Trust, the claimant would have been in a position of real conflict in as regards any decision to consent to the grant of the lease. S, like the claimant, had not given proper consideration to the separate interests of the beneficiaries of the 1987 Trust. Had he done so, he would have been bound to conclude that the lease was not in fact in the interests of the 1987 Trust. If and in so far as consent to the lease had been given on behalf of the 1987 Trust, it was vitiated by failure to take relevant considerations into account as well as under the self-dealing rule. On balance, the trustees were not precluded by laches or acquiescence from invoking the self-dealing rule. In all the circumstances, the trustees were entitled to have the lease set aside. The lease would be set aside. © LexisNexis 15 16 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Land Law A Nightmare for Students? by Nalina Nadarajah The subject of Property Law, for some reason or the other has always been a “student’s nightmare”. Its elusiveness and obscurity has been regarded by some as some sort of a “puzzle” laden with much difficulty, its dry and abstract concepts are supposedly beyond comprehension. This is further enhanced by “linguistic difficulties and arcane language” and makes it somehow detached from the reality of people’s lives. However the author’s intention in this article is to explore the prevailing values and objectives underlying the basic foundations of English property law and to show that the subject is indeed within the grasp of the law student and even more challenging; also the subject provides both a practical and valuable insight to the lay person. English land law has been steeped in history. Through the long process of development, there have been periods of gradual change, and more dramatic times, such as the Norman conquest of 1066 and the property legislation of 1925. Land law has kept its feudal roots and language but the substance of today’s law is fundamentally changed. The law of property is not a thing but rather about people, ie, a power relationship and the study of property law is ultimately about an inquiry into an important range of socially defined relationships and morally conditioned obligations. As A E-S Tay in “Property and Law in the Society of Mass Production, Mass Consumption and Mass Allocation”(1977) 10 ARSP(New Series) 87 at 97-98 once said, “… the concept of property, the way in which it is legally defined and the extent to which it is legally, socially and politically protected raise immediately the most fundamental problems of political philosophy and social life – the relationship between the individual and his social environment, between the citizen and the State and in modern society between the personal and the commercial …” Property law is a network of jural relations between individuals in respect of valued resources and land law as a body of rules which ultimately governs the distribution of utility in the particularly significant resource of realty. This article, therefore, seeks to explore the underlying ideology governing property law and how it interacts with key issues on priority and efficiency. As Karl Renner in The Institutions of Private Law and Their Social Functions (1949) p 107 once said, “[p]ower over matter begets personal power”. Property ultimately articulates political relationship between persons. Land becomes a vital component of all social and economic engineering. Thus, all property references are, at some level, a statement about the social legitimacy attaching to the claim in question – the law of property incorporates a series of critical value judgments, reflecting the cultural norms, the social ethics and the political economy prevalent in any given community. According to Gray and Gray in The Elements of Land Law, the law of land comprises “a crystallized expression of values, obligations and ideologies, all cast in sharp relief against the landscape of the law”. One of the fundamental values inherent in property law is the versatility of land in so far as it governs the expectations and life chances of an entire community. A significant social interest is to enable land to be used as a means of sharing out wealth and of allocating other kinds of benefit or advantage incidental to land eg, the concept of co-ownership of the family home where the owner of a legal estate may wish to share the equitable ownership of the family home with her partner or their children. The commerciability of land is another value inherent in English property law. One of the central truisms of market economics is the idea that the free alienability of property rights in practice makes it less likely that they will fall into disuse. Thus, the key focus of the Land Registration Act 2002 is upon the process and consequence of registered dispositions of estates in land. McFarlane in The Structure of Property Law (2008) demonstrates that the special features of land and the special legal rules to which they give rise are based upon the notion that land is permanent and it has the quality of endurance; the physical location of land cannot be shared by another piece of land and in this sense it is unique; land has the capacity of multiple simultaneous use. The same piece of land can be used in different ways by many different people, at the same time; land is capable of meeting important social needs and this is reflected in a number of special rules and the limited availability of land demonstrates that land is an expensive commodity and it also intensifies the need for land to be freely marketable. To illustrate the potential tension and conflict which arises when balancing the relevant values to be preserved, two cases of crucial relevance in the study of property law become prominent. The difficult questions of both doctrine and policy are demonstrated here. The interesting element in the discussion here involves examining some case laws where the manner in which the various Judges indulge in evaluating competing principles and policies are of utmost relevance and interest to demonstrate the judicial creativity involved. Further, the cases also demonstrate the kind of interests which land lawyers ought to always bear in mind when deciding which way the decision should be decided. Thus the interesting element to note here is that in practice, the importance of land law and its meaning is really about questions of priorities ie, which party should have a better interest and to what extent do the legal rules protect such interests. Further if land law concerns priorities, whose priority can be better justified and does land law demonstrate a proper balance in assessing the interests of the parties. There are many such examples but in the discussion here, two important land law cases will be considered. The relationship between the occupiers of land and the bank is in issue in the cases of: (i) National Provincial Bank v Ainsworth(1965) AC 1175, HL (“Ainsworth”); and (ii) William’s & Glyn’s Bank v Boland(1981) AC 487, HL (“Boland”). April - June 2012 Brickfields Law Review In Ainsworth, Mr and Mrs Ainsworth lived together in Milward Road, Hastings, Sussex. Mr Ainsworth was registered as owner of the home. In 1957, Mr Ainsworth moved out. In 1958, he borrowed £1,000 from the National Provincial Bank. The money was borrowed as part of a mortgage deal: to secure his duty to repay that sum plus interest, Mr Ainsworth gave the bank a particular right (a charge) over his home. This meant that if Mr Ainsworth were to fall behind in his repayments, the bank would have a power to sell the land and use the proceeds to meet his debt. By 1962, Mr Ainsworth had fallen behind on his repayments to the bank. The bank wished to sell the land. To get a good price, the bank knew that it had to sell the home with vacant possession. Because Mrs Ainsworth refused to leave, the bank applied for an order for possession of the home. hand and the need for social protection and the maintenance of a home on the other. The fact that the dispute involves land, a special kind of thing, does not help us resolve this conflict; instead, it heightens the tension. The Court of Appeal found that Mrs Ainsworth had a right to occupy the land that bound the bank. On that basis, the bank’s claim for possession would fail. (Lord Denning). The banks on both these cases may wish to counter-argue against the above proposition stating that a substantial loan has been made and as a result of the limited availability of land and coupled with its social importance, ensures that land has a high value. If the bank is unable to sell the land, it is likely to be left substantially out of pocket. It is thus suggested that the wider consequences of finding in favour of Mrs Ainsworth and Mrs Boland must be investigated. The legal rules of land law should, therefore, be made in favour of the banks or the building societies on this premise. The House of Lords, however, reversed the finding of the Court of Appeal. Mrs Ainsworth had to leave the land. It is submitted here that clearly the House of Lords decision was based on the content question in contrast to the decision of the Court of Appeal. Their Lordships found that Mrs Ainsworth’s right did not count as a property right and so was not capable of binding the bank. In Boland, Mr and Mrs Boland lived together in Ridge Park, Beddington, Surrey. Mr Boland was registered as owner of the home; Mrs Boland also made a substantial financial contribution to the costs of acquiring the home. Mr Boland and his brother were directors of Epsom Contractors Ltd, a building company. To support the business, Mr Boland borrowed money from the Williams & Glyn’s Bank. The money was borrowed as part of a mortgage deal. To secure his duty to repay that sum, plus interest, Mr Boland gave the bank a particular right (a charge) over his home. This meant that if Mr Boland were to fall behind in his repayments, the bank would have a power to sell the land and use the proceeds to meet his debt. Mr Boland had fallen behind on his repayments to the bank. The bank wished to sell the land. To get a good price, the bank knew that it had to sell the home with vacant possession. Because Mrs Boland refused to leave, the bank applied for an order for possession of the home. The Court of Appeal found that Mrs Boland had a right to occupy the land that bound the bank. On that basis, the bank’s claim for possession would fail. (Lord Denning). The House of Lords upheld the finding of the Court of Appeal: the bank’s action for possession, therefore, failed. (Lord Wilberforce). It is submitted here that the crucial questions were the content and defences questions and the House of Lords, in rejecting the bank’s argument, found that Mrs Boland’s right counted as a property right and that the bank had no defence to that right. In both the cases, the Court has a tough choice to make. The special features of land sharpen the Court’s dilemma. In the article by McFarlane, The Structure of Property Law (2008), it is suggested that the dispute between Mrs Ainsworth and Mrs Boland and the banks in both cases could be characterised as a wider clash between commerce and market forces on the one Both Mrs Ainsworth and Mrs Boland may want to point out the social importance and uniqueness of land; if both of them are currently using the land as a home and uprooting that home will cause severe disruption. Further, even if they are able to find a home elsewhere, it may be in a different location and this can give rise to disruptions in many aspects of their lives. Hence, it can be argued from this premise that the legal rules of land law should lean in favour of protecting the position of those currently occupying or otherwise making use of land. First, if banks have systematic problems in recovering loans, this can have repercussions not just for the bank’s customers but for the wider economy. Second, if the bank was unable to sell the land, we need to consider the effect of such a decision on lenders’ future practice of giving loans. Do banks have to carry out extensive and expensive checks to ensure the credibility of its customers and further since land is capable of multiple, simultaneous use, there might be many potential rights that a lender will need to watch out for. The dispute between market forces and social protection thus draws out the ambivalent nature of land itself. On the one hand, it is of limited availability and constitutes an important financial investment: we, therefore, do not want the process of buying land to be unduly difficult. Yet on the other hand, it is unique and socially important: we, therefore, do not want to give insufficient protection to those who use and in particular, occupy land. Harris in “Legal Doctrine and Interests in Land” in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence(1987) provides a valuable insight to the possible approaches/models that may inform a Court’s approach when dealing with cases such as Ainsworth and Boland. Two prominent but contrasting models are identified by Harris: 1. The “utility model of rationality” which is based on what Weber sees as a non-specialist’s expectation of how the dispute should be decided: it essentially consists of weighing up on one side the practical advantages of favouring the occupier and, on the other, the practical advantages of finding for the bank. 2. The “doctrinal model of rationality” is based on what Weber calls “lawyers’ law”: the dispute is resolved by the application of specific legal rules, not by a general weighing of the consequences of finding in favour of the occupier or the bank. 17 18 Brickfields Law Review In the Ainsworth case, Lord Wilberforce considers the nature of Mrs Ainsworth’s right to occupy her home; that right, arising when her husband left her was known as a “deserted wife’s equity”. The Court of Appeal, led by Lord Denning MR, had held that the “deserted wife’s equity” was capable of binding a third party, such as a bank later acquiring a charge over land. The House of Lords, however, rejected that analysis. Lord Wilberforce’s approach to deciding the case reveals two possible suggestions. First, whilst there may be good reasons for allowing Mrs Ainsworth the chance to remain in her home, there may also be good reasons for protecting a lender, such as the National Provincial Bank. That point alone is consistent with the “utility model” – that is, of weighing up the practical advantages and disadvantages of favouring either the occupier or the bank. Second, and much more important, is the need to avoid a “radical departure from sound principles of real property law”. This can be observed in Harris’s view which gives prominence to the “doctrinal model” – that is, a decision in favour of Mrs Ainsworth can be made only if it can be reconciled with the doctrinal, technical rules of land law. And according to Lord Wilberforce, those rules meant that Mrs Ainsworth’s right could not count as a property right ( a right capable of binding the bank) only if it was “definable, identifiable by third parties, capable in its nature of assumption by third parties, and have some degree of permanence or stability”. Because Mrs Ainsworth’s right did not have those features, the content question was decided against her and the bank was, therefore, free to remove her from her home. In the Boland’s case, there was a clear difference between the facts of Ainsworth and those of Boland. Unlike Mrs Ainsworth, Mrs Boland had made a significant financial contribution to the cost of the land owned by her husband. As a result, Mrs Boland’s right differed from the “deserted wife’s equity” of Mrs Ainsworth. Instead, Mrs Boland had a right under a trust of land. Hence, it is first important for us to understand the arguments forwarded by the William & Glyn’s Bank in their defence. First, the bank argued that like the “deserted wife’s equity”, that right failed the content test: it did not count as a property right that could bind a third party, such as the bank later acquiring a right in the land. This argument was based on a land law technicality ie, the doctrine of conversion. According to the bank, it meant that Mrs Boland’s right under the trust did not give her