Literature Review - Locating Intersectional Discrimination
Transcription
Literature Review - Locating Intersectional Discrimination
Literature Review Collected Summaries and Critical Review of Literature on Intersectionality Project „Locating Intersectional Discrimination“ Apostolovski Veronika, Philipp Simone, Smith Sheena, Starl Klaus 09.11.2011 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Content Introduction ............................................................................................................................................. 6 Einleitung ................................................................................................................................................. 6 AKERMARK, Sia Spiliopoulou (2002): The Limits of Pluralism - Recent Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights with Regard to Minorities: Does the Prohibition of Discrimination Add Anything?, Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe. ....................................................... 8 ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil I – Begriffe, Theorien und juristische Analyse, Frankfurt am Main. ........................................................... 13 ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil I – Begriffe, Theorien und juristische Analyse, Frankfurt am Main. ........................................................... 14 ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil II – Eine empirische Untersuchung anhand von autobiografisch-narrativen Interviews, Frankfurt am Main. ...................................................................................................................................................... 20 APPIAH, Anthony (1990): But Would That Still Be Me? Notes on Gender, “Race”, Ethnicity, as Sources of “Identity”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 87, No. 10, Eighty-Seventh Annual Meeting American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division (Oct., 1990), 493-499 ....................................................... 21 ARNADOTTIR, Oddny Mjöll (2008): Multidimensional Equality from within: Themes from the European Convention on Human Rights, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE, Victoria: European Union NonDiscrimination Law – Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law, RoutledgeCavendish, 59-89. .................................................................................................................................. 23 BAER, Susanne, SMYKALLA, Sandra (2009): Zur Bedeutung von Stereotypen für gleichstellungspolitische Interventionen, in: BAER, Susanne, SMYKALLA, Sandra, HILDEBRANDT, Karin, Schubladen, Schablonen, Schema F – Stereotype als Herausforderung für Gleichstellungspolitik, USP Publishing, Kleine Verlag, Hamburg....................................................................................................... 24 BAER, Susanne (2010), A Closer Look at Law: human rights as multi-level sites of struggles over multidimensional equality, Utrecht Law Review 6/2, 56-76.......................................................................... 25 BAILEY, Alison (2010): On Intersectionality and the Whiteness of Feminist Philosophy, 51 – 70 in YANCY, George (2010): The Center Must Not Hold: White Women Philosophers on the Whiteness of Philosophy, Lanham, Lexington Books .................................................................................................. 27 BELL, Mark (2007): Direct Discrimination, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar et al., Non-Discrimination Law, Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland. Zusammenfassung Section 2.3.1 Causation and Comparators, 205207. ........................................................................................................................................................ 29 BUTLER, Judith (2000): Appearances Aside, California Law Review 88, 55-63 ..................................... 30 BURRI Susanne, SCHIEK Dagmar (Hg.) (2009): Multiple Discrimination in EU Law: Opportunities for legal responses to intersectional gender discrimination? European Network of Legal Experts in the ETC Graz 2 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Field of Gender Equality, European Commission, Directorate-General for Employment, Social Affairs and Equal Opportunities, Unit EMPL/G/2, Theme - Equality, Action against Discrimination: Legal Questions, July 2009 .............................................................................................................................. 31 BURRI, Susanne (2011): Promises of an Intersectional Approach in Practice? The Dutch Equal Treatment Commission’s Case Law, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union NonDiscrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate, 97-110............................................................................................................ 35 CZECH, Philip, SALINGER Ulrike (Hsg.) (2011): Diskriminierung – Grundrechtsverletzung oder Kavaliersdelikt. Das Gleichbehandlungsrecht in der Praxis, Menschenrechte konkret, Band 3, Salzburg ............................................................................................................................................................... 36 CARLES; Isabelle, JUBANY-BAUCELLS, Olga (2010): GendeRace. The Use of Racial Antidiscrimination Laws. Gender and Citizenship in a Multicultural Context. Final Report ................................................ 39 COLLINS, Hugh (2003): Discrimination, Equality and Social Inclusion. The Modern Law Review 66, pp. 16 – 43 ................................................................................................................................................... 47 DEGENER, Theresia (2011): Intersections between Disability, Race and Gender in Discrimination Law, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union Non-Discrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate, 29-46. ............... 58 DEUTSCH, Francine M. (2007): Undoing Gender, Gender & Society 21, 106-127 ................................ 59 DIETZE, Gabriele, HORNSCHEIDT, Antje, WALGENBACH, Katharina, PALM, Kerstin (2007): Gender als interdependente Kategorie. Neue Perspektiven auf Intersektionalität, Diversität und Heterogenität, Opladen, Verlag Barbara Budrich. ......................................................................................................... 60 EUROPEAN UNION AGENCY FOR FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS (FRA) (2010): Data in Focus Report. Multiple Discrimination, EU-MIDIS, European Union Minorities and Discrimination Survey 05......................... 61 FREDMAN, Sandra (2002): Discrimination Law. Oxford, Oxford University Press. ............................... 61 FREDMAN, Sandra (2005): Double Trouble – Multiple Discrimination and EU Law in: European AntiDiscrimination Law Review, Issue No. 2, October 2005, 13-18 ............................................................. 66 FREDMAN, Sandra (2010): Positive Duties and Socio-economic Disadvantage: bringing disadvantage onto the equality agenda, European Human Rights Law Review, 290-304. ......................................... 68 FRERICHS, Petra (2000): Klasse und Geschlecht als Kategorien sozialer Ungleichheit, Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie 52, 36-59..................................................................................... 70 GOLDBERG, Suzanne B (2009): Intersectionality in Theory and Practice in: GRABHAM, Emily, COOPER, Davina, KRISHNADAS, Jane and HERMAN, Didi (Hg.) (2009): Intersectionality and beyond: law, power and the politics of location, Oxford, Routledge-Cavendish. .................................................................. 71 GRABHAM, Emily (2009): Intersectionality: Traumatic Impressions, in GRABHAM, Emily, COOPER, Davina, KRISHNADAS, Jane and HERMAN, Didi (Hg.): Intersectionality and beyond: law, power and the politics of location, Oxford, Routledge-Cavendish. ......................................................................... 74 ETC Graz 3 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. HANNETT, Sarah (2003): Equality at the Intersections: The Legislative and Judicial Failure to Tackle Multiple Discrimination, 23 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1, 65-86 .................................................. 77 JACOB, Jutta, KÖBSELL, Swantje, WOLLRAD, Eske (Hg.) (2010): Gendering Disability. Intersektionale Aspekte von Behinderung und Geschlecht, Bielefeld, Transcript Verlag. ............................................. 79 KERNER, Ina (2009): Alles intersektional? Zum Verhältnis von Rassismus und Sexismus, Feministische Studien 1/2009, 36-50 ........................................................................................................................... 80 KLINGER, Cornelia, KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli (2007): Achsen der Ungleichheit – Achsen der Differenz: Verhältnisbestimmungen von Klasse, Geschlecht, „Rasse“/Ethnizität, in: KLINGER, Cornelia, KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli, SAUER, Birgit (Hg): Achsen der Ungleichheit. Zum Verhältnis von Klasse, Geschlecht und Ethnizität, Frankfurt........................................................................................................................ 81 KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli (2005): Intersectionality – Ein neues Paradigma feministischer Theorie? Zur transatlantischen Reise von Race, Class, Gender, Feministische Studien 23, 68-81. ............................ 82 KUHAR, Roman (2009): At the Crossroads of Discrimination. Multiple und intersectional discrimination, Peace Institute, Ljubljana ............................................................................................. 83 LUTZ, Mark A. (2001): On the Norm of Equality, International Journal of Social Economics; 2001; 28, 10-12, 782 .............................................................................................................................................. 84 MAKKONEN, Timo (2002): Multiple, Compound and Intersectional Discrimination: bringing the experiences of the most marginalized to force, Institute for Human Rights, Åbo Akademi University, April 2002............................................................................................................................................... 86 MARCHETTI, Elena (2008): Intersectional Race and Gender Analyses: Why Legal Processes Just Don’t Get It, Social and Legal Studies 17, 155-174.......................................................................................... 89 McCOLGAN, Aileen (2007): Reconfiguring Discrimination Law, Public Law, 74-94 .............................. 93 MIDDLEMISS, Sam and DOWNIE, Margaret (2009): Recent Changes in the Evidential Requirements in Indirect Sex and Race Discrimination Cases, International Journal of Law and Management 51, 367 – 373 ......................................................................................................................................................... 98 MORAWA, Alexander H E (2002): The Concept of Non-discrimination: An Introductory Comment, Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe ...................................................................... 102 NIELSEN, Ruth (2006): EU Law and Multiple Discrimination, CBS Law Studies, Copenhagen Business School .................................................................................................................................................. 104 PAREKH, Serena (2007): Resisting “Dull and Torpid” Assent: Returning to the Debate Over the Foundations of Human Rights, Human Rights Quarterly 29, 754-778 ................................................ 112 PATEL, Pragna (2003): Notes on Gender and Racial Discrimination: An urgent need to integrate an intersectional perspective to the examination und development of policies, strategies und remedies for gender and racial equality.............................................................................................................. 117 POST, Robert (2000): Prejudicial Appearances: The Logic of American Antidiscrimination Law, California Law Review 88, 1 – 40 ......................................................................................................... 118 ETC Graz 4 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. POTHIER, Dianne (2001): Connecting Grounds of Discrimination to Real Peoples’ Real Experiences, 13 Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 37 ...................................................................................... 122 RAAB, Heike (2007): Intersektionalität in den Disability Studies. Zur Interdependenz von Behinderung, Heteronormativität und Geschlecht, in: WALDSCHMIDT, Anna (Hg.): Disability Studies, Kultursoziologie und Soziologie der Behinderung: Erkundungen in einem neuen Forschungsfeld, Bielefeld. .............................................................................................................................................. 125 SCHIEK, Dagmar (2009): From European Union Non-discrimination Law Towards Multidimensional Equality Law for Europe, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE, Victoria, European Union Non-Discrimination Law, Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law. Routledge Cavendish, London, New York.............................................................................................................................................. 125 SCHIEK, Dagmar (2011): Organizing EU Equality Law around the Nodes of ‚Race‘, Gender and Disability, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union Non-Discrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate. ............................................................................................................................................................. 129 SHESTACK, Jerome J (1998): The Philosophic Foundations of Human Rights, Human Rights Quarterly 20, 201-234 .......................................................................................................................................... 130 SOILAND, Tove (2008): Die Verhältnisse gingen und die Kategorien kamen. Intersectionality oder vom Unbehagen an der amerikanischen Theorie, Querelles-Net, Rezensionszeitschrift für Frauen- und Geschlechterforschung 26 ................................................................................................................... 134 SOLANKE; Iyiola (2009): Stigma: A Limiting Principle Allowing Multiple-Consciousness in AntiDiscrimination Law?, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE; Victoria, European Union Non-Discrimination Law, Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law. Routledge Cavendish, London, New York, 115-136....................................................................................................................................... 134 SOLANKE, Iyiola (2009): Putting Race and Gender Together: A New Approach to Intersectionality, The modern law review, 72(5), 723-749 .................................................................................................... 137 WALBY, Sylvia (2007): Complexity Theory, Systems Theory, and Multiple Intersecting Social Inequalities, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 37, 449-470 ............................................................... 142 WINKER, Gabriele, DEGELE, Nina (2009): Intersektionalität. Zur Analyse sozialer Ungleichheiten, Transcript Verlag.................................................................................................................................. 145 WINKER, Gabriele, DEGELE, Nina (2011): Intersectionality as Multi-level Analysis: Dealing with social inequality, European Journal of Women’s Studies 18, 51-66 ............................................................. 149 CASES ................................................................................................................................................... 151 ETC Graz 5 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Introduction The ETC-project “Locating Intersectional Discrimination” (LID) seeks to apply the intersectional theory to legal practice. It not only aims to reveal the relevance of intersectional discrimination but also to investigate how intersectional discrimination could be regarded by the existing legal norms. Therefore we conduct an interdisciplinary approach which encompasses theoretical and practical parts. The LID project asks the following questions: What are the characteristics and specifications of intersectional discrimination which distinguish it from other ‘single ground models’? How can intersectional discrimination be defined both in a legal and a social science context and how can it be identified in practice? To what extent do antidiscrimination laws cover intersectional discrimination? How can intersectional discrimination be integrated into law and how can it be included into legal practice, so that it is adequately addressed in legal proceedings? Are there solutions to the problems of finding adequate comparators? Does legal practice correspond to people’s real-life experience of intersectional discrimination? The collection of summaries was made for the purposes of research in the LID project. The summaries are, for that reason, somewhat selective in terms of content and focus and are not simply summaries of the articles; for example, any material judged to be irrelevant to the project was excluded while, on the other hand, quotes that had potential importance to the Locating Intersectional Discrimination were included so that this collection could function as a quick-find resource. The summaries and analyses are in an alphabetical order by authors. Some are in English, some are in German. Einleitung Das Projekt „Locating Intersectional Discrimination” (LID) strebt danach, intersektionale Theorie auf die Rechtspraxis anzuwenden, um intersektionale Diskriminierung erkennen und adäquat adressieren zu können. Es zielt nicht nur darauf ab aufzuzeigen, dass intersektionale Diskriminierung relevant ist, sondern auch darauf zu untersuchen, wie intersektionale Diskriminierung von den bestehenden Rechtssystemen behandelt werden kann. Dazu wird im Projekt ein interdisziplinärer Zugang verfolgt, der theoretische und praktische Ansätze beinhaltet. Die Forschungsfragen des LID Projektes sind: Was sind die Merkmale und Besonderheiten von intersektionaler Diskriminierung und was unterscheidet diese von den „single-ground Modellen“? Wie kann intersektionale Diskriminierung im rechtlichen und sozialwissenschaftlichen Kontext entsprechend definiert und in der Praxis identifiziert werden? ETC Graz 6 Literature Review In wie weit Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. decken die bestehenden Antidiskriminierungsgesetze intersektionale Diskriminierung ab? Wie kann intersektionale Diskriminierung in bestehendes Recht integriert und wie mit diesem verhandelt werden, sodass intersektionale Diskriminierungen angemessen bedacht werden? Welche Lösungsansätze existieren für die Problematik mit adäquaten Vergleichspersonen? Decken sich Lebensrealitäten und Rechtspraxis hinsichtlich intersektionalen Diskriminierungserfahrungen? Im Rahmen des Projektes Locating Intersectional Discrimination (LID) wurde in Hinblick auf die Forschungsfragen ein umfangreiches Literaturstudium betrieben und zu ausgewählten