a right enabling her to use the land: it only gave her a right to a share of any money made by her husband from the land. Second, the bank held that even if Mrs Boland did have a property right that was capable of binding the bank, the bank had a defence to that right. The particular defence relied on by the bank was provided by a land registration statute and was based on the fact that when the bank acquired its charge, Mrs Boland’s right was not noted on the entry in the register relating to her home. However, this argument by the bank could easily be displaced on the basis that the lack of registration defence does not apply if the party with the unregistered property right is in “actual occupation” of the land. In these circumstances, the property right held by the party in occupation is known as an “overriding interest” – that April - June 2012 is, a right that is immune from the lack of registration defence. Another technical argument raised by the bank was that where a wife occupies alongside a husband, the wife does not count as a person in actual occupation. This argument is based on the idea that if the bank were to investigate the land before making its loan to the husband, the presence of the wife there would not alert the bank to the risk that she had a property right in the land. Both the bank’s arguments were rejected by the Court of Appeal and the House of Lords. The content and defences question were thus decided in Mrs Boland’s favour: her right under the trust counted as a property right in land and, due to her actual occupation, the lack of registration of that right did not give the bank a defence to it. Lord Denning MR was clearly concerned that as had occurred in Ainsworth over fifteen years earlier, the House of Lords would reverse the decision of the Court of Appeal and favour the bank rather than the occupier. His Lordship’s fear was, however, unjustified. Clearly, the House of Lords reached different results in Ainsworth and Boland. In the former case, the bank’s claim for possession was successful; in the latter, that claim was denied and the occupying wife won out. From a doctrinal point of view, that difference can be simply explained: it depends on the different content of the right held by each occupier. Mrs Ainsworth’s right, a “deserted wife’s equity” was not seen as capable of binding the bank; Mrs Boland’s right, arising under a trust of the land, was capable of doing so. Harris argues, however, that there is also a difference in the underlying approach adopted by the House of Lords in each case. Harris’s analysis emphasises the fact that at a general level, Ainsworth and Boland each raised the same question: should the pre-existing right of an occupier, even if it was not created by the bank nor was necessarily easy for the bank to discover, bind the bank? In Ainsworth, the facts that the occupier’s right was uncertain and hard to discover led the Court, adopting a technical, doctrinal approach, to find that her right could not bind the bank, because it did not count as a property right. In Boland, those same facts did not stand in the occupier’s way. Harris suggests this is because in Boland, the House of Lords: (i) prioritised the need to reach what it regarded as a just result; and (ii) decided that it was just to require banks, before lending money to an owner of land, to check whether any other occupier of that land claimed a right in relation to that land, and if so, to get the consent of that occupier to any right that the owner might give the bank. The purpose of studying the Ainsworth and Boland decisions: 1. Land law is clearly very important in practice. The decisions in each case had significant practical consequences not only for Mrs Ainsworth and Mrs Boland and the respective banks but also for many occupiers and mortgage lenders in these positions. April - June 2012 2. The cases focused on whether the occupier had a private right to use land that she could assert against the bank: the key question was whether the occupier had an interest in land (ie, a property right) that could bind the bank. 3. The decisions in Ainsworth and Boland highlight the importance of the content, acquisition and defences questions. 4. As Harris highlights, the cases such as Ainsworth and Boland also raise broader questions about the approach that a Court should adopt when deciding a dispute about private rights to use land. The discussion between the validity of the utility model and the doctrinal model is not simply based on which model is better. It is not about the utility model being irrelevant or that there is no need to consider the practical merits or wider justice of the doctrinal rules of land law. On the contrary, the social importance of land law means that it is vital not only to understand land law rules but also to evaluate them. Land law changes over time and those changes must be based on a view that the previous legal rules were, in some way, deficient. The developments occurring after Ainsworth is a classic example to illustrate this point. As a result of Ainsworth, Parliament enacted the Matrimonial Homes Act 1967 – the Act established: 1. That a spouse has a qualified statutory right to occupy a home owned by his or her partner; and 2. That the statutory right to occupy, if protected by registration, was capable of binding a third party, such as a bank, later acquiring a right in relation to the matrimonial home. Parliament thus reformed the law by coming up with a specific, tailored solution that it believed formed the best compromise between the need to protect an occupying spouse and the need to protect a third party such as a bank. That compromise, now found in the Family Law Act 1996, ss 30-33 avoids the doctrinal question of whether the right to occupy counts as a property right; instead, the right is allowed to bind a third party, such as a bank, only if it is registered. Actual occupation cannot protect the statutory right to protect: if it is not registered, it cannot bind a third party. And, even if the right is registered, a Court still has the discretion to allow a third party to remove the occupying spouse. The contrast between the approach adopted in Ainsworth and the solution implemented by the Matrimonial Homes Act 1967 reflects a wider tension in land law – that is, between judicial and legislative reform. Therefore, if it is felt that the existing land law rules need to be changed, there is a tension between judicial and legislative reform: can Judges develop the law in the appropriate direction, Brickfields Law Review or should they hold back and wait for Parliamentary intervention? A classic example of such a problem arises in relation to the acquisition of rights under a trust of a family home. Here we have considered this in the case of Boland and according to Lord Denning MR in the Court of Appeal in Boland, the Court’s willingness to recognise such rights stems from a “remarkable series of decisions” confirmed by the House of Lords in 1970 in Gissing v Gissing(1971) AC 886. The topical debate around when a partner can acquire a right under a trust of a family home demonstrates a wider question of whether the best response to a particular problem necessarily consists in changing the land law rules: it may be, as the Law Commission has suggested in the context of disputes over the family home, that we have to look beyond land law for a solution. The Law Commission Report No 278, Sharing Homes: A Discussion Paper (2005) initially attempted to respond directly to the criticism that the land law rules make it too difficult for a partner to acquire a right under a trust of a family home. However, it concluded that it was impossible to come up with a satisfactory legislative scheme setting out precisely when a partner should acquire such a property right. Its focus, therefore, shifted away from a core land law question (when a party can acquire a property right in relation to land) to a different question: if the relationship of cohabiting, but unmarried partners ends, are there circumstances in which one of the parties should be under a duty to provide some financial support to the other partner? The Law Commission in its report, Report No 307, Cohabitation: The Financial Consequences of Relationship Breakdown (2007) concluded that Parliament should enact such a scheme. Hence, one way of analysing the Law Commission’s approach is to say that it has moved from a “land law” solution to a “family law” solution. Its focus is no longer on private rights to use land; rather, it has shifted to the question of whether a partner should be able to receive financial support. There is a wealth of material surrounding the fundamental debate on the appropriate values, which Property Law should enhance but clearly the balance is not an easy one to strike. However, recent developments and reforms in the area of property has shown that both the values have been in one way or the other preserved by virtue of Parliamentary enactments on one hand and case law developments on the other. References: Kevin Gray and Susan Francis Gray, Elements of Land Law (4th ed). Roger Smith, Property Law (6th ed). Judith Ann MacKenzie and Mary Phillips, Textbook on Land Law. Martin Dixon, Modern Land Law (7th ed). 19 20 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Evidence Section 114(1)(d) Criminal Justice Act 2003 – A Discussion on the Discretion of a Judge in Respect of Admitting Hearsay Evidence Pursuant to the Safety Valve Exception by Puvanal Sri The Criminal Justice Act 20031 has brought about some changes, especially in governing the admissibility of the common law rule against hearsay and our focus of discussion is in regards to a special provision known as the “safety valve” provided under s 114(1)(d) which states: In criminal proceedings a statement not made in oral evidence in the proceedings is admissible as evidence of any matter stated if, but only if the court is satisfied that it is in the interests of justice for it to be admissible. This provision as proposed by the Law Commission and provided by the Criminal Justice Act seems to have relaxed the admission of hearsay statements. However, the question that arises here is how much discretion does a Judge have in admitting a hearsay statement under this exception? The hearsay rule was applied at common law excluding such evidence until the Criminal Justice Act 2003 (“CJA”) was introduced to clarify and reform the law on the admissibility of hearsay evidence. The law with regards to criminal trials is governed by Part 11, Chapter 2 of the Criminal Justices Act 2003 (“CJA 2003”) which defines the rule and codifies the exceptions to it. In examining this provision, s 114(2) of the Criminal Justice Act 2003 goes on to provide the list factors or considerations which the Judges will have to take into account in deciding whether or not to admit a hearsay statement under the safety valve. As stated in s 114(2): In deciding whether a statement not made in oral evidence should be admitted under subsection (1)(d), the court must have regard to the following factors (and to any others it considers relevant) — (a) how much probative value the statement has (assuming it to be true) in relation to a matter in issue in the proceedings, or how valuable it is for the understanding of other evidence in the case; The major justification for the exclusion of such evidence is fairly straightforward. Hearsay evidence is not reliable simply because it carries a possibility of fabrication by witness due to the fact that such evidence is not given on oath. There is also uncertainty as to the truth of such statement. (b) what other evidence has been, or can be, given on the matter or evidence mentioned in paragraph (a); (c) how important the matter or evidence mentioned in paragraph (a) is in the context of the case as a whole; On the contrary, many have expressed concerns that this rule may lead to cogent evidence being excluded and hence the denial of a fair and just outcome. Certain evidence bears credible, probative and reliable evidence thus giving a clear picture of what transpired and, therefore, is better than having no evidence at all. The need for reform was demonstrated by Judges. For example in the case of Myers v DPP 3 where Lord Reid stated: (d) the circumstances in which the statement was made; (e) how reliable the maker of the statement appears to be; (f ) how reliable the evidence of the making of the statement appears to be; (g) whether oral evidence of the matter stated can be given and, if not, why it cannot; (h) the amount of difficulty involved in challenging the statement; (i) the extent to which that difficulty would be likely to prejudice the party facing it. The hearsay rule is classically defined as “an assertion not made by a person giving oral evidence and which is tendered as evidence of the matters stated”. The ever popular case which demonstrates the rule in application is the case of Subramaniam v Public Prosecutor2 where the Privy Council said: “A statement is not hearsay and is admissible when it is proposed to establish by the evidence, not the truth of the statement but the fact that it was made”. If we are to extend the law it must be by the development and application of fundamental principles. We cannot introduce arbitrary conditions or limitations; that must be left to legislation: and if we do in effect change the law, we ought in my opinion only to do that in cases where our decision will produce some finality or certainty. If we disregard technicalities in this case and seek to apply principle and common sense, there are a number of parts of the existing law of hearsay susceptible of similar treatment, ... The only satisfactory solution is by legislation following on a wide survey of the whole field ... A policy of make do and mend is not appropriate. Looking at the wording of s 114(2), the Judge must have regard to the nine factors. In construing the wording of this section, reference can be made to the case of Taylor4 whereby the trial Judge admitted hearsay evidence through s 114(1)(d) but could April - June 2012 not reach a conclusive decision in regards to any factors. On appeal, the Court of Appeal was required to decide whether a Judge had to reach a decision in regards each and every one of the factors. Rose LJ in the case of Taylor held that s 114(1)(d) does not impose an obligation on the Judge to reach a conclusion on each factor. The Judge need only give consideration to those factors and access the significance of those factors which he considers relevant. There is nothing in the wording of s 114(2) which requires a Judge to consider all nine factors or reach a conclusive decision in relation to any factors. From Rose LJ’s statement, it is clear that despite the wording of the statute which states that the Judge must have regard to all the factors, the Court of Appeal is ready to overlook the fact that the trial Judge did not in fact consider all factors, especially where the hearsay evidence is admitted in the interest of justice and regards the Judge’s decision as an exercise of discretion. In Taylor, the trial Judge admitted evidence from two prosecution witnesses whom named T as one of the participant in the attack which led to a charge of causing grievous bodily harm with intent. Where the Judge admits evidence after taking into account the above factors, it will be difficult to challenge such a decision. There are a good number of cases where the Judge’s discretion to tender evidence pursuant to this section is justified. The case of Sparks v R5 would have been one such case where the three-year-old girl claimed that “a coloured man” committed the offence. The accused was a Caucasian adult male charged of assaulting that three-year-old girl. The statement was held to be inadmissible as it was caught by the rule against hearsay. If the case was to be decided in light of the CJA coming into force, the statement could be tendered in the interest of justice pursuant to s 114(1)(d) CJA 2003. A recent similar case is the case of R V J(S),6 where the evidence of what a two and a half- year-old girl said to her mother concerning the defendant’s actions was admissible under s 114(1)(d). There is a certain relief today since evidence which is clearly reliable is admitted via this provision. Another situation where it is appropriate to use s 114(1)(d) is demonstrated in the case of Thomas.7 In this case, T was accused of murdering his girlfriend. The issue that arose was the time of death. An eight-year-old girl had told a police officer that she had seen the victim leaving her house after the alleged time of death. By the time of trial, the child had forgotten the whole incident. In this situation, arguably s 114(1)(d) can be used to admit this statement as the chances of fabrication or concoction is hardly there. A case like Cooper 8 also qualifies where C was charged and T who happened to look very similar to C admitted to a friend that he had in fact committed the assault, and not C. T’s confession might have been admitted pursuant to s 114(1)(d) CJA 2003. Maher v DPP 9 is a case decided after the CJA came into force and hence was able to benefit from the safety valve provision. In this case, the accused brought an appeal to the High Court arguing Brickfields Law Review that s 117 of the CJA was wrongly used to tender evidence contained in a log book. The reason the log was to be tendered was because the note written by a bystander who witnessed the incident went missing after the police officer recorded the content of the note into the log book. The High Court held that the evidence falls under the discretion of the Magistrate and hence can be admitted under s 114(1)(d) as it is clearly in the interest of justice, reliable and of substantial value. The Law Commission recommended s 114(1)(d) to circumvent the possibility of injustice occurring due to the exclusion of hearsay evidence where it could not fit into any other exceptions. The purpose of this section as stated by the Law Commission is: To allow for the admission of reliable hearsay which could not otherwise be admitted, particularly to prevent a conviction which that evidence would render unsafe. However, the Law Commission went on to explain that this exception should only be used in very limited circumstances. Although it is clear that the statutory wording does not indicate that s 114(1)(d) was meant to operate as the last resort(safety valve), the natural reading of the section and the purpose stated by the Law Commission seems to suggest that this provision would only apply when the evidence cannot fall into any other recognised category of exceptions. Despite this explanation, the Courts are inclined to actually use this provision as of right, like other exceptions and give it equal treatment, if not more, despite it being intended to be a fallback provision and to be used only where an evidence cannot be tendered under other exceptions to hearsay. The approach of treating the safety valve as a weapon of first resort rather than a weapon of last resort can be dangerous. An illustration of such a case is R v Y.10 In this case, the Court held that a hearsay statement can be adduced under s 114(1) (d) even if it tends to incriminate the accused. The statement is not automatically precluded simply because it incriminates the accused or may amount to an admission of a certain extent of guilt by the person who made it. However, the interest of justice test still has to be satisfied, and attention needs to be given to the factors set out in s 114(2). This case of R v Y cited the case of McLean11 as stating the principle that any type of statement may be admitted under s 114(1)(d). In McLean where a joint enterprise was alleged, it was held that an accused was entitled to adduce a hearsay statement made by his co-accused under s 114(1)(d). Furthermore, in the case of R v Hayter,12 it was held that s 114(1) (d) can be used to admit evidence of an out-of-Court statement by one defendant against the other. This suggests a propensity for the Courts to use s 114(1)(d) of the CJA as a code of admissibility rather than inadmissibility, to treat all sub-sections of s 114(1) as equal, none subordinate to another and, therefore, any statement which is caught against 21 22 Brickfields Law Review the rule against hearsay is admissible under s 114(1)(d), subject only to s 114(2). The effect of this would render other exceptions under s 114 nugatory. The case law of R v Z (“Z”)13 is a very recent case where it laid down the manner in which an evidence ought to be admitted pursuant to s 114(1)(d) CJA 2003. In this case the prosecution seek to admit evidence of a statement made by a witness who was sexually attacked by the defendant as bad character evidence. The Court of Appeal held that the trial Judge had wrongly admitted the hearsay statement where the witness was well and able to testify, though with much reluctance. The trial Judge had failed to take into account the factors under s 114(2), particularly s 114(2)(g) which relates to the witness being unable to testify and if not, why was the witness unable to testify? The Court of Appeal said that s 114(1)(d) was to be applied cautiously, if not the conditions under s 116 CJA 2003 ie, the inadmissibility exception will be circumvented, rendering it nugatory. Only where the evidence cannot be tendered under s 116, can it then be tendered pursuant to s 114(1)(d) CJA 2003. A similar outcome was reached in the case of Finch14 where the Court of Appeal upheld the trial Judge’s decision not to admit the confession made in a police interview by the second defendant which exonerated the first defendant from the offence of possessing prohibited firearm and ammunition. It is not in the interest of justice to admit such an evidence since the second defendant was reluctant to support his statement on oath. This undermines the reliability of the statement and hence should not be brought within the exception as it is contrary to the interest of justice. Also, when there are breaches under other exceptions for excluding, such as the Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984, s 114(1)(d) should not be used to admit such evidence. In the case of Smith15 the Court of Appeal insisted that evidence which does not satisfy the criteria for admissibility under s 74 PACE would also fail to meet the criteria required under s 114(2) CJA 2003. In the case of Marsh16 the Courts stated that Judges should be slow in admitting evidence under this exception, especially where the reliability of a statement depended on the veracity of the person making such a statement which could not be tested and where as in this case itself, the reliability of the statement was obviously open to considerable question. Furthermore, the defence had other evidence available instead of the statement in question, hence the exclusion of the evidence was not fatal to the defence. As explained by Hughes LJ in the case of Marsh, even when the defendant invokes s 114(1)(d), “the interest of justice .... are not synonymous with the interest of the defendant. They mean the public interest in arriving at the right conclusion in the case, including of course the acquittal of anyone about whose guilt there is proper doubt”. Of course there is the fear that if Judges were to use this provision widely, it would circumvent conditions of admissibility under other provisions and may extend it to circumvent confessions which does not comply with s 76 and s 78 PACE 1984. April - June 2012 In each case, s 114(1)(d) needs to be applied in its statutory context. There is no fixed standard as to how much discretion Judges have in opting to admit an evidence under this exception. As observed by Stanley Burton LJ in Z para (d) is unhelpfully drafted. According to his Lordship, it has been referred to as creating a residual power or as a safety valve. When considered in isolation, it might be given a wide or a narrow application. As Dobbs J in Sak v Crown Prosecution Service17 commented, although there is nothing in the section to indicate that Judges must take a narrow approach in applying the safety valve provision, this provision must not be lightly applied and the Courts must exercise its judgment according to s 114(2) CJA 2003. There is no doubt that there are benefits arising from using this provision in the same manner as the other exceptions, but there are equally flaws in doing so. Arguably, therefore, although there are no express wording limiting the application of this exception, the purpose of this section should be taken into account so that this s 114(1)(d) is not applied in a manner that undermines or jeopardises other exceptions as it is clear that this exception is intended to be the last resort in which an evidence can be admitted after consideration of all the other exception and when all others fail. References: Roderick Munday, Evidence, 5th Edition, Core Text Series. Ian Dennis, The Law of Evidence (Fourth Edition, Sweet & Maxwell). Peter Murphy, Murphy on Evidence (Eleventh Edition, Oxford). Law Com. 254, paras 8.133. Notes 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 Part 11, Chapter 2 of the Criminal Justices Act 2003 (CJA 2003). Subramaniam v PP [1956] W.L.R. 965. Myers v DPP [1965] AC 1001. Taylor [2006] 2 Cr App R . Sparks v R [1964] AC . R v J(S) [2009] EWCA Crim 1869. Thomas [ 1994] Crim LR. Cooper [1969] 1 QB. Maher v DPP [2006] EWHC 1271 (Admin). R v Y [2008] 2 All E.R. 484. McLean [2008] 1 Cr App R. R v Hayter [2005] 1 WLR. R v Z [2009] EWCA Crim 20. Finch [2007] 1 WLR. Smith [2007] EWCA Crim 2105. Marsh [2008] EWCA Crim 1816. Sak v Crown Prosecution Service [2008] 172 JP 89. 24 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Jurisprudence John Austin: Is Hart’s Criticism Against Austin’s Command Theory Fair? by Puvanal Sri Austin’s Command Theory John Austin is considered by many to be the creator of the school of analytical jurisprudence, as well as, more specifically, the approach to law known as “legal positivism.” Many critics including H.L.A Hart have hurled criticisms against Austin’s command theory. However, whether Austin’s theory is able to withstand those criticisms will be discussed in this article. As to what the core nature of law is, Austin’s answer is that laws are commands of a Sovereign. “A command is an express wish that something be done and if such a wish is not complied with, there is willingness and ability to impose ‘an evil’”. To Austin, rules are general commands applying generally to a class (“The speed limit on the highway is 120 km/h”) and not specific or individual commands (“Eat chicken pie today” or “Richard must eat chicken pie”). Law to Austin consists of those commands laid down by a Sovereign. The Sovereign is the entity that enjoys habitual obedience from the subjects. Austin further suggests that the underlying reason for obedience is fear of sanction. To Austin, sanction means a “visitation of evil” whereby failure by the subject or citizen to obey the command of the Sovereign would lead to them being punished. The “Sovereign” is defined by Austin as a person or body of persons who receives habitual obedience from the bulk of the population. However as Austin puts it, the “Sovereign” is not in itself in the habit of obeying others, whether it is another institution or person. Austin has given us a simple theory. However, this theory has been subjected to many criticisms, especially by Professor Hart of which some will be examined in this article, including whether Austin’s theory is truly flawed. that of a gunman’s order backed by threats. According to Hart, where a command is given, there need not be the threat of harm in the event of disobedience. According to Hart, to command is characteristically to exercise authority over men, not power to inflict harm, as a command is primarily an appeal not to fear, but to respect authority. Hart is of the view that making law differs from ordering people to do things and that the gunman has only temporary superiority over his victim whereas laws have “standing” or continuing characteristics. A gunman to Hart does not issue “standing orders” to be followed time after time by classes of persons, yet laws pre-eminently have this “standing” or “continuing nature”. Hart states in his work Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy that Law is surely not “the gunman situation writ large” and legal orders are surely not to be identified with compulsion or force. It is submitted that Hart’s statement that a law-maker ( “the Sovereign”) is unlike a gunman is agreed with as both do not share the same position or status. The gunman is a lay person like any other person and as Hart pointed out there is no habitual obedience towards him. However, when he takes out his gun, aims it at someone and states his wish, his command is immediately complied with as there exists fear that he (“the gunman”) would pull the trigger and this obedience is only gained by the gunman as long as he still holds the gun. On the other hand, the status of the Sovereign is different altogether. Every citizen of the country or even that of other countries knows and recognises the Sovereign. Now the Sovereign need not do anything but issue commands unlike the gunman who has to take out his gun before issuing a “command” or “order” as Hart puts it. According to Austin, citizens obey the “command” or “law” as Austin calls it, out of fear that disobedience would result in there being a “visitation of evil”. Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart, better known as H.L.A Hart was an influential legal philosopher of the 20th century. He devoted Chapters 2, 3 and 4 of his most famous work, The Concept of Law to criticising Austin’s theory. Hart contends that Austin failed to realise the difference of being under an obligation and being obliged. In a gunman situation, the “victim” so to speak, has no option or choice but is obliged to the wishes of the gunman; however in society, not every citizen feels that he or she is obliged to the wishes of the Sovereign or person in power but feels that they are under an obligation to do so as they share the same view as the law-maker. Amongst the many criticisms hurled at Austin’s command theory, a well-known criticism from which much discussion can be derived would be Hart equating Austin’s command theory to For example, a law stating that it is an offence for a person to throw rubbish into lakes and if caught doing so would be subject to a fine of $1,000, would receive immense support from nature Criticism of Austin’s theory April - June 2012 lovers as they themselves would not throw rubbish into lakes and would welcome such a law as they feel that they are under an obligation not to pollute the lakes. Another example would be that if a lecturer walked into a classroom and told the students, “You must all hand in your assignments by next week and anyone who fails to do so will not be able to attend classes the following semester.” In the event students handed in their assignment, following Austin’s theory, the reason students handed in their assignments was because of fear that they would not be allowed to attend lectures in the following semester if they did not hand in their assignments. However according to Hart, Austin failed to account for students who would willingly hand in their assignments in order to gauge and improve themselves. Another criticism of Austin’s theory found in The Concept of Law is Austin’s failure to provide in his theory, other species of law which cannot be construed as orders or commands since they perform a different social function known as the power conferring rules which confers powers on private individuals and public officials. It is argued that the significant difference between “commands” in Austin’s theory and the power conferring rules is that in the event of a breach of a command, a sanction will follow. However, where the procedures governing the power conferring rules are not complied with, a situation of nullity arises. Hart states that the extension of the concept of sanction to include nullity would lead to confusion since nullity is a notion totally different from the punishment that follows from the breach of a criminal statute. Nullity according to Hart cannot be assimilated to that of a punishment attached to a rule as an inducement to distance oneself from activities which the rule forbids. For