Beiträgen Zusammenfassungen und kritische Auswertungen verfasst und zusammengestellt. Diese Zusammenstellung dient interessierten Personen aus Wissenschaft und Praxis als praktischer Ressourcen-Quickfinder. Zu berücksichtigen ist, dass die Auswertungen und Zusammenfassungen in ihrem Fokus selektiv sind. Einerseits wurden Teile ausgelassen, die für das Projekt von geringer Relevanz erschienen, andererseits wurden zahlreiche direkte Zitate aus den bearbeiteten Materialien eingefügt. Die Zusammenfassungen und Auswertungen sind alphabetisch geordnet. Sie sind teils in englischer, teils in deutscher Sprache verfasst. ETC Graz 7 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. AKERMARK, Sia Spiliopoulou (2002): The Limits of Pluralism - Recent Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights with Regard to Minorities: Does the Prohibition of Discrimination Add Anything?, Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe. Article 14 of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms is the only explicit reference to minorities in that convention (Akermark p. 1). Article 14’s accessory nature was established in Belgian Linguistic Case. (Akermark pp. 2 -3) Protocol No 12 adapted to the European Convention on 26 June 2000 (Akermark p. 3), but in 2002 it still had not been ratified by enough states for it to enter into force (as 10 needed, but only 2 had). (Akermark p. 4) Protocol 12 was designed to be substantive (and so not an accessory like Article 14) (Akermark p. 4): “However, in Thlimmenos v. Greece, following the thrust in its earlier case law, the Court explained that the application of Article 14 does not presuppose a breach of one or more of any such provisions and to this extent it is autonomous. Instead, for Article 14 to become applicable it suffices that the facts of a case fall within the ambit of one or more substantive provisions of the Convention or its Protocols.” (Akermark p. 4, emphasis original) Akermark noted that here the court took a liberal approach to interpretation, first of Article 9 (freedom of religion) and then even more so in regard to Article 14. Akermark provides the following quote from the case as support: “The Court has so far considered that the right under Article 14 not to be discriminated against in the enjoyment of the rights guaranteed under the Convention is violated when States treat differently persons in analogous situations without providing an objective and reasonable justification .... However, the Court considers that this is not the only facet of the prohibition of discrimination in Article 14. The right not to be discriminated against in the enjoyment of the rights guaranteed under the Convention is also violated when States without an objective and reasonable justification fail to treat differently persons whose situations are significantly different”. (Thlimmenos v. Greece, Application No. 34369/97, Judgment 6 April 2000, para. 44 (emphasis added). In Akermark p. 5) In this case a Jehovah’s Witness refused to participate in military service and, as a result of this refusal, got a criminal record which prevented him from practicing as an accountant. From the judgment in this case Akermark draws two conclusions: “In other words, the Court seems here to be doing two things: firstly, it is shifting the burden of proof from the applicant to the respondent state. The applicant needs to ETC Graz 8 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. argue only that the complaint concerns significantly different situations, which are treated similarly. It is then up to the state to prove that the undifferentiated treatment has a legitimate aim, which can be justified as objective and proportionate. Secondly, and perhaps more importantly, the Court is arguing that the Convention imposes positive obligations on the basis of the prohibition of Article 14, which is otherwise usually perceived as a primarily negative obligation. The assumption is that different situations should be treated differently.” (Akermark p. 5) However, Akermark then discusses the more recent case of Podkolzina v Latvia which points to a more conservative approach being taken. In that case Article 14 was not even considered in addition to Article 3 of Protocol No 1, although it did seem to be open to consideration. Here Latvia has strict language requirements as a basis for eligibility for election, ruling out many members of minority groups. This leaves the status of Article 14 in doubt. (Akermark p. 6) Akermark’s method is to examine a selection of cases in two areas: 1) registration and recognition of minorities and minority institutions; 2) right to respect for a traditional way of life. (Akermark p. 8) The first group fall mostly within Article 11 (freedom of assembly and association) but also Article 6 (right to fair trial), Article 9 (freedom of thought, conscience, and religion) and Article 10 (freedom of expression) taken alone and together with Article 14 (prohibition of discrimination). Akermark also classifies this as the public sphere concern. (Akermark p. 8) The second group mostly concerns Article 8 (right to private and family life) as such and in conjunction with Article 14. Akermark classifies this as the private sphere concern. (Akermark p. 8) Registration and Recognition of Minorities and Minority Institutions Akermark divides this further into two groups: 1) minority organizations, including political parties; and 2) religious institutions. (Akermark p. 9) The first cases concern the dissolution of political parties in Turkey on the basis of national security, public safety etc. Against this the Court put the importance of political pluralism and found Turkey in violation of Article 11 – it did not then need to consider other grounds such as Article 14. (Akermark pp. 9 – 10) In Refah Partisi v Turkey, however, the party dissolved was an Islamic party that was held to breach Turkey’s policy of secular government. No violation of Article 11 was found and no other violations were considered as the court said they would all concern the same facts as those that failed to show a violation of Article 11. (Akermark pp. 11 – 12) ETC Graz 9 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Akermark criticizes the argument that Article 14 had been dealt with in the consideration of Article 11. Akermark also thinks that this decision was inconsistent with the earlier decisions that did find violations of Article 11. Akermark suggests that perhaps the Thlimmenos approach of different cases being treated differently explains it. Although he is very critical of what this would mean for democracy and liberal individualism. (Akermark p. 13) Also, in Gorzelik v Poland the Polish authorities refused registration of an organization but the court found no violation of Article 11. (Akermark pp. 13 – 14) Akermark identifies four steps in the reasoning of the court: 1) Democracy does not mean that the majority must always prevail. 2) Recognition of minority membership requires bilateral treaties or registration of associations but this alone did not have consequences for Article 11 rights. 3) The name of the association, which was insisted upon, made it sound political. 4) It was reasonable for the state to protect its electoral system as it did. (Akermark p. 14) Akermark notes the apparent contradictions in this reasoning and that the court failed to address issues of discrimination even though both the government and the group had raised it as an issue. (Akermark p. 14) Akermark now moves to the second group of cases concerning religious institutions. (Akermark p. 16) In Canea Catholic Church v Greece, the court found a violation of both Article 6 and Article 14 taken together with Article 6. The group succeeded by comparing itself to both the Greek Orthodox Church and the Jewish community and the government could not justify its difference in treatment. (Akermark p. 16) In Cha’are Shalom ve Tsedek v France an Orthodox Jewish group wanted to secure ritual slaughter rights according to its own standards which were different than those that had been granted to the wider Jewish community. The court found no violation of Articles 9 and 14 considered together. The reasons seem to be based mainly around the proportionality of the particular practice they wanted allowed within the right to religion and the state’s interest in health etc. The fact that the meat they wanted could be imported and that the difference between their own practice and the standard Jewish practice was seen to be minimal also had an impact. (Akermark p. 16) The dissenting judges, however, were very critical and felt that the fact that the group was a minority of a minority had counted against it but that it should not have, even though allowing minority groups to fracture in this way with regard to rights claims would be more work for the state etc. (Akermark p. 17) ETC Graz 10 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. In Metropolitan Church of Bessarabia and others v Moldova the court found the refusal to recognize the church was disproportionate to the legitimate aims pursued and so amounted to a violation of Article 9. It thought the claim under Article 14 was a repetition of the Article 9 claim. It also found a violation of Article 13 (right to an effective remedy). Akermark is critical of the court’s avoidance of the question of the status of the church – was it a splinter group or something else? - he argues that this is necessary in order to assess discrimination. (Akermark pp. 17-18) Respect for a traditional way of life Article 8 ECHR protects the right to private and family life – does this include the right to respect for a traditional way of life? Buckley v the United Kingdom 1996 – a Gypsy woman was denied permission