Hart, nullity unlike a sanction cannot be equated to punishment. It can be derived from this view of Hart’s that he sees Austin’s “visitation of evil” as a punishment and this view of Hart’s makes perfect sense as not all non-compliance of law will lead to punishment. For example, in the UK, failure to comply with s 9 of the Wills Act would not be followed closely by punishment for noncompliance but the will would be rendered invalid and would not be upheld by the Courts for want of formalities and so the wishes of the testator would not materialise. For Hart this is not a punishment but rather nullity and as such Austin failed to account for nullity-like punishments. A further criticism forwarded by Hart is that the law-maker so to speak must himself be bound by the law that he makes and Austin’s Sovereign does not comply with this, as according to Austin, the Sovereign is not in the habit of obeying anyone. This seems to suggest that Austin’s monarch is free of limitations and can do whatever His or Her Majesty wishes and issue commands freely. This, according to Hart, is yet another flaw in Austin’s theory. Brickfields Law Review Hence at this point, it is submitted that prima facie Hart’s criticisms of Austin do make sense and do give us something to think about. However, both sides of the coin should be looked at and hence it is only fair that defences in support of Austin’s theory should be considered. Defence of Austin’s Theory When Austin came up with his lectures, he lived in a society ruled by a monarch and thus based his theory on what was observed. Now, Hart equates Austin’s command theory to that of orders backed by threats but was that what Austin intended it to be? It is argued that the Sovereign cannot possibly be equated to a gunman. Hart came up with this imaginary gunman and his orders backed by threat theory, equated it to that of Austin’s Sovereign and the command theory and concluded that it could not work as a legal theory as he detected many flaws in it, some of which were pointed put above. However, interestingly as Hart puts it, Austin’s command theory should not and indeed, is not the gunman’s orders backed by threat. The two are like the North pole and South pole. First, the gunman does not in any way share the same status as the Sovereign. The Sovereign is the figure of a state, which is recognised by the citizens of the state and even those from other states. On the contrary, the gunman is not recognised by anyone. The Sovereign has the duty to govern its subjects or citizens and regulate society through proper administration through its “agents” which can be argued to be Judges, ministers etc. Hence, the commands issued by the Sovereign would be to regulate society and thus would carry the force of a law and is not a forced order as issued by the gunman. Only when the command issued by the Sovereign is breached would there be a visitation of evil or punishment. However, with regard to the gunman situation, the gunman could pull the trigger even if the order is complied with as seen in many live examples, where gunmen have pulled their triggers even though they had got what they wanted. Thus, it is submitted that Professor Hart had rebranded Austin’s theory as an order backed by threat theory and it is in the author’s view that this rebranding is not an accurate branding of Austin’s theory. Next with regard to nullity, Hart states that nullity is not a form of sanction. However, it is submitted that nullity can be considered a sanction or punishment. It is simply because if one does not get what one wants, is that not a form of punishment? For example, if two people are entering into a contract in the UK and the formalities stated in the Contracts Act 1950 is not complied with, the contract would be null and void and both parties cannot be held to the contract. Likewise, if the formalities and regulations found in the Companies Act is not complied with when setting up a company, the company cannot be registered and would not be recognised. Similarly, a marriage would be null 25 26 Brickfields Law Review and void if the formality governing the legality of a marriage is not complied with. It is the author’s view that nullity caused by non-compliance of rules and regulations laid down by the lawmaker can be taken to be a form of punishment or sanction. Next, with regard to the commands issued by the Sovereign, as suggested, the Sovereign is not free of limitations when issuing a command. In fact, only legal limitation does not bind the Sovereign. If the Sovereign issues commands that are highly improper or immoral for example, “to kill all red haired babies”, the Sovereign would be subjected to condemnation by the subjects and there would be protests and rebellion against this command. This inevitably would cause the Sovereign to lose habitual obedience by its citizens in time. This being the case, it is submitted that Professor Hart has probably failed to take a closer look at Austin’s theory before hurling his criticism at it. It is submitted that Austin’s theory makes sense even today. For instance, if Jack ( a fictitious character) was driving at 3 am and reaches a traffic light that shows red and there are no cars to be seen in the vicinity, he would not stop but continue driving. Most people in this country would. However, if there was a police patrol car behind him or if there is a camera attached to the traffic light to capture the number plates of cars that do not stop at the traffic light when it turns red, Jack would most probably stop at the traffic light. The reason for this is simple: Jack fears the punishment that would follow if he fails to stop when the light turns red, which in his case may be a fine. Hence, Austin was right in saying that citizens obey the law out of fear of sanctions as even today, citizens obey the law out of fear of sanctions. A further example would be a Ruler who ignores the limitations of statutory law, constitutional law, and international treaty commitments, while the public and other officials lack the will or the means to hold that Ruler to the legal norms that are aimed to constrain his or her actions. Conclusion It is in the author’s view that though Hart has put forward some very interesting criticisms against Austin, Hart has failed to understand the foundation and era which influenced Austin’s April - June 2012 writings. In other words, Hart failed to see through Austin’s eyes. If he did, arguably, he would understand that Austin’s theory applied perfectly well in his time. In further support of Austin, Austin could not have possibly foreseen a society governed by Parliament or any other body divested with power other than the monarch. The question that arises here is: was Austin’s theory really flawed as Hart claimed or does it work well within a community that is governed by a monarch? Perhaps the answer is just a simple one which is: both Austin and Hart were right in their own way as their respective theories represent the era in which they wrote. Hart failed to appreciate the historical context in which Austin wrote. Hart may be absolutely right, that “visitation of evil” is not the only reason why there is habitual obedience by citizens but at the same time Austin was not wrong. “Visitation of evil” may be the reason why some of us still obey the body in power. Thus it is submitted that Austin’s theory is like the Great Wall of China, which had served an extremely important purpose during its time but today, though no longer used for the purpose that it was built, still stands as one of the wonders of the world. Likewise, Austin’s theory has helped us in our understanding of jurisprudence during the times of monarch and he ought to be credited for that. Austin’s distinct command theory of law has been subjected to widespread criticism, but its simplicity gives it an evocative power that continues to attract adherents, the author included. Reference: H.L.A Hart, Concept of Law (2nd edition, Clarendon Law Series). H.L.A Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983). Wayne Morrison, Elements of Jurisprudence (International Law Book Services, 1994). J Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (Cambridge University Press, 9 Mar 1995). April - June 2012 Brickfields Law Review WHAT’S IN STORE? • LAW BOOKS • REFERENCE MATERIALS • MERCHANDISE OPERATING HOURS Monday - Friday 10.00am - 6.00pm Saturday 10.00am - 2.00pm OUR ADDRESS BRICKFIELDS ASIA COLLEGE 68-2, Jalan Tun Sambanthan 50470 Brickfields, Kuala Lumpur, Malaysia T: +603 2274 4165 F: +603 2274 4174 27 28 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Company Law Queen’s Bench Division, Commercial Court Enercon GmbH and another company v Enercon (India) Ltd [2012] EWHC 689 (Comm), [2012] All ER (D) 47 (Apr) Before: Justice Eder 23 March 2012 The litigation arose between the claimant German companies and the defendant Indian company (EIL) regarding a wind energy joint venture. The parties had been engaged in litigation for some years in India. The instant proceedings concerned claims by the claimants under an alleged written agreement between the first claimant and EIL, concerning intellectual property (the “IPLA”). The IPLA contained, inter alia, an arbitration clause (cl 18). EIL contended that the IPLA was not legally binding and that in the alternative, although cl 18.3 stipulated that the “venue of the arbitration proceedings” would be London, “venue” was not synonymous with “seat” and on the true construction of the IPLA, the “seat” of any arbitration would be London, not India (the seat issue). The claimants sought a declaration under s 32 of the Arbitration Act 1996 that the seat of the arbitration was England, and an anti-suit injunction restraining certain proceedings on behalf of EIL in the Bombay High Court (the “BHC”). EIL filed its own claim in the Indian Daman District Court (“DDC”) seeking, inter alia, a declaration that the IPLA was not a concluded contract and that EIL was not, therefore, bound by the arbitration agreement. In April 2008, the Indian Court granted EIL an anti-suit/anti-anti-suit injunction on an interim basis. In January 2009, the DDC refused an application by the claimant for EIL’s claims to be referred to arbitration and for the Indian anti-suit injunction to be lifted. In August 2009, the DDC allowed the claimants’ appeal against that order. EIL subsequently filed what it described as “appeals” in the Indian Court. Those proceedings on their face appeared to be writ petitions to the BHC for, inter alia, the quashing of the order of August 2009 (the “order of August 2009”). In November 2011, the claimants issued proceedings in an Arbitration Claim Form (the “ACF”). In February 2012, the claimant successfully made an application without notice to the Court for a freezing injunction against EIL (the “freezing injunction”). Although the claimants had previously issued proceedings in the English Court, they had not chosen to pursue them. Four applications were before the Court: (i) EIL’s application to challenge the jurisdiction of the Court regarding the claimant in the ACF; (ii) the first claimant’s application for the appointment of an arbitrator; (iii) EIL’s application to set aside or vary the anti-suit injunctions; and (iv) EIL’s application to set aside or vary the freezing injunction and the first claimant’s application to continue the same. The Court gave further consideration to the question of whether the sea issue should be left to the Indian Courts and whether EIL had been correct to rely on the stay of the order pending the hearing of the writ petitions. The Court ruled: 1. It would be appropriate to stay the proceedings pending resolution of the writ petitions currently before the BHC. Any such order would include the requirements that: (i) EIL undertook all necessary steps to expedite those proceedings; and (ii) the stay was for a limited period only. The proceedings would be stayed pending resolution of the writ petitions. Abidin Daver, The [1984] 1 All ER 470 applied. 2. On the evidence, the fact that there was a stay of the order pending the hearing of the writ petitions was enough to enude that judgment of any finality and conclusiveness it might otherwise have. EIL was correct to rely on the alleged stay because, on balance: (i) it had been right about the existence of such a stay; and (ii) there was sufficient doubt so as to preclude any possible reliance on res judicata or issue estoppel. There was no relevant res judicata or issue estoppel. 3. On the true construction of, inter alia, the wording of cl 18.3, the appropriate venue for the hearing of the claim would be London. London would be the “seat” of any arbitration under cl 18.3. 4. In the circumstances, a number of factors justified the discontinuation of the freezing injunction. The freezing injunction would not be continued. © LexisNexis April - June 2012 Brickfields Law Review Conflict of Laws Queen’s Bench Division, Commercial Court West Tankers INC v Allianz SpA (formerly known as Riunione Adriatica Sicurta) and another [2012] EWHC 854 (Comm) [2012] All ER (D) 166 (Apr) Before: Flaux J 4 April 2012 The underlying dispute arose out of a collision in August 2000 between the appellant’s vessel “Front Comor” and a pier in Sicily belonging to Erg Petroli SpA (“Erg”), who had chartered the vessel from the appellant. The charter contained a London arbitration clause with English law to apply. Erg made claims against the appellant for its losses arising out of the collision, and obtained security in the form of a letter of undertaking from the appellant’s P&I insurer. The dispute was referred by Erg to arbitration. The appellant denied liability and counterclaimed for a declaration of non-liability. Erg was insured by the respondents pursuant to contracts of insurance which were governed by Italian law. The respondents paid Erg up to the policy limits and then brought judicial proceedings in Sicily against the appellants, seeking to recover the amount paid. The claim was brought by way of subrogation under Italian law. The appellant sought an anti-suit injunction from the English Courts to restrain the respondents, which was granted and made permanent in March 2005. The respondents were ordered to refer any and all disputes to London arbitration in accordance with the terms of the charterparty, and it was declared that the Italian proceedings were disputes arising out of the charterparty and, therefore, fell within the arbitration clause. A “leap frog” appeal to the House of Lords followed, which referred questions to the European Court of Justice (“ECJ”) concerning jurisdiction. While the matter was pending before the ECJ, the appellant continued with the arbitration in London. The tribunal made declarations similar to those of the Commercial Court. Thereafter, the claim by Erg against the appellant came on for hearing. The respondents took no part in the hearing. While the tribunal was considering the terms of its award, the opinion of the advocate general was delivered. She concluded that the Council Regulation (EC) 44/2001 (the “Regulation”) precluded the Courts of a member state from making an order restraining a person from commencing or continuing proceedings before the Courts of another member state because, in the opinion of the Court, such proceedings were in breach of an arbitration agreement. In light of that opinion, the tribunal stood over certain issues that arose only between the appellant and respondents (referred to as issues 8 and 9) until the ECJ’s judgment. It published a further partial final award by which it held that the appellant was under no liability whatsoever (in contract, tort or otherwise) to Erg in respect of the collision. In the alternative, any liability would be limited under the Convention on Limitation of Liability for Maritime Claims 1976. The ECJ then found to the same effect as the advocate general: the anti-suit injunction was incompatible with the regulation. The House of Lords, therefore, discharged the anti-suit injunction, but preserved the declarations of the Commercial Court that the respondents were obliged to refer any and all charterparty disputes to arbitration. The Commercial Court and subsequently the Court of Appeal declined to set aside the order granting leave to enforce the award under s 66 of the Arbitration Act 1996. The instant case concerned the question of whether arbitration fell outside the regulation and, therefore, an arbitral tribunal was not bound to give effect to the principle of effective judicial protection. The Court ruled: 1. Arbitration fell outside the Regulation and, therefore, an arbitral tribunal was not bound to give effect to the principle of effective judicial protection. It followed that the tribunal had been wrong to conclude that it did not have jurisdiction to make an award of damages for breach of the obligation to arbitrate or for an indemnity. 2. If, contrary to that conclusion, the tribunal had been obliged to give effect to the principle of effectiveness or effective judicial protection, the question still arose as to whether an award of damages or an indemnity constituted illegitimate interference with the proceedings in the Italian Court. Neither the advocate general nor the ECJ contemplated that the arbitral tribunal in London should decline jurisdiction altogether until the Italian Court had ruled. In the event that the Italian Court decided in due course that it did not have jurisdiction and the respondents were obliged to arbitrate in London, then there would be a strong case for awarding damages for breach of the duty to arbitrate. David Bailey QC, Marcus Mander and Elizabeth Lindsay (instructed by Ince & Co LLP) for the appellant. Stephen Males QC and Sara Masters (instructed by MFB Solicitors) for the respondents. © LexisNexis 29 30 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Succession Outer House, Court of Session Turner v Turner and others [2012] CSOH 41, 2012 Scot (D) 6/4 Before: Lord Tyre 7 March 2012 This case, which came before the Court for summary trial by agreement of the parties, raised an important question which had not previously been the subject of decision by a Scottish Court. Where an attorney, acting prudently in accordance with the terms of a continuing power of attorney, disposed of an item of property from the granter’s estate after the granter had become incapable of managing his or her own affairs, was a bequest in the granter’s will of that property thereby adeemed? The late Miss Isabella Coutts Gordon (“the testatrix”) was born in 1915. She was formerly the proprietrix and occupier of a house at 33 Dunnottar Avenue, Stonehaven. On 17 April 1996, she granted a power of attorney in favour of a solicitor, AB, conferring on the attorney “power to do all things which can lawfully be done by an attorney” and, in particular, the powers detailed in a schedule to the deed which included power to sell any part of her means and estate, heritable or moveable. The power of attorney included a declaration that “all acts done or granted by my Attorney in virtue of the powers hereby conferred shall be as valid and binding as if done or granted by myself ”. The deed concluded: “And I hereby ratify and confirm all that my Attorney shall do or cause to be done in virtue of the powers hereby conferred”. On 2 July 1997, the testatrix executed a will, appointing the pursuer and the first defender as her trustees and executors. In her will she directed her executors to make over the heritable property at 33 Dunnottar Avenue to the first defender, and to realise and make over the residue of the estate equally among the pursuer and the first to eighth defenders. In 2001, the testatrix became incapable of managing her own affairs and moved into a nursing home. In September 2001 the attorney sold the house at 33 Dunnottar Avenue for £71, 250. As regards the sale, the parties were agreed as follows: “The sale of the house by [AB] was a prudent act of administration, having regard to the disadvantage in leaving the house empty with attendant maintenance costs. It was not a necessary act, not having been an act which [the testatrix] as principal, had she been sui juris, would have been constrained to effect, there being sufficient other funds available to meet the costs of [her] care”. The testatrix died in January 2008. The pursuer and the first defender were confirmed as her executors on 27 March 2008. The total estate for confirmation was £220,217. As at 5 April 2011, the value of the estate was £173,455. The law regarding power of attorney (or, to use the traditional Scots term, factory and commission) was the subject of a significant amendment by s 71 of the Law Reform (Miscellaneous Provisions) (Scotland) Act 1990. Before that amendment the authority of an attorney or factor acting under a power of attorney–or factory and commission–terminated in the event of the mental incapacity of the granter. With effect from 1 January 1991, that rule of law ceased to apply. The current law was contained in s 15 of the Adults with Incapacity (Scotland) Act 2000. The provisions of s 15 did not apply to the power of attorney in the instant case, which was granted in 1997, but by virtue of para 4 of Sch 4 to the 2000 Act, the attorney became a continuing attorney on the entry into force of the Act. Counsel for the pursuer, one of the residuary beneficiaries, contended that the legacy of the house was adeemed. The short answer to the special legatee’s claim was that the sole question was whether the subject of the legacy was in the testatrix’s estate at death? If not, the legacy was adeemed. The long answer depended upon the development of the law of both ademption and conversion. Conversion was dependent upon the presumed intention of the testatrix. In the instant case the attorney’s act was equivalent to the testatrix’s act. Because the disposal of the house was authorised (and prospectively ratified) by the testatrix, it effected conversion of the heritable property consisting of the house to moveable property consisting of the proceeds of sale. Intention was not, however, relevant to ademption. Where, as here, property had been converted by an appropriately authorised transaction, it was simply gone from the estate and the legacy of it was accordingly adeemed. Counsel for the first defender submitted that a transaction carried out by an attorney should be regarded as analogous to a transaction carried out, under pre-2000 law, by a curator bonis. A sale by a curator bonis effected neither conversion of the property nor ademption of a legacy thereof, unless it could be shown that it would have been a necessary and unavoidable act on the part of the ward if sui juris. By agreement, that was not the position here. The legacy was not, therefore, adeemed and the first defender was entitled to the proceeds of sale as a surrogatum for the house. The Court ruled: Most attorneys were now appointed (as was the attorney in the instant case) by a deed conferring upon them a general power to do everything that the granter could do for himself or herself, supplemented by a list of specific powers granted without prejudice to the generality. The attorney was thus, in essence, a factor or general and special agent appointed and authorised by the granter to manage his affairs and, in the course of so doing, to bind him in legal relationships with third parties. There was April - June 2012 no legal fiction which treated the attorney as the same person in law as the granter, or which treated the attorney’s acts as those of the granter. Rather, the attorney’s acts were as valid and binding on the granter as if they had been carried out by him, and the attorney was accountable, as was any factor, agent or mandatory, to the granter for his intromissions. The fact that the power of attorney in the instant case included a clause that prospectively ratified and confirmed the acts of the attorney did not make any difference to that analysis. It was also worth emphasising that the granter was not divested of any power to act for himself during the subsistence of the power of attorney. The nature of the office of curator bonis (which was rendered obsolete by s 80 of and sch 4 to the 2000 Act) was considered by the Court in Inland Revenue v McMillan’s Curator Bonis. Lord President Clyde observed: “The essential purpose of the appointment of a curator bonis to an incapax is to supersede the latter in the management of his estates . . . In my view, the curator bonis is in the same category for the present purpose as an agent or factor appointed by a capax to manage his affairs and ingather his estate. In the case of an incapax the Court necessarily has to make the appointment, because the ward is incapable of doing so.” Those remarks provided an authoritative statement of general application, that so far as management of the estate of the ward/granter (as the case might be) was concerned, a curator bonis was in a position similar to that of an attorney appointed by a granter with full capacity, the only difference being that in the case of a curator bonis, the appointment necessarily had to be made by the Court. Each was authorised to act on behalf of a person who, for differing reasons, was or might be unable to manage his own affairs. The parallel was even closer between, on the one hand, a curator bonis appointed by the Court and, on the other, an attorney acting under a continuing power of attorney granted by a person who had subsequently become incapable. The Court was satisfied that in addressing the issue which arose for decision in the instant case, it could and should seek guidance from case law concerning the effect of the actings of a curator bonis on succession or on ademption of legacies. Macfarlane’s Trs v Macfarlane (“Mactarlane’s Trs”) provided clear and binding authority for the proposition that a sale by a curator bonis of the subject of a specific legacy did not have ademptive effect unless the sale would have been a necessary and unavoidable act on the Brickfields Law Review part of the ward if sui juris. If, therefore, the Court was correct in the view that in deciding the instant case it should seek guidance from case law concerning the effect of the actings of a curator bonis on ademption of legacies, Macfarlane’s Trs provided the requisite authoritative guidance. On an analysis of the authorities, the argument on behalf of the first defender, in his capacity as the beneficiary of the specific bequest of 33 Dunnottar Avenue was to be preferred. In view of the parties’ agreement that the sale of the house by the attorney was a prudent act of administration but not a necessary act in the relevant sense, the bequest of the house was not adeemed by the sale. The pursuer’s “short answer” failed to recognise the exception to the general rule for disposals by a curator bonis that was established in relation to ademption by Macfarlane’s Trs. So far as the long answer is concerned, first, Scots law had not at any time adopted authorisation by an appropriate authority as the relevant test either in relation to conversion of heritable to moveable property (or vice versa) or in relation to ademption of special legacies. Instead, Scots law developed the test of necessity in relation to conversion and subsequently adopted it in relation also to ademption. Second, there was no sound basis for deeming the acts of an attorney to be the acts of the granter of the power, as opposed to treating such acts as valid and binding upon the granter. Finally, even if it had accepted that a sale by an attorney operated conversion because it was authorised, the Court would not have felt able to accept the next step in the argument, namely that a legacy of heritage was extinguished by ademption because it had been converted to moveable property on conclusion of missives for sale. Pollok’s Trs v Anderson could not have been decided as it was if the argument were correct. The first defender was entitled to receive a sum equivalent to the proceeds of sale of the house. He was also entitled to receive a sum representing the fruits of those proceeds during the period since the date of receipt of the sale proceeds. The sum payable to him by way of such fruits should approximate as closely as possible to the amount that had actually been earned by deposit or investment of the proceeds since 2001, after deduction of any tax paid thereon. © LexisNexis 31 32 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Family Law Family: The after-shock by Anna Heenan The decision in Radmacher v Granatino resulted in an increase in pre-nuptial agreements. However, that was not the end of the story. Case law shows that each case is fact-specific and tailored legal advice is required. We are now almost two years on from the case of Radmacher v Granatino [2010] UKSC 42, [2011] 1 All ER 373 (“Radmacher”), in which the Supreme Court swept away the old rule that prenuptial agreements were contrary to public policy. The result has been an increase in pre-nuptial agreements by those attempting to combat the uncertainties of divorce. Courts have a wide discretion to redistribute property on divorce, which they exercise according to the principles set out in s 25 of the Matrimonial Causes Act 1973 (MCA 1973) and the concept of “fairness”. It is, however, widely accepted that the elasticity of “fairness” does little to create certainty. Recent case law on prenuptial agreements explores the circumstances in which they will be upheld and provides some guidance to those seeking a more certain outcome. The Radmacher Decision This decision has been the subject of widespread comment and further analysis is perhaps unhelpful (and somewhat late). It is, however, useful to review the factors that the Supreme Court thought would affect the weight given to a pre-nuptial agreement: 1. There must not be undue influence, duress, fraud or misrepresentation; 2. Exploitation of a dominant position to secure an unfair advantage may reduce or eliminate the weight given to an agreement; 3. The parties must have been told about the implications of the agreement; 4. The Court should consider any lack of disclosure and legal advice. It would be unusual in the absence of these factors for a party to be taken to have entered into the agreement with a full appreciation of its implications. However, if a party was fully aware of the agreement’s effects and unconcerned by the detail of the other party’s assets, then this should not detract from the agreement’s weight; and 5. Unfair terms reduce the weight of the agreement but this issue is considered in the context of whether the agreement is unfair in the circumstances of the marriage breakdown. In particular, an agreement cannot prejudice the reasonable requirements of children or the needs of a party (although a party’s needs may be interpreted restrictively than they would be by a Court). An agreement may also be given more weight where it seeks to protect pre-marital property than where it deprives one party of a share in wealth that s/he has contributed to equally. Recent cases have made clear that the needs of the parties remain the critical factor in determining whether prenuptial agreements should be upheld. However, the requirements for legal advice and financial disclosure have been interpreted quite differently depending on the individual circumstances. Cases in which Weight was Given to the Agreements ZvZ In Z v Z [2011] EWHC 2878 (Fam), [2011] All ER (D) 112 (Dec), the parties were French and both were highly intelligent and well-educated. The husband was a senior manager in a private equity firm and the parties’ assets totalled approximately £15m. They entered into a marriage contract in France, which both parties entered into freely and with a full understanding of its implications. There was no formal legal advice or financial disclosure but the wife understood what the agreement meant. Both parties knew the financial position of the other. The wife might not have known the full details of the husband’s income but she knew he was doing well and earning increasing amounts. The wife argued that the husband had varied the pre-nuptial agreement. In particular, she relied on an unsigned letter, written after they had decided upon a trial separation (at that time the wife wanted the marriage to continue and the husband was unsure). The letter made very generous provision for the wife. This letter was not given any weight as neither party