to live in her caravan on her own land. “The applicant claimed that the designation system under the 1968 Caravan Sites Act and the criminalization of “unauthorized camping” under the 1994 Criminal Justice and Public Order Act discriminated against gypsies by preventing them from pursuing their traditional lifestyle.” (Akermark p. 18) The court found no violation of Article 8 although it did think that the case was admissible on this point. This means that protection of a traditional lifestyle falls within Article 8. (Akermark p. 19) The court also found no violation of Article 14. Akermark is critical of the court’s analysis, arguing that the court did not properly consider the whole picture of the difficulties of Gypsy life in the UK and, in particular, that the court failed to take into account that the applicant was a single mother of three children which made many of the sites offered by the UK unsuitable. (Akermark p. 19) A group of cases on the same topic as Buckley followed in 2001. Akermark focuses on Chapman v the United Kingdom (Application no 27238/95). Here the court discusses the situation facing Roma in the UK in more detail. It also held that being a member of a traditional minority may have an influence on the manner in which laws were implemented. From the judgment: “As intimated in the Buckley judgment, the vulnerable position of gypsies as a minority means that some special consideration should be given to their needs and their different lifestyle both in the relevant regulatory planning framework and in arriving at the decisions in particular cases .... To this extent there is thus a positive obligation imposed on the Contracting States by virtue of Article 8 to facilitate the gypsy way of life.” (quoted in Akermark p. 20) So a positive obligation on states was found. However, even though it is well established that there are not enough camping places etc in the UK for Gypsies, this was not held to be a ETC Graz 11 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. violation of Article 8. The court thought that Article 8 could not be interpreted to impose a positive obligation that had such far reaching implications for social policy. There were however dissenting judgments that did find a violation. (Akermark p. 20) Problems that need to be addressed There is uncertainty about when and why a court even considers Article 14 violations. (Akermark p. 21) “In general, the Court does not examine Article 14 violations if it has established a violation of another substantive provision.” Although Akermark notes that this is not always the case. (Akermark p. 21) A reference to intersectional discrimination: “A related matter is that of the theoretical and practical consequences (for instance concerning procedural or compensation matters) as well as the advantages or disadvantages of the identification of multiple, cumulative violations by the Court. This would be particularly relevant to study in situations of so called 'multiple discrimination'.” (Akermark p. 21 – reference to Makkonen omitted) Akermark also notes that in order to consider discriminatory practices, the court requires a lot of evidence – statistical and narrative – and that apart from the difficulty of obtaining the statistical evidence that can exist, there can also be a tension between the subjective experience of the applicant and the objective reality of the statistics. (Akermark p. 21) Akermark argues that the Court uses faulty logic in dealing with indirect discrimination. The legislation seems much more open to claims than the court admits. (Akermark p. 22) Akermark also points out that the protection of minorities is not a consistent scheme in Europe. The relationship between the European Convention of Human Rights and the Framework Convention on National Minorities has been discussed in cases such as the Gorzelik case and the Chapman case. (Akermark p. 22) ETC Graz 12 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil I – Begriffe, Theorien und juristische Analyse, Frankfurt am Main. A) Diskriminierungsgründe benennen nicht Unterschiede hinsichtlich persönlicher Merkmale sondern Lebensrealitäten als Diskriminierungserfahrungen. Es handelt sich hierbei um Kategorisierungen, anhand welcher Menschen stereotypisiert und bewertet werden. (Antidiskriminierungsstelle des Bundes I. (im Folgenden: ADB I), S. 4) Es gibt eine intersektionale Verwobenheit der Kategorien, daher ist davon auszugehen, dass intersektionale Diskriminierung die Regel ist. Es besteht ein Bedarf an interdisziplinärer Forschung zum Thema (ADB I, S. 5), auch in der Erhebung von Beschwerdedaten muss intersektionale Diskriminierung berücksichtigt werden. Benennungen führen zu Kategorisierungen. (ADB I, S. 20) Auch die Benennung von „Gründen“ im Recht kann zur Fortschreibung von Stereotypen führen. Man muss sich überlegen, wie man über Menschen und ihre Erfahrungen sprechen kann, ohne Diskriminierung sprachlich zu wiederholen. (ADB I, S. 21) Baer spricht sich für das Wort Kategorisierung statt Gründe oder Merkmale aus. (ADB I, S. 26) Sie verwendet prozessuale Begrifflichkeiten, um den konstruierten Charakter von Kategorisierungen offenzulegen. Beispiele hierfür wären: ethnisierte Herkunft statt ethnische Herkunft; „Vergeschlechtlichung“ statt Geschlecht; „Kulturalisierung“ statt Religion oder Weltanschauung; „behinderte Entfaltung“ statt Behinderung; „Bio-Chronologisierung“ statt Alter; „sexuelle Normierung“ statt sexuelle Identität. Hierdurch wird klar, dass diese Kategorien nicht Identitäten sind, die Menschen haben, sondern dass es um Kategorisierungen geht, um Zuschreibungen durch andere, die sich in anderen, meist übergeordneten Machtpositionen Selbstbeschreibungen betroffener befinden. Diese Personen Kategorisierungen übernommen werden. können Der als Begriff Kategorisierung weist auch auf den Zusammenhang von Benachteiligung und Norm hin. Was/wer nicht normkonform ist, macht mit höherer Wahrscheinlichkeit Diskriminierungserfahrungen. Gegen die Verwendung des Begriffes „Gründe“ hat Baer zu sagen, dass die Verwendung des Begriffes juristisch sinnvoll ist, da sie im Gesetz festgelegt ist. (ADB I, S. 61) Darüber hinaus sollte der Begriff jedoch nicht verwendet werden, auch in der Rechtspraxis nicht, denn Gründe legen den Schluss auf Begründung nahe, also auf Motivation zur Diskriminierung durch verschiedene Akteure (ADB I, S. 61), was für Diskriminierung irrelevant ist. Es darf nicht um Hintergründe und Motive gehen. Gründe können auch an ETC Graz 13 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Ursachen denken lassen und mit einer (Teil-)Schuld der Betroffenen an ihrem Schicksal einhergehen. Die Gründe für Diskriminierungen sind jedoch Zuschreibungen und Kategorisierungen, die andere Menschen in meist höheren Machtpositionen gegenüber anderen vornehmen. Dabei spielt die Norm eine wichtige Rolle, in anderen Worten das, was als normal konstruiert wurde. Gegen den Begriff Merkmal (ADB I, S. 62) hat die Autorin folgendes einzuwenden: Merkmal scheint etwas zu bezeichnen, das Menschen innehaben (Wesenszüge etc.). Tatsächlich werden diese Merkmale aber den Menschen zugeschrieben, weil sie außerhalb der Norm stehen. Merkmal birgt die Gefahr, dass die Schuld bei den betroffenen Personen gesucht wird und dass sich die betroffenen Personen auch mit diesen Merkmalen identifizieren. Die Begriffe Grund und Merkmal legen zudem nahe, dass es sich bei den betroffenen Personen um Gruppen handelt. (ADB I, S. 83) ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil I – Begriffe, Theorien und juristische Analyse, Frankfurt am Main. B) Das Allgemeine Gleichbehandlungsgesetz (AGG) in Deutschland hat zum Ziel, „Benachteiligungen aus Gründen der Rasse oder wegen der ethnischen Herkunft, des Geschlechts, der Religion oder Weltanschauung, einer Behinderung, des Alters oder der sexuellen Identität zu verhindern oder zu beseitigen“ (§ 1 AGG) Diese genannten ‚Gründe’ sind weder Unterschiede noch Diversität, sondern benennen Lebensrealitäten, nach denen sich gesellschaftliche Chancen verteilen (S. 4). Anhand dieser Lebensrealitäten (Anm: die sich durch Interaktionen immer wieder in abgewandelten Formen und Ausdrucksweisen reproduzieren) werden Menschen stereotypisiert und bewertet. Es handelt sich daher um Kategorisierungen (wertende Zuschreibungen und wertende Einordnungen). Diese Kategorisierungen sind intersektional verschränkt, nicht eindimensional, sondern komplex und werden auch als komplex erlebt. Die Lebensrealitäten als eindimensional zu behandeln, stereotypisiert wiederum und verkürzt die Probleme, um die es geht (S. 4). Als (mehrdimensionale) Diskriminierung beschreibt Baer die Erfahrung, in der sich bestimmte ‚Achsen der Ungleichheit’ (Klinger/Knapp) kreuzen und entlang derer soziale Positionen eingenommen werden (Anm: zugeschrieben werden). Kategorisierungen sind demnach Verhältnisse, in denen Menschen leben. Die rechtlichen Konsequenzen mehrdimensionaler Diskriminierung sind weitgehend ungeklärt, vereinzelt anerkennt der Gesetzgeber allerdings, dass Kategorisierungen zusammentreffen. Baer unterscheidet zwischen den Mehrdimensionalitäten, ob erst die Verschränkung zu Benachteiligung führt (Intersektionalität ieS) oder Kategorisierungen ETC Graz 14 Literature Review nebeneinander Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. wirken (‚Multiple Discrimination’) (S. 4). Die Analyse von Gerichtsentscheidungen zeige, dass Mehrdimensionalität entweder nicht erkannt oder nicht angemessen berücksichtigt wird. Als wichtigster Schritt ist zuerst die Aufhebung der Hierarchisierung von Diskriminierungen durch unterschiedliche Anwendungsbereiche und unterschiedliche Begründung zu beseitigen. Strukturelle Diskriminierung bedarf der mehrdimensionalen Analyse. Dabei ist mit dem Konzept der politischen