had received legal advice and the husband was under significant pressure. The original agreement was upheld but the wife received around 40 per cent of the total assets to meet her needs. VvV In V v V [2011] EWHC 3230 (Fam), [2012] All ER (D) 18 (Jan), the husband was an Italian banker with pre-earned and inherited wealth. The wife was Swedish and had not worked since she was 19. The total assets at the time of divorce were around £1.28m. The parties had entered into a pre-nuptial agreement under Swedish law at the husband’s insistence, on which neither party took legal advice. The agreement excluded the husband’s pre-marital property, and any property inherited by either party, from the division of property on divorce. Charles J held there was no duress, fraud or misrepresentation and felt the agreement was a “good and powerful” reason for departing from an equal division of assets on divorce: 1. While the parties did not receive legal advice there was nothing unfair or difficult to understand; April - June 2012 2. The wife was indifferent to the value of the husband’s property so there was no material non-disclosure; 3. There was no finding that the wife felt under undue pressure to sign or that she was acting against her better judgment; and 4. The inequality in bargaining power did not reduce the weight to be given to the agreement. However, if the husband’s pre-owned assets were excluded and the remaining assets divided equally, the wife’s financial needs would not be met. Therefore, the wife was awarded a greater share than the agreement provided for. Cases in which Agreements were Given Little or No Weight In Kremen v Agrest (No 11) [2012] EWHC 45 (Fam), [2012] All ER (D) 146 (Jan), the husband was found to have assets of £20-£30m. The parties had entered into a pre-nuptial agreement which gave the wife only $1.5m. Although the wife had some idea of the husband’s wealth, there was no financial disclosure when the agreement was entered into. The wife received some legal advice from the husband’s cousin but it was not independent. It was held that the wife would have understood the literal words of the agreement, but not what rights she would be losing under English law as a result. Brickfields Law Review in Europe and that neither the husband nor the wife were from Catalonia. This agreement was given no weight whatsoever. The parties had not discussed whether the agreement was intended to be influential, let alone binding, if the parties were to divorce in England and they had received no legal advice on the point. Therefore, neither party entered into the agreement “with a full appreciation of its implications” as required by Radmacher. GS v L In GS v L [2011] EWHC 1759 (Fam), [2012] All ER (D) 178 (Mar), the parties were Spanish. The husband was a banker and the wife a homemaker who was highly educated. After they married they signed a document providing that all future assets would be held under a matrimonial property regime known as Sociedad de Gananciales. Although the agreement was signed after the parties married, post-marital agreements are treated in the same way as pre-nuptial agreements so the guidance is relevant. It was held that the primary purpose of the agreement had been to give the wife financial security if the husband died. The parties did not have a common intention about what the agreement was intended to achieve: the wife sought financial security, whereas the husband wanted to protect his pre-owned assets. Spanish legal experts could not give a clear explanation of what the agreement meant under Spanish law so the parties could not have understood this either. In any event, all of the assets (bar the husband’s pension), which totaled £4m, were needed to meet the parties’ needs and they were divided equally. The agreement was given no weight whatsoever, for various reasons. In particular, the wife did not freely enter into the agreement with a full appreciation of its implications, it was the product of pressure from the husband and there was a material absence of independent legal advice and disclosure. It would be grossly unfair to hold the wife to an agreement depriving her of her fair share of a fortune which she had contributed equally to. Finally, the award she would have received under the agreement did not remotely meet her reasonable needs and it grossly prejudiced the needs of the children. Conclusion Mostyn J remarked that it would be unusual to consider that a party had freely entered into a pre-nuptial agreement with full appreciation of its effects if there had been no legal advice or full disclosure. Independent legal advice and financial disclosure are highly advisable. While the cases show some flexibility, they indicate that cases where these safeguards are not present should be the exception rather than the rule. BvS Above all, these cases make clear that Radmacher was not the end of the story as far as pre-nuptial agreements are concerned. Details remain to be refined. Pre-nuptial agreements are a very useful tool in the wealth protection armory but each case is factspecific and tailored legal advice is essential. In B v S [2012] EWHC 265 (Fam), [2012] All ER (D) 189 (Mar), the parties entered into a Catalonian agreement providing that the default rules of Catalonia would apply to their property. It is notable that the default rules in Catalonia are almost unique The cases are fact-specific and there is clearly a contrast between the extremes of Kremen v Agrest, on the one hand, and V v V and Z v Z on the other. Fairness, especially the needs of the parties and the children, appears to be critical. Z v Z demonstrates that needs may be interpreted generously, despite the guidance in Radmacher. This will be particularly relevant where the wealth has been acquired during the marriage and is not pre-owned by one of the parties. © LexisNexis 33 34 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 EU Law Through the Back Door? by Trevor Tayleur The European Court of Justice has traditionally refused to extend horizontal direct effect to Directives. However, its judgments in Mangold & Kücükdeveci have enabled the horizontal enforcement of Directive 2007/78 on the grounds that national Courts should disapply national legislation which infringes the general principle of equality. This has led to legal uncertainty as the circumstances in which national Courts should disapply national legislation for infringing general principles of EU law are far from clear. It is a basic tenet of EU law that Directives are not capable of horizontal direct effect. The European Court of Justice (“ECJ”) has decisively rejected extending horizontal direct effect to Directives (Faccini Dori v Recreb Srl: C-91/92 [1995] All ER (EC) 1). However, subsequent judgments of the Court have clouded the issue (Mangold v Helm: C-144/04 [2006] All ER (EC) 383 (“Mangold”), and Kücükdeveci v Swedex GmbH & Co KG: C-555/07 [2010] All ER (EC) 867) (“Kücükdeveci”). Mangold Mangold, aged 56, was employed on a fixed-term employment contract. He subsequently brought proceedings in the German Courts against his private sector employer, challenging the fixedterm nature of his contract. He argued that the contract breached Directive 2000/78 (the “Directive”), which prohibits various types of discrimination, including age. The discrimination occurred because a German law introduced in 2002 only permitted fixed term contracts for employees younger than 52 in exceptional circumstances; this restriction did not apply to employees aged 52 and over. Although the Directive had been adopted in 2000, its due date for transposition by member states was not until 2003, and member states were even allowed to delay transposition until December 2006. Directives are only capable of having direct effect after expiry of their transposition date (Pubblico Ministero v Ratti: 148/78 [1979] ECR 1629) and Mangold had entered into his contract in July 2003. Accordingly, on a traditional analysis Mangold would not have been able to rely on the Directive. The Court did not adopt this analysis. Instead, holding that the national Court was under a duty to set aside any provision of national law which conflicted with the Directive even if the time limit for transposition had not expired. The Court gave two main reasons for this: 1. Member states were, during the transposition period, under a duty to refrain from taking measures which would seriously compromise the attainment of the Directive’s objectives. This reasoning is uncontroversial, as it does not extend existing case law (Inter-Environnement Wallonie ASBL v Région Wallonne: C-129/96 [1998] All ER (EC) 155). 2. Controversially, the Court also invoked general principles of EU law in its reasoning. The Court stated that the Directive did not itself lay down the principle of equal treatment in the field of employment. The source of the actual principle underlying the prohibition of the forms of discrimination covered by the Directive (discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief, disability, age or sexual orientation) was found “in various international instruments and in the constitutional traditions common to the member states”. The principle of non-discrimination on the grounds of age was, therefore, a general principle of EU law, and observance of this principle, in particular in relation to age, could not be conditional on the expiry of the Directive’s transposition period. As the German government was unable to justify objectively the discrimination against older workers, Mangold was effectively able to rely on an unimplemented Directive horizontally against his employer. This represented a major extension of existing case law, as it enabled the horizontal enforcement of a Directive prior to its transposition date. The Inter-Environnement ruling had merely resulted in the annulling of the offending national legislation. There was uncertainty as to whether the Court’s judgment was confined to age discrimination or whether it had established a new principle for enforcing rights granted by EU law. However, Kücükdeveci made it clear that the Court was establishing a new principle. Kücükdeveci Kücükdeveci had been employed by a German company since the age of 18. After 10 years’ employment, she was given notice of termination. The employer gave her the period of notice applicable to an employee who had been employed for three years, as German law provided that periods of employment under the age of 25 should be disregarded when calculating the length of employment. Following a reference by a German Court, the ECJ firstly ruled that the national legislation was unlawful, as “EU law, more particularly the principle of non-discrimination on grounds of age as given expression by the Directive” precluded national legislation of this nature. The Court secondly considered the question whether in proceedings between private individuals, national Courts had to disapply legislation that infringed the principle of non-discrimination. The Court confirmed that Directives could not have horizontal direct effect. It then restated the principle of indirect effect, viz a national Court must interpret national law, as far as possible, in the light of the wording and the purpose of any relevant April - June 2012 Directive, in order to achieve the Directive’s aims (Marleasing SA v La Comercial Internacional de Alimentacion SA: C-106/89 [1990] ECR I-4135). The Court then noted that because of its clarity and precision, the national legislation could not be interpreted in conformity with the Directive. Under the traditional approach, the national Court would then have applied national legislation even though it infringed EU law, leaving the unfortunate claimant without a remedy against her employer but with a potential claim for state liability against the German government. The ECJ, however, did not go down this route, instead holding that the principle of non-discrimination on grounds of age was a general principle of EU law to which the Directive merely gave expression. The national Court was, therefore, under a duty to disapply any provision of national legislation breaching this principle. The Response of National Courts There was speculation that some national Courts, in particular the German Federal Constitutional Court (“FCC”), might rebel at this extension in the reach of EU law. The FCC has accepted the supremacy of EU law, but has stressed that this is contingent on the EU acting within the scope of the competences conferred on it by the member states. The FCC has reserved the right to review EU law where the EU has acted outside the scope of its competences. Should this occur, the FCC will declare the EU act ultra vires and inapplicable in Germany. In Re Honeywell [2011] 1 CMLR 1067, the FCC considered whether the judgment in Mangold was ultra vires. However, the FCC stated ultra vires review of European acts was limited to “evident” or “obvious” cases of an infringement of competences and applied only in cases in which an obvious lack of competence led to a grave shift of the power structure between the EU and the member states. As age discrimination fell within the scope of EU law, the ECJ had not created any new competences nor had it extended an existing competence so as effectively to create a new competence. The English Courts have also shown their willingness to abide by Mangold and Kücükdeveci. X v Mid Sussex Citizens Advice Bureau [2011] EWCA Civ 28 involved a disability discrimination claim based in part on the Directive. On the facts, the Court of Appeal decided it did not need to consider the horizontal effect of the Directive against a private party. However, Elias LJ stated obiter that there was a strong argument that Kücükdeveci would have permitted its direct enforcement. He also doubted the argument put forward that although protection from age discrimination might be a fundamental EU right; protection from disability discrimination was not. Had a reference to the Court of Justice been necessary, he would also have asked whether the principle in Kücükdeveci applied to other forms of discrimination. If the ECJ had answered in the affirmative, which it almost certainly would have done, the Court of Appeal would surely have loyally applied the ruling. Brickfields Law Review An Unnecessary Development In Kücükdeveci the ECJ reiterated that Directives are not capable of horizontal direct effect, but then granted them horizontal direct effect by the back door under the guise of enforcing general principles of EU law. It is possible to discern some logic in its reasoning, as in neither Mangold nor Kücükdeveci did the ECJ actually rule that national Courts should apply the Directive directly against the employers concerned. The duty imposed on national Courts was merely to disapply conflicting provisions of national law. The practical effect, though, is virtually identical. Both Mangold and Kücükdeveci succeeded in horizontal claims against private employers. While it is desirable that victims of discrimination should have effective remedies, the judgments in these two cases are an unnecessary development. In both cases the employers had acted in accordance with clear provisions of German employment law. By imposing liability on them, the ECJ has penalised the employers for the German government’s mistake. In the absence of indirect effect, Mangold and Kücükdeveci would have been able to pursue damages claims against the German government for incorrect transposition of the Directive. The German government could possibly have defended their claims by arguing it had not committed a sufficiently serious breach of EU law (joined cases Brasserie du Pêcheur v Germany: C-46 & 48/93 [1996] All ER (EC) 301). However, to prevent this occurring, the ECJ could have ruled that in cases involving discrimination, the liability of member states should be strict. At least the perpetrator of the error, the government concerned, would then have to pick up the bill, rather than innocent employers. Legal Uncertainty These judgments have also created legal uncertainty. Where Directives give effect to general principles of EU law, according to Mangold and Kücükdeveci, national Courts must dis-apply national legislation which conflict with those principles. Although it is clear that Directives combating discrimination give effect to the general principle of equality, it is far from clear in other fields whether Directives give effect to general principles. Where a claimant is pursuing a horizontal claim based on indirect effect and there is a clear conflict between the national legislation and any relevant Directive, prior to these two cases the ECJ accepted that the national Court would apply the national legislation, rather than adopting a contra legem interpretation to make it comply with EU law (Miret v Fondo de Garantia Salarial: C-334/92 [1995] 2 CMLR 49). However, where a Directive gives effect to general principles, this is no longer the case; the national Court must disapply the offending national law. Unfortunately, apart from Directives combating discrimination, there is little guidance about which Directives give effect to general principles. Mangold and Kücükdeveci will undoubtedly result in more litigation. © LexisNexis 35 36 Brickfields Law Review April - June 2012 Law & Literature War Criminals in Kangaroo Courts by Sabah Carrim Post-war literature has the distinct characteristic of retelling stories and real life incidents from the perspective of the oppressed. It is through these narratives that we become the bystanders in torture rooms and gas chambers and get an inkling of what war victims experienced within the confines of those walls. 2. Should we distinguish between evil doers and their evil deeds? Eventually, however, the memory of the psychological injury endured by these victims wins a distance from the actual events. This is when post-war literature takes a new turn as writers begin relating similar stories, but this time from the perspective of the oppressors – that is the perpetrators themselves. The novel The Reader is such a story told by a former Judge of a German Court who embarked on a project to recount the life of an imaginary SS security guard working for the Third Reich. An account is given of the trial where she is successfully convicted in a Court set up by the victors of the war. Hanna Schmitz, the war criminal, is charged with bloodying her hands with the murder of a few thousand Jews during the performance of her duties. On close scrutiny, this story – although fictitious – appears to be an adaptation of Hannah Arendt’s own account of what transpired during the trial of Adolf Eichmann in 1961.1 The latter who occupied the position of Lieutenant Colonel with the SS, was also charged with the duty of implementing pogroms to evacuate Jews from the country and exterminate those who had stayed behind. 4. What is the value of “show trials” set up to try War Criminals? But there is more to this: during wartime, torture is employed as a tool of subjugation, control and manipulation in order to divide, disorient and weaken the enemy. It is then too easy in its aftermath for the victors to set up Courts in order to decry the evil nature of the oppressors, hunt them down and then mete out punishment to do justice to the sufferers. Thus fifteen years after the Second World War, a man who had been charged with the task of facilitating and managing the mass deportation of Jews to ghettos and extermination camps, was condemned in the tribunal of Jerusalem for being a War Criminal. He was Adolf Eichmann. In a similar trial depicted by Schlink in The Reader, Hanna Schmitz is tried for the murder of hundreds of Jews in Auschwitz. Schmitz was also charged for her inaction in coming to the rescue of Jewish women who were trapped in a church that was on fire. Most of them perished in the flames save for two ladies who bore testimony against her in that trial. Although both trials – that is of Eichmann and Schmitz – culminate into successful convictions, readers exposed to the intricacies of the setting and the psychological makeup of the accused parties quickly detect other factors that call for more analysis. At first glance, both these works – that is The Reader and Eichmann in Jerusalem – put forward the same questions to us: 1. Should oppressors always be the objects of our scorn and the oppressed the recipients of our sympathy? 3. Do Eichmann and Schmitz deserve a differently formulated judgment? These questions will be tackled in turn in the course of this essay. Should Oppressors be the Objects of Our Scorn and the Oppressed the Recipients of Our Sympathy? Much to the surprise of those who have intimate knowledge of Eichmann and Schmitz’s personality traits, the latter do not carry the sinister air and display the conduct expected of oppressors who have committed such despicable and vile actions.2 On the contrary, both are depicted as ordinary everyday simpletons. Schlink describes Schmitz as follows: She had no sense of context, of the rules of the game, of the formulae by which her statements and those of the others were totted up into guilt and innocence, conviction and acquittal.3 We are told that Hanna Schmitz faced a dilemma when she was offered a job with Siemens which she later turned down to take up guard duties with the SS. This is because she – Hanna Schmitz – could not read and write and she was not very proud about this. At many points in the story, she does everything to conceal this truth from Michael Berg – the narrator and the young lad she has an amorous affair with. It is he who realises that her involvement with the SS only came about because she had refused the promotion at Siemens fearing that this handicap would be discovered at some point or the other.4 Eichmann is depicted in similar terms as a “fairly boring and unimaginative white-collar bureaucrat who, in his understandable desire to advance his career, helped to perpetrate one of the most atrocious evils of human history”.5 Originally, Eichmann’s employment with the Vacuum Oil Company was relatively smooth-going until he was transferred to Salzburg in 1932 where he said he “lost all joy in (his) work … no longer liked to sell, to make calls”.6 When he was thus offered a position by Kaltenbrunner who later became chief of the Head Office for Reich Security, he simply replied “Why not?” and that is how he came to be connected with the organisation. Arendt goes on to explain how this was a boost in status for a man who was a failure to his social class and was desperate to do just about anything to get the respect he deserved. Even if he was April - June 2012 forewarned, she goes on to say that Germany would lose the war and a terrible fate would await him in the Courts of Jerusalem, he would not be deterred in any way to give up that miserable life of his as a traveling salesman for the Vacuum Oil Company.7 Schmitz and Eichmann, therefore, share a common history in that they were both average individuals who had no particular achievements to acclaim them. In addition, their future had nothing promising and job security was definitely an issue. Having been offered respectable positions in the SS, they were understandably eager to take up the challenge. The common histories of the two characters are in harmony with their semblance of innocence and innocuousness in Court. It is clear that their involvement with the SS was purely a result of their circumstances. In wanting to secure their new positions, and being the slaves of an organisation that had hire/fire power, it is contended that the thought that dominated their minds was the standard approval – the “Doggy Pat” – that every member of an intricate bureaucratic organisation expects from his superior. Thus every “Doggy Pat” would have the value of securing their positions even further within the powerful framework that exerted obvious control over the territory they lived in at that time. It is averred that the effectiveness of this “Doggy Pat” is only possible in average individuals who do not have a clear-cut notion of either a conventional or an individualistic sense of right and wrong. It appears that they are more prone to relegating higher order values to the lower ones of sociability, conformity and obedience.8 In addition to this, the process of routinisation also adds an element of banality in the real crimes being committed. Through the mechanism of division of labour in a typical bureaucratic setting, it becomes easier for the bureaucrat to distance himself from the actual plan being furthered and his job loses its meaning in the greater scheme of things. As Berger says, “Bureaucrats value only their competence, efficiency, and problem-solving abilities.”9 Was it therefore fair to convict Schmitz and Eichmann when their roles could be likened to mere puppets? Indeed, their actions followed the nod or approval of their superiors but this distinction appears unnecessary and futile: in truth, the operations of the organisation should be looked upon as an orchestra where deciding whether the violinist is the one who controls the symphony because he plays his instrument before the guitarist, is pointless. The whole set-up is cleverly woven, according to Arendt, to diffuse responsibility for the actions and decisions taken that may be detrimental for the people. Arendt deems this bureaucratic setting to be a government by nobody10 – in her opinion the worst form of tyranny. A tyrannical dictator, at least, she reasons, can still be identified as the mastermind behind cruel and destructive policies but in the type of setting that Eichmann and Schmitz were caught up in, it seems to be difficult to place the blame on one particular player or a few of them for that matter.11 In the end, the evil bureaucrat is just a “cog in the machine” and hurling the onus of the blame solely on his shoulders appears unwarranted. Brickfields Law Review Should We Distinguish between Evil Doers and Their Evil Deeds? How should we react when instead of witnessing signs of the Eichmann and Schmitz’s sure-footedness in Court, we observe surprise, confusion – even despair – on being accused of their crimes? Eichmann, Arendt says, was certified “normal” by half a dozen psychiatrists. One of them had even “found his whole psychological outlook, his attitude toward his wife and children, mother and father, brothers, sisters and friends … not only normal but most desirable”.12 Although evidence to the contrary was meted out by other experts, Arendt brings to light the many other instances that support Eichmann’s general harmlessness. She reveals how the various classes of stakeholders – the prosecutor, the defense counsel and the Judges – in the trial were also not interested in revealing the softer parts of his character. Arendt opines that in the process they “missed the greatest moral and even legal challenge of the whole case”.13 As for Hanna Schmitz, her interventions during the trial where in at least two instances, on being hurled accusations for the crimes she was charged with, she turns to the Judge and asks: “What would you have done?”14 The narrator of the story, Michael Berg, then continues by adding: “Hanna meant it as a serious question. She did not know what she should or could have done differently, and, therefore, wanted to hear from the Judge, who seemed to know everything, what he would have done.”15 This scenario betrays a tone of helplessness on Hanna’s part where the situation she was in, did not appear as clear-cut as it would have appeared to the people present in Court during the trial. Hanna seemed to be equally under a form of duress of obeying the official orders of her superiors. If the evil doers are not always connected to their evil deeds, then where does evil originate from? Arendt says: Good can be radical; evil can never be radical, it can only be extreme, for it possesses neither depth nor any demonic dimension yet—and this is its horror!—it can spread like a fungus over the surface of the earth and lay waste the entire world. Evil comes from a failure to think. It defies thought for as soon as thought tries to engage itself with evil and examine the premises and principles from which it originates, it is frustrated because it finds nothing there. This is the banality of evil.16 Since time immemorial, a linear relationship has been said to exist between evil doers and their evil deeds. But in a complex system of bureaus, where decisions are made in a piecemeal fashion, it would be unjust to hurl the blame on the shoulders of just a few persons within the structure. The commission of one evil deed – or say one evil decision – can easily be imagined to exert a ripple effect eventually roping in multiple players in the commission of a succession of evil deeds thereafter. The real extent of damage is not foreseeable and this is why the cause-effect relationship established by scientists and technicians has been frowned upon 37 38 Brickfields Law Review by thinkers and philosophers alike. Thus if evil doers are not always linked to their evil deeds, then this calls for an analysis for other variables that have intruded in this seemingly simple relationship. Hannah Arendt attributes Eichmann’s actions to an “absence of thinking” which in her opinion, happens not just to stupid people but also to intelligent ones: Absence of thought is not stupidity; it can be found in highly intelligent people, and a wicked heart is not its cause; it is probably the other way round, that wickedness may be caused by absence of thought.17 So what happens when there is an “absence of thought” on the part of the evil doer in such situations? Under the sway of a complex bureaucratic system as the one painted above, where there is “rule by Nobody”, any innocent party can have his hands tied up with the verdict of guilty in the commission of monstrous crimes of great dimensions. All that is needed under the present system of bureaus is an officer with bleak prospects of rising in social status, sufficiently desperate for a regular income and generally bored and unhappy with his status quo, who on being offered a respectable position, would pounce on every opportunity to be favoured by his superior. He would then put in the effort required to further the organisation’s political objectives just to win the approval of – or get a “Doggy Pat” from – his superior. There is often a disconnection between the evil doer and the evil deed in a bureaucratic system where decisions are made from behind an office desk. Eichmann it is said, did not have to hear the “screams of pain” and thus “(t)he evil consequences of his actions were belated and distant”.18 Do Eichmann and Schmitz Deserve a Differently Formulated Judgment? Arendt argues that Eichmann’s conviction was correct. She is, however, critical of the grounds on which the verdict was reached. Instead she concocts an imaginary judgment where in her view, the Judges should have said: “We are concerned here only with what you did, and not with what the possible noncriminal nature of your inner life and of your motives.”19 Arendt goes on to add that: April - June 2012 authority of prerogative powers – it is important to point out the obvious erosion of the inviolable principle on retrospective law. According to the international community, as much as freedom from torture is a jus cogens principle and should not be violated under any circumstances, the principle against the application of retrospective legislation carries similar status. Thus, trying “war criminals” for actions that were deemed legitimate under the former regime that suffered defeat, is in itself a blatant violation of international legal principles. Tribunals faced with such reprisals take solace in the fact that choosing to condemn war criminals rather than letting them go scot-free is tantamount to choosing the lesser of two evils; the bigger evil being letting the criminals go unpunished and the lesser one being flouting the principle against retrospective law. Perhaps the arguments for condoning the punishment of war criminals need to be reformulated without touching on jus cogens principles or international law: the justification for punishment of war criminals like Schmitz and Eichmann can be derived through a closer analysis of the genealogy of punishment. Punishment, according to Aristotle, is not meant to be a form of correction or disciplining of the evil doer—because in Grecian tradition