Intersektionalität zu zeigen, wer von Diskriminierungen profitiert, dh, Diskriminierung muss durch die Rechtsdurchsetzung unrentabel gemacht werden. Allerdings bedarf es bei der Vorgabe wirksamer, angemessener und abschreckender Sanktionen noch eine rechtsdogmatisch befriedigende Lösung zu finden, die mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung nicht additiv, sondern einzelfallgerecht berücksichtigt (S. 6). In der Rechtsdurchsetzung müssen die Indizien für einen Anfangsverdacht mit entsprechenden statistischen Daten unterlegt werden (zur Vermeidung des Phänomens, das Smutny beschreibt, wenn es darum geht, das für die Diskriminierung ausschlaggebende Motiv zu benennen, Smutny 2011). Baer stellt fest, dass Diskriminierungsfälle in der Regel nicht eindimensional sind. Als Beispiel bringt sie die Debatte um das muslimische Kopftuch (S. 7). Die Kategorisierungen Religion, Geschlecht und ethnische Herkunft spielen eine Rolle. Aber auch der soziale Status muss berücksichtigt werden, denn die Debatte betrifft zumeist etwa Lehrerinnen in staatlichen Schulen und weniger Raumpflegerinnen in öffentlichen Gebäuden. Als weiteres Beispiel nennt Baer den Zugang zu zB Diskotheken (S. 8), der beispielsweise arabischen Männern verwehrt, Männern im Allgemeinen und arabischen Frauen jedoch gewährt wird. Es handelt sich in Diskriminierungsfällen um Situationen sozialer Ausgrenzung. Damit sind sie auch durch zB CERD oder CEDAW umfasst. Auch die Grundrechtecharta der EU ist so auszulegen, dass Anti-Diskriminierungsrecht sowohl ungerechtfertigte Ungleichbehandlung als auch soziale Ausgrenzung verhindern und beseitigen will (dazu auch Ulrich 2011). Wichtig ist weiters, dass das Gleichbehandlungsgesetz nicht darlegt, welche Beweisanforderungen für mehrdimensionale Diskriminierungen bestehen. § 4 AGG behandelt ja auch nicht mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, sondern die Anforderungen an eine Rechtfertigung von Ungleichbehandlung (S. 8). Begriffsklärungen Abzuklären sind „mehrdimensionaler“ die Bedeutungsinhalte von „mehrfacher“, und „intersektionaler“ Diskriminierung. „verstärkender“, Intersektionalität ist der Oberbegriff zur Beschreibung des Zusammenwirkens mehrerer Ungleichheitskategorien. Crenshaw’s Anliegen war es, Sachverhalte nicht nach Kategorien zu zerlegen, sondern als komplexes Geschehen zu verstehen. Ihr Einwand war rechtsdogmatisch: Aus dem ETC Graz 15 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. allgemeinen Gleichheitssatz werden unterschiedliche Schutzniveaus konstruiert und deshalb Menschen dazu gezwungen, sich exklusiv einer Kategorie zuzuordnen. Dies verhindere das Erkennen von und den Rechtsschutz bei intersektionaler Diskriminierung (S. 11). Intersektionale Diskriminierung bleibt unerkannt oder nicht anerkannt, wenn: a) eine Benachteiligung weder hinsichtlich der einen noch der anderen Kategorie nachgewiesen werden kann, sondern nur für beide Kategorien gemeinsam. Insbesondere handelt es sich hier um Probleme bei der Auswahl der Vergleichsperson; b) die Kategorisierung, die aus der Verschränkung entsteht oder eine der verschränkten Kategorisierungen nicht vom Schutzbereich umfasst sind; c) die von Kategorisierungen betroffenen Gruppen als homogen angenommen werden. Zur Behebung von b) schlägt Baer vor, im Gesetz bei den verpönten Motiven den Hinweis „oder aus einer Kombination“ bzw. „oder beim Zusammenkommen oder -wirken“ anzufügen (kritisch dazu Schiek 2011, durch die nachträgliche Einführung des Passus würde geklärt, dass dies bislang nicht möglich wäre). Als Ursache in der Nichterkennung von Mehrdimensionalität sieht Baer die Verharrung im eindimensionalen Modell des Anti-Diskriminierungsrechts, das sich auf Hierarchisierung der Motive, auf entsprechende Verhandlungsstrategien oder auf die Eigenwahrnehmung von Betroffenen auswirkt. Beispiele für Intersektionalitäten Homosexualität: Geschlecht und Sexualmoral (S. 11). Häusliche Gewalt: Geschlecht und Rechtsstatus Pflege und häusliche Arbeit: Reproduktionsarbeit durch MigrantInnen begünstigt „Weiße“ Schwangerschaftsabbruch bei behinderten Frauen (Problem der Entsexualisierung, Fürsorge statt „Enthinderung“). Behinderte Frauen haben aufgrund ihrer Abhängigkeit ein höheres Risiko, sexueller Gewalt und Belästigung ausgesetzt zu sein. Kategorisierungen müssen konsequent interdependent gedacht werden (empirischer Nachweis der Interdependenz durch Zick ua 2011), um Konstruktionen wie auch das Konzept der Normperson zu durchbrechen (S. 13). Es müssen jedenfalls machttheoretisch informierte Konzepte herangezogen werden (S. 16). Zentrale Fragestellungen sind, ob es um Individuen oder Gruppenzugehörigkeiten geht und ob es um subjektive oder zugeschriebene Identitäten oder um „natürliche“ oder soziokulturelle Merkmale der Betroffenen geht, oder um die Motive der TäterInnen (S. 17). Weiters ist die Frage wesentlich, nach welchen Begründungen die Auswahl der Motive erfolgt. Bleiben die Kategorien in allen Kontexten gleich relevant oder sind die Kategorien empirisch ETC Graz 16 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. laufend neu zu bestimmen? Baer plädiert für eine offene Liste der Diskriminierungsverbote nach dem Vorbild des Menschenrechtssystems (S. 18). Konzepte Baer stellt vier Konzepte vor: Achsen der Ungleichheit (Klinger/Knapp), Interdependenzen (Walgenbach), Intersectionality (Crenshaw) und Mehrfachdiskriminierung (Makkonen). Der erste Ansatz ist ein makrosoziologischer Ansatz. Walgenbachs Ansatz sieht eine genuine Verschränkung der Diskriminierungsgründe, wobei nicht Wechselwirkungen zwischen Kategorien betrachtet werden, sondern Kategorien selbst sollen als interdependent aufgefasst werden. Ihre Herstellung erfolgt durch Sprache bzw. Sprechakte. Crenshaw’s Konzept der Intersectionality bezieht sich auf die Benachteiligung, die durch das Recht aufgrund der homogenen Gruppensicht und der Eindimensionalität nicht gesehen wird. Makkonen wiederum unterscheidet zwischen Mehrfach-, Compound- und Intersektioneller Diskriminierung (Beispiele zu Makkonen S. 23). Zwischenfazit ist, dass die gesellschaftliche Chancenverteilung durch Kategorisierung – und nicht zufällig – ungleich ist. Die Chancenverteilung erfolgt durch Ausschlüsse entlang von „Achsen“ der Ungleichheit. Kategorisierungen entstehen durch Stereotypisierung und wertende Zuschreibung. Ungleichheit ist funktional. Diskriminierung hat ihre Grundlagen in kulturellen und symbolischen Ordnungen, ideologischen Verfestigungen und in Strukturen, die sich verletzend und in nachteiligen Erfahrungen manifestieren (S. 25). Der Begriff Kategorisierung soll erstens zeigen, dass es sich nicht um individuelle Merkmale handelt, die eine Diskriminierung „auslösen“, sondern um Dimensionen von Benachteiligung. Zweitens beschreibt der Begriff im Unterschied zur Kategorie ein aktives Handeln, es geht nicht darum, was Menschen sind, sondern darum, was aus ihnen im Zuge von Machtdiskursen gemacht wird (S. 26). Rechtsetzung Europäische und nationale Anti-Diskriminierungsgesetze beinhalten (bislang) keine Legaldefinitionen von Mehrfachdiskriminierung. Inwieweit die diversen Formen abgedeckt sind, ist einerseits interpretativ zu klären oder in der jeweiligen Fallkonstellation zu analysieren. Rechtlich gesehen, sollten diejenigen Fälle keine Schwierigkeiten bereiten, in denen Diskriminierungshandlungen oder deren Motivationen analytisch zu trennen sind, z.B. bei sexueller Belästigung und rassistischer Beschimpfung, oder, wenn, aus welchen Motivationen auch immer, die Diskriminierungshandlungen in einer zeitlichen Abfolge erfolgen (Beispiele S. 33). ETC Graz 17 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung ist laut Baer durch die gleichzeitige Diskriminierung unter Zugrundelegung mehrerer Kategorisierungen, wobei diese verschränkt sein können, aber nicht müssen. Zur rechtlichen Beurteilung sei die Zuordnung zu einer „Gruppe“ notwendig. Die Zuordnung zu mehreren Gruppen ist zwar nicht ausgeschlossen, jedoch bedarf es zur rechtlichen Beurteilung eines jeweils analytischen Vergleichs. Gerade dies ist aber bei verschränkter (intersektioneller) Diskriminierung nicht möglich, weil erstens diese „Gruppe“ nicht im Gesetz benannt wird und zweitens die Bestimmung und Auswahl einer Vergleichsperson schwierig oder unmöglich ist. Es ist klar, dass im Beispiel der diskriminierten „Schwarzen Frau“ weder Männer noch Weiße adäquate Vergleichsgruppen darstellen, allerdings ist auch das „Gegenteil“, nämlich der „Weiße Mann“ – um die beiden Gegengruppen zu verschränken – nicht notwendigerweise die geeignete Vergleichsperson, gleichwohl der hypothetische „Weiße Mann“ als Normperson im Verdacht steht, in der vergleichbaren Situation anders behandelt zu werden. Ein weiteres Problem besteht darin, dass zum Nachweis einer Diskriminierung ein Nachweis der Kausalität zwischen Ungleichbehandlung und verpöntem Motiv erforderlich ist. Monokausale Formeln (Nachweis des eigentlich ausschlaggebenden Grundes, vergleiche auch Smutny 2011) sind bestenfalls für eine analytisch trennbare Mehrfachdiskriminierung anwendbar. Bei Verschränkungen missachten monokausale Formeln entweder ein Motiv oder im ungünstigsten Fall wird das Vorliegen einer Diskriminierung verneint („hidden discrimination“). Diese Konstellation kann auch durch die Hierarchisierung der Diskriminierungsgründe auftreten, selbst dann, wenn die Mehrdimensionalität erkannt wird. Baer schlägt mit Hinweis auf Zinsmeister (Zinsmeister, Julia: Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Baden-Baden 2007) die inzidente Prüfung vor (S. 35). Dabei müsste im Verdacht auf das Zutreffen mehrerer Kategorisierungen auch hinsichtlich aller geprüft werden (kritisch dazu Makkonen, der den „intersektionalen Verdacht“ mit dem Hinweis auf die Gefahr von Opferstigmatisierung ablehnt, Makkonen 2002). Schließlich kommt noch das Problem des statistischen Beweises hinzu. Mehrdimensionale, insbesondere intersektionale Benachteiligungen und Diskriminierungen sind mittelbar, weil sie strukturelle Benachteiligungen sind. Nun ist der statistische Beweis anerkannt, jedoch insgesamt nur aufwändig zu erbringen und im Fall von Intersektionalitäten auch häufig nicht verfügbar, weil es keine Vergleichsgruppendaten gibt oder die von der spezifischen Intersektionalität betroffene „Gruppe“ zu klein ist, um statistisch signifikante Daten aufweisen zu können. Baer argumentiert, dass die EU (S 42, KOM (2004) 379; S. 44 KOM (2008) 4261) grundsätzlich das Problem von Mehrfachdiskriminierungen anerkennt und eine „kohärente 1 Der Vorschlag der Harmonisierungsrichtlinie soll die Hierarchisierung zwischen den Diskriminierungsgründen aufheben und soll der Vervollständigung der Anti-Diskriminierungsgesetzgebung dienen. Weiters stellt die Erwägung klar, dass es sich um die Konsistenz zwischen Diskriminierungsbekämpfung, Wachstumsstrategie ETC Graz 18 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. und integrierte Vorgangsweise“ (Anm: durch die Mitgliedstaaten) gefunden werden muss. Der nationale Gesetzgeber ist somit gefordert. Der Vorschlag, der Liste der verpönten Motive den Zusatz „oder Kombinationen“ anzufügen, wäre ein einfacher Schritt. Die Aufhebung der Hierarchisierung scheint jedoch (vorerst) an ideologischen Hürden zu scheitern, ebenso wie die Öffnung der taxativen Liste, wie dies die Charta der Grundrechte vorsieht. Sowohl aus dem Primär- als auch aus dem Sekundärrecht der Union kann ein entsprechendes Handlungsgebot für die Mitgliedsstaaten abgeleitet werden. Die größten Probleme für die Anerkennung von mehrdimensionalen Diskriminierungen liegen im Unwissen (der Insensibilität) und im Zwang zur Vergleichsgruppenbildung. Unter Hinweis auf Burri und Schiek (Burri/Schiek 2009) wird die Verknüpfung von sozialwissenschaftlicher und juristischer Herangehensweise empfohlen. Menschenrechte Baer verweist auf die neuen Ansätze in der Behindertenrechtskonvention, welche sowohl „schwierige Bedingungen“, also Lebensverhältnisse, anerkennt, die zu Diskriminierung von Menschen mit Behinderung (auch und zusätzlich) aus anderen Gründen (taxative, aber sehr weit interpretierbare Liste) ausgesetzt sind (Präambel, zit S. 46). Das heißt, die Behindertenrechtskonvention anerkennt den mehrdimensionalen Charakter von Diskriminierung, nimmt aber darüber hinaus auch auf die Benachteiligung und nicht nur auf formale (und symmetrische) Gleichbehandlung Bezug. Grundsätzlich hält Baer das Menschenrechtssystem mit seinem materiellen Gleichheitsanspruch und der Möglichkeit von positiven Maßnahmen zur Herstellung von Gleichheit (Gleichstellungsgebot) für ein geeignetes Instrument (S. 48). Daher folgert sie, dass das Gleichbehandlungsrecht im Lichte der Menschenrechtsnormen ausgelegt und daran angepasst (Anm: gemessen) werden müsse. Rechtsdurchsetzung Mehrdimensionalitäten können vor Gericht nur verhandelt werden, wenn sie auch entsprechend thematisiert und vorgebracht werden. Ist dies der Fall, ergeben sich dennoch die Probleme der Hierarchisierung der verpönten Motive durch die unterschiedlichen Anwendungsbereiche, die eingeschränkte Liste verpönter Motive, die Schwierigkeit in der Identifikation und Auswahl der Vergleichsperson bzw. Vergleichsgruppe, die Schwierigkeit der Verfügbarkeit eines statistischen Beweises sowie das Problem der monokausalen Begründung. Allerdings belegen die bisherigen Forschungsergebnisse, dass Mehrdimensionalitäten im Wesentlichen aus zwei Gründen gar nicht thematisiert werden. Zum einen sind sich die (Lissabon Strategie), den Zielen des Sozialschutzes und der sozialen Integration in Übereinstimmung mit der Grundrechtecharta handelt (S 3). ETC Graz 19 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Betroffenen der Mehrdimensionalität sehr oft nicht bewusst. Außerdem herrscht große Unsicherheit bei den Beratungseinrichtungen, einschließlich RechtsvertreterInnen, so dass diese ihre Mandantschaften auch nicht darauf aufmerksam machen. Zum Zweiten spielt das verhandlungstaktische Argument in der Praxis eine große Rolle. Abgewogen wird die Erfolgschance in einem kürzeren Verfahren nach den herrschenden Regeln nach einem Motiv und der monokausalen Formel gegenüber einer aufwändigen Argumentation mit vielen Unsicherheiten und großem Beweisrisiko. Eine kollektive Rechtsdurchsetzung könnte helfen, ist aber in den meisten EU Mitgliedstaaten nicht möglich (S. 51). Baer argumentiert, dass die „Gründe“ nicht im Zentrum der gerichtlichen Prüfung stehen sollten und führt dazu eine Entscheidung des EUGH (EuGH C-177/88, Urteil vom 8.11.1990 (Dekker)) an (S. 61), nach der es beim Diskriminierungsschutz nicht um Motive oder Absichten gehen dürfe. „Gründe“ ließen sich sonst als Ursachen denken, was dazu führe, dass der benachteiligten Person eine Verantwortung für ihre Benachteiligung zugeschrieben würde. Der Grund liege vielmehr in den „Achsen der Ungleichheit“, womit Vorstellungen vom „normalen“ Körper, von Geschlechterrollen usw. verbunden sind (S. 61). ANTIDISKRIMINIERUNGSSTELLE DES BUNDES (Hg.) (2010): Mehrdimensionale Diskriminierung, Teil II – Eine empirische Untersuchung anhand von autobiografischnarrativen Interviews, Frankfurt am Main. Ziel des Artikels: Autobiografische Interviews sollen ausgewertet werden, um zu erfahren, ob Erfahrungen mit Personengruppen mehrdimensionaler besonders betroffen Diskriminierung sind und gemacht in wurden, welchen welche Lebensbereichen. (Antidiskriminierungsstelle des Bundes II (im Folgenden: ADB II), S. 3) Insgesamt wurden 290 Interviews geführt. Es wurde nicht direkt nach Diskriminierungserfahrungen gefragt. (ADB II, S. 5) Die Dimensionen Alter, Herkunft, Geschlecht und sexuelle Orientierung wirken verstärkend aufeinander, Behinderung dominierend (Baer et al S. 6), Geschlecht zeigt sich fast immer als relevante Dimension. (ADB II, S. 7) Orte der Diskriminierung sind an erster Stelle die Familie (ADB II, S. 10, vor allem bei sexueller Orientierung), gefolgt von Schule (Herkunft und sexuelle Orientierung) und Arbeit (vor allem Herkunft Alltagssituationen und (Herkunft), Geschlecht). am Aber auch Wohnungsmarkt bei Behörden (Herkunft) und (Herkunft), in in stationären Einrichtungen (Alter) findet Diskriminierung statt. Da Diskriminierung nicht immer von den Betroffenen selbst so benannt wird, der Begriff sogar oft zurückgewiesen wird, wurden andere Begriffe verwendet, wie zum Beispiel „ungleiche Behandlung“, „mangelndes Zutrauen“, „Übersehen“, „Abwertung“, „Übergriffe“. ETC Graz 20 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Ressourcen und Rückhalt bieten die Familie (vor allem bei sexueller Orientierung, Behinderung und Herkunft) und die Religion (Religion und Weltanschauung, allerdings nicht bei sexueller Orientierung). (ADB II, S. 13) APPIAH, Anthony (1990): But Would That Still Be Me? Notes on Gender, “Race”, Ethnicity, as Sources of “Identity”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 87, No. 10, EightySeventh Annual Meeting American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division (Oct., 1990), 493-499 This article is old (1990) but is often referenced in more recent work. It may also form a bridge between “French”/continental philosophical approaches and “Anglo- American”/analytical ones. So although this article may be both a little too broad in its ideas for anti-discrimination and too old for state-of-the-art, it remains useful and worth considering as a foundational article. It discusses why gender and ‘race’ are not simple categories. Appiah does this in very traditional, analytic terms. He even uses Kripke, but it is not clear that this approach can avoid some kind of biological determinism. It is true that discussing gender in terms of chromosomal difference and physical appearance does create more than two categories, but is still a rather crude way of classifying people. It would seem to mean that medical science has the final say. Appiah proposes that culture is more fundamental and longer lasting than ‘race’ as a category. He poses the question “What if I had been raised a girl?” (but he was still chromosomally a boy). He proposes that, in such an eventuality, there is one way of looking at the question in which he would still be himself, and another in which he would not. (Appiah p. 494) He first considers the question changed to consider somebody who has undergone a sexchange: “What answer I should give to the question under-stood this way depends on how central my being-a-man is to my identity, not on how central I choose to make it.” (Appiah p. 495) He proposes that a transsexual would claim that this was the “Ureal me, the one I have always really been all along” but Appiah’s answer is “No. A sex-change operation would make of the (metaphysical) person a different (ethical) person.” (Appiah p. 495) He now turns to identity and ‘race’ which he thinks is very complicated in that ‘races’ are not clearly defined in the way gender seems to have certain physical signs (chromosomes etc) even if this, too, can be complicated. Appiah does not deny that people can have identities based on ‘race’ and that these can be externally determined. (Appiah p. 496) ETC Graz 21 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. He proposes a hypothetical of ‘race’-change: “Surely, in contemplating this possibility, she could ask herself whether, once these changes had occurred, the resulting ethical person "would still be me." And, so far as I can see, almost everyone who does contemplate this question in our society is likely to judge that, whether or not these changes are desirable, the answer here must be 'yes'.” (Appiah p. 497) Appiah’s conclusion is that in the modern West, racial ethical identities