this was deemed impossible to achieve—but rather to do justice to the plight of sufferers and victims of the wrong. Letting Schmitz and Eichmann go scot-free would simply not be the solution required because this is the closest the sufferers can get to having their anger assuaged through the suffering of their apparent perpetrators. Arendt says that “the wrongdoer is brought to justice because his act has disturbed and gravely endangered the community as a whole, and not because, as in civil suits damage has been done to individuals who are entitled to reparation”.21 What is the Value of “Show Trials” Set Up to Try War Criminals? Politics is not like the nursery; in politics obedience and support are the same and just as you supported and carried out a policy of not wanting to share the earth with the Jewish people and the people of a number of other nations- as though you and your superiors had any right to determine who should and should not inhabit the world- we find that no one, that is no member of the human race can be expected to share the earth with you. This is the reason, and the only reason, you must hang.20 There are many instances in history of War Crimes Tribunals being set up to convict War Criminals. The question that arises, now that it is clear that where there is rule by Nobody, convicting “small fishes” like Eichmann or Schmitz will not do. Accusing “big fishes” like George W Bush, Donald Rumsfeld and Richard Cheney, among others, as was done in a recent trial in Kuala Lumpur22 would also be an affront to the system in place where in all justice, we should not just be criminalizing human actors, but also vague and inanimate objects such as systems, concepts and weaponry for the torture and extermination of war victims. But putting aside such unrealistic aspirations, the practice of criminalizing small fishes – in Eichmann’s trial, the Nuremberg trials or even in the famous Russell Tribunals23 – has moved on to walloping the big fishes and this is definitely more laudable. Considering the fact that Eichmann and Schmitz could both have had their conduct during the Third Reich justified on the premise that they were “Acts of State” – a legal term to connote that the orders and actions were carried out under the unquestionable At the same time, needless to say that these kangaroo Courts have been derogatively labeled as “show trials” – a term which when employed by Arendt to describe what she saw of Eichmann in Jerusalem was fiercely opposed and criticised by Jewish April - June 2012 authorities. The main argument against these Courts is that the impartiality of those running such forums is often questionable and somehow or the other, there is always a creature prowling backstage with vested interests in the show. Ben-Gurion’s interest in staging the show trial of Eichmann24 is not different from Malaysian former Prime Minister Mahathir Mohamad’s recent attempt to stage a similar one in Kuala Lumpur. Putting aside their political motives, which is beyond the scope of this essay, their official reasons appeared to say in the least, noble and honourable. Ben-Gurion made his intentions clear at the time of Eichmann’s trial: it was to “educate the young” and the entire world and to give the Jewish people a voice in making a historic accounting with its persecutors”.25 Mahathir Mohamad laid out his intentions too and said that it was to teach the world the truth about the US government and its evil policies.26 Needless to say, although these show trials may achieve these aforementioned objectives effectively, they cast a negative outlook over the very meaning of an impartial tribunal where sacred principles such as Nemo judex in causa sua (No man can be a Judge in his own cause), “Audi alteram partem” (the rule against bias), and nullum crimen, nulla poena sine praevia lege (law against application of retrospective legislation) are wilfully laid aside. In the order of the aforementioned breaches of natural law principles, issues have arisen about the background of the Judges trying the cases; criticism has been directed towards the setup of Courts whose verdicts are already known beforehand and of course, the imposition of laws that were not necessarily in force at the time of the commission of the (criminal) acts.27 Controversy also surrounds the fact that these trials were conducted in absentia of the accused parties. However, in many ways the latest version of the kangaroo Court that was set up in Kuala Lumpur constituted a step made in advance of previous ones set up to try war criminals. Two areas of improvement can be discerned: first of all damages were ordered to the war crime victims for the harm and injury, pain and suffering they had undergone – even though this tribunal was merely a tribunal of conscience with no real power of enforcement. Second, this tribunal targeted the “big fishes” for a change – although again, it can be averred that the “big fishes”, as bureaucrats giving out orders from behind their desks, are just a few players in the system. In addition to the above, hope has been expressed that despite the “toothlessness” of the Kuala Lumpur tribunal, the final judgment should exert a similar influence on the international community. How? Well, some time ago, the International Criminal Court which tried the President of Sudan in absentia ordered his arrest and this led many member states to decry his actions. The result is that today he cannot visit many countries for fear of arrest. The Kuala Lumpur War Crimes Tribunal Committee has expressed similar wishes for the fate of the War Criminals who were tried and successfully convicted. Brickfields Law Review Notes 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A report on the Banality of Evil (Penguin Books: New York, 2006). “Her initial reaction, expressed in letters to Jaspers, McCarthy, an Blucher, was impressionistic. He isn’t even sinister, she wrote …” (Eichmann in Jerusalem, “Introduction”, p xii). Bernhard Schlink, The Reader (Vintage International: New York, 1997), p 109. The Reader, p114. Renee Jeffrey, Adam Morton, “Beyond Banality? Ethical Responses to Evil in Post-September 11”, Adam Morton, International Relations on Evil; Peter Singer, The President of Good and Evil: Questioning the Ethics of George Bush; Michael Ignatieff, The Lesser Evil: Political Ethics in an Age of Terror The Gifford Lectures, International Affairs (Royal Institute of International Affairs 1944-), Vol 81, No 1 (Jan., 2005), pp 175-186 at p 177. Eichmann in Jerusalem, p 31. Ibid, pp 33-35. Birgit Maier-Katkin and Daniel Maier-Katkin, “At the Heart of Darkness: Crimes against Humanity and the Banality of Evil”, (Aug 2004) Vol 26, No 3 Human Rights Quarterly pp 584-604 at p 600. Ronald Berger, “The ‘Banality of Evil’ Reframed: the social construction of the ‘Final Solution’ to the ‘Jewish Problem’”, (Nov 1993) Vol 34, No 4 The Sociological Quarterly pp 597-618 at p 609. Hannah Arendt, “On Violence”, Crises of the Republic (Harcourt Brace and Company: New York, 1972). Ibid, pp 137-138 where Arendt says: “If, in accord with traditional political thought, we identify tyranny as government that is not held to give account of itself, rule by Nobody is clearly the most tyrannical of all, since there is no one left who could even be asked to answer for what is being done. It is this state of affairs, making it impossible to localize responsibility and to identify the enemy, that is among the most potent causes of the current world-wide rebellious unrest, its chaotic nature, and its dangerous tendency to get out of control and to run amuck.” Eichmann in Jerusalem, p 26. Ibid. The Reader, p 127. Ibid, p 110. Eichmann in Jerusalem, “Introduction”, p xi. Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind: The Groundbreaking Investigation on How We Think (Harcourt inc: USA, 1978), p 13. Paul Formosa, “Understanding Evil Acts”, (Jun 2007) Vol 30, N0 2 Human Studies pp 57-77 at p 68. Eichmann in Jerusalem, p 278. Ibid, p 279. Ibid, p 261. See Kuala Lumpur War Crimes Tribunal. Other similar tribunals would be the Permanent Peoples Tribunal set up in 1976 and the most recent predecessor of the KLWCT: World Tribunal on Iraq set up in 2005. Eichmann in Jerusalem, “Introduction”, p xiv. Ibid, “Introduction”, p xx. Al Jazeera, Kuala Lumpur Tribunal – “Bush and Blair Guilty” http://www. perdana.org.my/emagazine/tag/klfcw/ (accessed on 20/06/2012). These details are unfortunately beyond the scope of this essay. Tun Mahathir hopes that Malaysians will not invite persons convicted of war crimes to the country http://my.news.yahoo.com/tun-mahathirhopes-msians-not-invite-persons-convicted-150013407.html (accessed on 20/06/2012). 39 Advertise in the Brickfields Law Review Law of Contract 4th edition ad (PRAXI S)_Layout 1 10/14/1 1 12:45 PM Page 1 2 Brick field Law of Contract Sinnadurai Law Jury T Reas rials: F oning Now ro & Ins to Fac m the To tituti ssing e book ons by Sab of Co ah C ins to arrim the O uija In 17 85 Order Now! via our eBookstore @ www.lexisnexis.c om/ store/my/ “ pt 20 Board 11 had de , two juro rs conf termin a verd essed ed th th ict e the wh delivered verdict by at the pane jury (w by a jury tossing a l of jury th matter) ole 2 coin. 1 ey sat fo hi Later, on on ho . In 1994 ch means reman wa s in Second w th , then lea a verdict wa jurors prov at the latter not determ 1922, are ram ly, note that in ided th 1995, ked the sto s reached a third had no say ed by in relate pant. Whe ese irregul a ry to d th arities to invo group of a journ a criminal party info in the contin tool caused er or not in the ju rm tri ke ali ro al; ati st rs the sp would irit of was involve who then the third pa on these ue to give un the irregul the Ouija conduct of pr ov pu board ju irr th ari rty id d due im 2011 blished e dece e guid in usin or an ry trials instead egularities. ju portanc ties is irrele interne In defen ror Joanne ance in de ased victim g an Oui it. 3 In vant. of e to th ch e da must livering tja board Maria in the bear in annelling en process, we the means However, other nt, Jamie Fr th ho ail e pe of pe we l in co ve de St ergy all min dulge mmun a few fendants we ewart thro egedly co rdict. 4 Rece that it in mere rpetuating icatio d that with into fire th nt cases ug nt pr re n ere ac firefi h Face ly, in eventio ted th will tec still aw wi am scand e ac bo n. After ghting aiting Yet, rec ll always be definitely hnological als that ong the their ok even th quitted man pr occur ough scand ords reveal new chall become m ogress, meth all one in jury y others th verdicts. or al th en th In orde Th e e br ge od at tri at compl ese eaks ou 8 s to fac s of we are als. 5 indica when ex, t. te the are only e sti all to allowr to avoid th nature advanc these incid It looks utter ll taken ab in managin and so ac g of cleare trial Judg ese irregulari e and r es thereby ents could ly ridiculou k every tim juries. have ve e a ne s to rea on th instructions to particip ties, there ha avoid e in Tack w ate ct ed. ry we ling th at a loc ternet 6 or to jurors be in jury de ve been sugg ll been in this wa y e Ro ev predict ot Ca comm ation where en to seque fore the tri liberations estions ed in ; to It is al; uses un ster ju they would ication. 7 rors du to build fir issue in clear that How have no merely the dicates ring cri ew tackle ever, it is access to the ne continuing minal alls di the pr ed for m , But fir oblem y belief th gital meth trials Th a drast if not grow ods of e key superfi at these ic solu ing nu questionst and forem cially tion. mber of the to finding and in measures of th m pr aforem : why is th ost, it is ishaps adequa spirits, oblem by e solution importa e in entione tely. is to asking: nt to d cases formation could toss coins why do focus on th /ev ask th deem or be man It woul e ed un idence ob e to: (1 d y answ contact the jurors feel originatin reliab tained following ) th spirits be too easy le? throug trial; (2 e inadequa ers to this defendant the need to g cause an h the morall d contac to dismiss co th of expe ) the mere cy of instruc question: it in the trial? 9 ntact tin y pl difficu outrageou g the accu e acts of to tio situatio rience and ayfulness on ns given could be att There ssing lt s sed th a coin ou sel wrong. to come up and irrati ributed n. Th rough , in ese wi f-confiden the part of t at the sta on ju ll be de rt test to Therefore, with clearl al. As m Facebook voking ce of Th as bein jurors rors; or (3) of the oral rel we alt wi y determ th in g giv e first caus ati ine wh rely heavily defined sta the fo in dealing the lack e see ndard vists, it at is all en on an llowing wi Fortu owed objectiv s of right is for clear instruc ms to be un nately, parag th the an ex an d tio am e ju rap that fil our leg what d th stified: ns at th ple, At hs. is not and positivi ter allowed objectiv s eviden al system ha st sh e trial Judg torney-Gen e start of a jurors are ce e had already trial. In s . ould eral given therefo e test of rel and admits instated a “repeateDominic Gr Joanna Fr being We ca not discuss co iab re, th nn th ail many iev at ad ility and only that wh mplex mec the sam ot avoid th e case with d directions e QC sta ’s trial wa m cogenc hanism ich ted th meticu ys. When itting su an the ca e type of m e realisation yone outsi to the jury ch ev y. It goes has passed at lously this ty th withou pa idence an falsified isc pe of sieved of their city of juro onduct in that the pe de their nu at they t we m rp rs di explain — in othe out eviden ak eviden is question saying, cut lin obligation do not see cates that etual occu ber…” ce r ce able rrenc m to s. They lay e in causes s why the words it tam , the overa is combi ned wi eviden that legal outbrea ll resul retrials fail m appreciat people, ac e of pers ex ce th energ y are wa to be orde k of such with the fin t is obvious definite . Hence giv perts draw iserably to e the seriou ting in scand al ve s natu ly red. In ly not betwee recogni sted. ing ou re solve n t se the pr als in the rdict. This in rel th str iab the pr ocess, ju In the oblem uctions, alb le and un e clear time, ry system . en rel eit cle money above. d, we are ar on iable and lef es, wi that th Without ha t with th ll e last ving to ey also tw jurors point o possi go th do lack co es not sit to the sam rough them bilities m e co entione nfidenc we in d e in tak ll with them nclusion: th detail, it is e ing de . cision They are role taken trite up shifty, s. unsure by and and ISBN 978-967-400-0 Dato’ Seri Visu Sinn adurai, Law of Contract, Fourth Edition RM 700 About the Author Dato’ Seri Dr Visu Sinnadurai, who also authored the first three editions of this book is highly respected by legal profession als and academicians in the region. He is a Fellow Nottingham Unive of rsity, England, form er Dean and Professor for Comparative Law at the University of Malay a and Specialist of the World a Senior Judicial Bank, USA. He is a former Judge of the High Court of Malay a and a former Commissi oner for Law Revis ion. The first three editions of The Law of Cont ract received excellent reviews and have been quoted extensively in local and intern ational case law reporters and journals. July-Se 30-1 In 2010, the Mala ysian Parliament introduced amendm ents to the Consumer Protecti on Act to provide for unfair contrac t terms in consumer transact ions. This, perhaps is the maj or piece of legislation, together with the Electronic Commer ce Act, that has affected contrac tual relationship over the past cen tury.” Revie w mon Fourth Edition Dato’ Seri Dr Visu s Law Com Sinnadurai Leading Cases on the Law of Contract will be coming soon! Sinnadurai Leading Cases on the Law of Contract contains relevant cases on the law of contract in Malaysia. These edited judgm ents of the Malaysian Cour ts complement the discussion of these cases in the Law of Contract, Fourth Edition. Log on to www.lexisnexis.c to browse and purchas om/store/my e books online For Enquiry, please contact our Helpdesk at 1800-80 -6374 or Email: help.my@lexisn exis.com Follow us on Twitter @ http://twitter.com /LexisNexisMY For further enquiries, please contact Mr Hasnizam Mohamad at Tel: (603)7882 3534 / 019 392 6951 or E-mail: hasnizam.mohamad@lexisnexis.com R R