are “Dapparently less conceptually central to who one is than gender ethical identities.” (Appiah p. 497) He improves the position: “Nevertheless, even for those for whom being-African-American is an important aspect of their ethical identity, what matters to them is almost always not the unqualified fact of that descent, but rather something that they suppose to go with it: the experience of a life as a member of a group of people who experience themselves as-and are held by others to be-a community in virtue of their mutual recognition-and their recognition by others-as people of a common descent.” (Appiah p. 497)] He then discusses briefly the difference between ethnic and racial identities. “People of Irish-American descent adopted and raised outside Irish-American culture are still, perhaps, to be thought of as Irish-Americans; but they have a choice about whether this fact, once they are aware of it, should be central to their ethical identities, and their taking it as central would involve them in adopting certain cultural practices. D So far as I can see, by contrast, African-Americans who respond in this way fall into two categories, depending on whether or not their visible morphology permits them to "pass," permits them, that is, to act in society without their African ancestry's being noticed. If they cannot pass, they will often be thought of as inauthentic, D, though they will not be thought to be dishonest, since their morphology reveals the fact that is being denied. If they can pass, they will be thought of by many, as being not merely inauthentic but dishonest.” (Appiah p. 498) Appiah thinks that this distinction between ‘race’ and ethnicity is based on false beliefs as the distinction between ‘races’ is not even biologically determined. (Appiah pp. 498 – 499) None of this is to suggest that ‘race’ and gender are not centrally important to people when, for example, constructing their life plans. (Appiah p. 499) But: “We construct ethical identities-woman, man, African-American, ‘white’-in ways that depend crucially on false beliefs about meta-physical identities; something like each of them could be reconstructed out of other materials. But if we were to live in a society that did not institutionalize those false metaphysical beliefs, it is unclear that the project of reconstruction would be an attractive one. In a truly nonsexist, nonracist society, ETC Graz 22 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. gender, the ethical identity constructed on the base of sexual differences, would at least be radically differently configured, and might, like ‘‘race’,’ entirely wither away; ethnic identities, by contrast-and this is something an African- American identity could become-seem likely to persist so long as there are human cultures and subcultures, which is likely to mean as long as people are raised in families.” (Appiah p. 499) ARNADOTTIR, Oddny Mjöll (2008): Multidimensional Equality from within: Themes from the European Convention on Human Rights, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE, Victoria: European Union Non-Discrimination Law – Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law, Routledge-Cavendish, 59-89. Arnadottir stellt die Frage, ob aus dem einmaligen System der EMRK und Art. 14 etwas für die multidimensionale Zukunft des EU Gleichbehandlungsrechts gelernt werden kann. Vielversprechend an Art. 14 (und auch am gleichlautenden Artikel im 12. ZP) ist die nicht abschließende Aufzählung von Gründen. Dadurch ist es möglich, dass ein/e Kläger/Klägerin seine/ihre Beschwerde auf einer Vielzahl an Identitäten und Diskriminierungsgründen gründet. (Arnadottir S. 54) Wichtig in diesem Zusammenhang ist der Ermessensspielraum (margin of appreciation), den der EGMR den Mitgliedsstaaten zuspricht - dieser ist in Bezug auf die einzelnen EMRK Bestimmungen durchaus unterschiedlich ausgeformt. Dieser Ermessensspielraum fließt aus dem Prinzip der Subsidiarität des Konventionsschutzes, d.h. die ursprüngliche Betrachtung einer Rechtssache obliegt den Mitgliedsstaaten. Außerdem - da es innerhalb der Mitgliedsstaaten kulturelle Diversität gibt - soll diesen auch durch den Ermessensspielraum Rechnung getragen werden. (Arnadottir S. 58) In Art. 14 variiert der Ermessensspielraum in Bezug auf die Umstände, die Sache und den Hintergrund (Rasmussen v. Dänemark, 1985). Der Ermessensspielraum in der Geschlechterdiskriminierung ist sehr eng ausgestaltet, da die Gleichbehandlung der Geschlechter als allgemeines Ziel in allen Mitgliedsstaaten verstanden wird. Zum Thema der Vergleichsperson führt Arnadottir aus, dass der EGMR keine strikten Vorgaben hat, wie der Kläger seine Vergleichsperson präsentieren muss. Des Weiteren weist die offene Liste an Diskriminierungsgründen in Art. 14 darauf hin, dass der Gerichtshof auch eine Reihe an Fällen untersucht hat, die nicht mit den üblichen Diskriminierungsgründen zusammenhängen. Eine Case-Law deutet auf eine offene Herangehensweise an die Konstruktion der Diskriminierung hin. Artikel 14 ist nicht die allumfassende Lösung, jedoch sollte sein Potential nicht unterschätzt werden. Eine Norm für alle Diskriminierungsgründe und ein menschenrechtlicher Ansatz können manche Probleme im Umgang mit multidimensionaler Diskriminierung lösen. ETC Graz 23 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Nichtsdestotrotz müssen, so Arnadottir, diese allgemeinen Normen mit den konkreten Normen für die einzelnen Gründe koexistieren, um sich gegenseitig zu ergänzen. BAER, Susanne, SMYKALLA, Sandra (2009): Zur Bedeutung von Stereotypen für gleichstellungspolitische Interventionen, in: BAER, Susanne, SMYKALLA, Sandra, HILDEBRANDT, Karin, Schubladen, Schablonen, Schema F – Stereotype als Herausforderung für Gleichstellungspolitik, USP Publishing, Kleine Verlag, Hamburg. Gute und kurze Zusammenstellung von Definitionen von Stereotypen, Vorurteilen und ihrem Zusammenhang mit Diskriminierung sowie eine sehr brauchbare Darstellung und Argumentation, dass das EU-Antidiskriminierungsrecht (auch) Gleichstellungsrecht ist. Obwohl (Geschlechter)Diskriminierung fortbesteht, und dieses Faktum aufgrund eines großen Umfangs an Daten weithin bekannt ist, wird erstaunlich oft behauptet – auch von Frauen, zB Richterinnen – Frauen wären gleichberechtigt: auch das ist ein Stereotyp und für den Fortbestand von Diskriminierung (mit)verantwortlich. Welche Rolle spielen Stereotype für die Gleichstellungspolitik? Stereotype Vorstellungen binden Menschen an bestimmte und begrenzte Lebenslagen, sie schaffen das Bild vom „Wir“ und vom „Anderen“ und wirken dadurch unreflektiert – häufig unbemerkt und unbewusst – identitätsstiftend (S. 8). Wann wirken solche Bilder und Vorstellungen? Verursachen sie geschlechterdiskriminierende Erziehung, heteronormative und patriarchale Beziehungsvorstellungen, fehlende Vereinbarkeit von Erwerbs- und Privatleben, segregierte Ausbildungsentscheidungen und schließlich geschlechterbezogene Altersarmut? Ja, wenn sie institutionalisiert sind bzw. werden. Stereotype wirken nur im Kontext, dh dann, wenn in Regelungen auf sie Bezug genommen und sie in pädagogische Vorgaben einfließen. Stereotype benützen eine allgemeine Markierung, um eine Gruppe zu benennen – somit wird durch einen Oberbegriff eine Gruppe konstruiert (gute Beschreibung von Beispielen auf S. 9). Baer grenzt die Begriffe Stereotyp, Klischee, Stigma und Vorurteile ab. Vorurteil ist ein Stereotyp, das affektiv besetzt ist, wohingegen ein Stereotyp ein rationales „Muster im Kopf“ sein kann. Ein Stigma ist ein sozialer Definitionsprozess, bei dem ein Attribut eine negative Bewertung erhält. Stereotype bringen grundlegende Unterscheidungen zum Ausdruck, sie sind (auch) Orientierungshilfen und entfalten ihren Sinn erst durch die Einordnung in bestimmte Kategorien („Schubladen“). Sie sind damit ein Instrument zur Herstellung gesellschaftlicher Werte und Normen und iwS eine Praxis der Kategorisierung von Menschen und Verhältnissen (S. 10). ETC Graz 24 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Die Gleichstellungspolitik konzentriert sich zunehmend auch offiziell (EKommission 2006) auf Interventionen Schwerpunkten, zu S. Stereotypisierungen 11). Die (einer von Gleichstellungspolitik sechs ist gleichstellungspolitischen jedoch von konjunkturellen Schwankungen bedroht („zuerst Finanzkrise lösenU“), permanent mit einem Wechsel ihrer Zielgruppen konfrontiert (Gruppendiversifikation, Diversity-Mainstreaming, usw.) und muss sich an wechselnde Governancestrukturen anpassen, die nicht immer transparenzfördernd sind (zB Auslagerungen). Zudem kämpfen Gleichstellungspolitiken gegen ein schlechtes mediales Image und schließlich existieren auch innere Spannungen, wie Geschlechterdifferenzierungen oder Reproduktionen von Ausgrenzung und Dominanz. BAER, Susanne (2010), A Closer Look at Law: human rights as multi-level sites of struggles over multi-dimensional equality, Utrecht Law Review 6/2, 56-76. This article discusses conflicts between human rights relating to religion and equality, along with the way that these disputes are framed. Baer uses examples such as headscarves and swimming lessons and so centres the discussion on Muslim women and girls. She pays quite a lot of attention to the conflict that can occur between a religious group’s interest in maintaining strict gender roles and the individual’s freedoms to choose her own way of life. Within this context she discusses ‘groupism’: “Doctrinally, groupism is another problematic effect of symmetrical, Aristotelian equality analysis, in that this needs fixed units to compare, to similarly situate. Instead, equality is a right against groupism if it is understood as asymmetrical and substantive, a difference I return to below. Regarding religion, the difference is one between a concept of religious freedom tied to a collective and religious freedom as an individual right which may eventually be turned against hegemonic claims within a religious community.” (Baer p. 60) In short, she links ‘groupism’ to equal treatment and argues that, in contrast, it is in tension with substantive equality. From the perspective of the project Locating Intersectional Discrimination, she also makes some interesting observations about the ‘othering’ of sex inequality. These observations may be generalised to protected characteristics in discrimination law more generally and do hold a warning for an increased sensitivity to intersectional discrimination – it may lead to an increase in ‘othering’ of discrimination and a popular backlash or devaluing of the importance of discrimination (as it would be increasingly be viewed as a problem of the other etc). “Othering is a strategy to locate a problem elsewhere and to remain categorically clean, untouched; and orientalising is othering in a particular mode, establishing the occident ETC Graz 25 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. as the unlabelled standard and the orient as different, dark, elsewhere, the problem. D This is a move to protect majorities from challenges to the normalcy of privilege. They are not unknown. Regarding gendered and sexualized violence, many societies have labelled child abuse or the rape of married women by their husbands or domestic violence generally as a problem of the lower classes, effects of little education, bad habits, alcohol and other drugs, unemployment, poverty. Then, class is used to other inequality. And nowadays, it is often religion, sometimes coupled with class, which codes similar classifications. ‘Those’ immigrants, the mainstream story goes, do not yet know about modernity, have traditional problematic habits, are often unemployed and generally less economically successful than the rest of ‘us’.” (Baer pp. 61-62) One should be aware that something similar could happen with intersectionality and multiple discrimination. It could serve to make discrimination more removed from those in the dominant group. A rather uncontroversial and overarching point that may be of use to the LID project is that Baer points out that one should look at the broader context in considering conflicts such as the example of Muslim girls not attending swimming lessons in school. “To understand conflicts in human rights, we however need to understand the specific political, regulatory, or judicial procedures, the politics therein, the regulatory schemes around it, the actors involved, the discourses and the governance arrangements. So although it seems tempting to refer to ‘a case’ when it comes to very complicated issues, to look at ‘a right’ as if it had clear meaning and as if it would be guaranteed on one level, as if there were no competing claims of interpretation and on different levels of regulation, that does not do justice to the conflict nor to the law.” (Baer p. 64) Baer characterises this, however, as a kind of protest against the ‘fetishisation’ of law which is more controversial and not entirely convincing. She makes a more convincing case for pointing out the way that the equality vs religion and secularism debate is played out in a way that privileges Christianity and that the real problems are only emerging today when the religion concerned is Islam. Using Germany as an example: “Religions enjoy tremendous freedom to discriminate against all they define not to belong, and women are thus excluded from several positions in Catholic churches as well as Jewish communities. Now that Muslims claim such rights, conservatives call for equality, to not extend the privileges (to discriminate!) that they enjoy. And, as mentioned, the headscarf controversy has motivated some Länder to explicitly privilege Christianity, yet keeping the taboo of the yarmulke (which would have certainly shattered the Christian privilege in Germany), and never touching upon a Sikh turban, which seems not to appear in Germany on a relevant stage.” (Baer p. 68) ETC Graz 26 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Her further analysis of this issue does reveal what appear to be some troubling assumptions, though. In particular she states that “religious freedom often appears in the guise of culture” and uses this to point out the link to racism. The link to religious freedom and concerns with racism is solid, but the idea that religion “appears in the guise of culture” is a concern as it seems to imply that religion, properly understood, is a matter of private belief, conviction and spirituality. This itself seems to be a rather protestant Christian view of religion as private faith. Other religions (and brands of Christianity) would seem to place much more emphasis on ritual, community etc; which sounds a lot like culture. To see religion as merely a private matter of belief would be to diminish its importance and limit its scope. BAILEY, Alison (2010): On Intersectionality and the Whiteness of Feminist Philosophy, 51 – 70 in YANCY, George (2010): The Center Must Not Hold: White Women Philosophers on the Whiteness of Philosophy, Lanham, Lexington Books Philosophy has not engaged much with intersectionality debates at all. (Bailey p. 51) Bailey is critical of feminist philosophy’s attempt to get closer to white, male philosophers rather than feminist thinkers from other disciplines. (pp. 51 – 52) She is also critical of the way that, when other feminists are encountered, they are measured against white, male philosophical standards rather than measuring white, male philosophical standards against the work of feminists. (Bailey pp. 52 – 53) Bailey gives an outline of intersectionality (Bailey pp. 53 – 57) including a sketch of Crenshaw’s three varieties of intersectionality as identified in “Mapping the Margins”: structural, political and identity politics. In terms of intersectionality and identity politics, Bailey thinks it might be described philosophically as “an existential phenomenological approach that highlights human life from the inside, as lived experience, rather than pretending to understand it from an outside macroscopic point of view.” (Bailey p. 56) Bailey suggests that philosophy is resistant to engaging in the intersectionality debate as it is too Western, too tied to reason, valid arguments, theory, abstract argument and also, simply, too arrogant. (Bailey pp. 57 – 60) “So, intersectional approaches can place feminist philosophers in a disciplinary doublebind. If we theorize gender or ‘race’ too abstractly we lose sight of the diverse material conditions of women’s lives, and if we begin arguments in specific locations with women of color, then some will say that we are no longer doing philosophy.” (Bailey p. 58) Bailey also thinks that it is just plain painful for white women to acknowledge intersectionality as it complicates matters. (Bailey p. 60) ETC Graz 27 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Bailey suggests that it is worth pursuing the development of critical ‘race’ feminism in philosophy along the lines of critical ‘race’ feminism in legal studies in order to overcome the problems of philosophy being inherently white and male. (Bailey p. 61) She sees legal studies as a good model as it has useful conceptual similarities and concerns to philosophy. (Bailey p. 61) She then outlines what such a critical ‘race’ feminist philosophy might do. (Bailey p. 62 ff) She suggests starting with those concepts (such as person, rationality, objectivity) that feminists attacked for being male, and ask whether and how they are also white and colonial. (Bailey p. 62) She uses feminist bioethics as an example of an area that chose its interests in terms of what would be important to white, middle-class, Western women (high-tech issues such as in vitro fertilisation) at the expense of the issues that affect (poor) women of colour. (Bailey p. 62) To approach feminist bioethics intersectionally would mean starting anew. “Thinking intersectionally about surrogacy in a global context gets us to ask a different set of questions about the complex relationships between colonialism, capitalism, caste, and ‘race’ that are not addressed by the earlier literature on white American women’s experience as surrogates.” (Bailey p. 63) Bailey thinks the choice of language has also been white. She argues that the terms ‘choice’, ‘liberty’ etc reflect “...the class and ‘race’ privileges of women with access to healthcare.” (Bailey p. 63) Women of colour (and others) had different interests – such as involuntary sterilisation. (Bailey p. 63) For women of colour it seems to be more about justice than rights as such. Bailey thinks this changes the focus from individuals to structures. (Bailey p. 64) She cites work that has been done by men of colour (e.g. Charles Mills) to show that philosophy is white, but points out that this did not include an argument about philosophy also being gendered. (Bailey p. 65) Bailey suggests de-colonial philosophy as a starting point for taking an intersectional approach, citing the work of Maria Lugones. (Bailey p. 65) She discusses the way that colonialism particularly required that women be divided into separate genders based on ‘race’, so that black women could be set to hard manual labour while the white women were seen as chaste, delicate and mild etc. (Bailey p. 66) That is, the division between men and women worked differently depending on whether they were colonists or natives. (Bailey p. 66) Bailey suggests that philosophy can contribute to the intersectionality discussion by clarifying, expanding and challenging intersectionality. (Bailey p. 67) As an example, she suggests five premises on which intersectionality seems to rely: ETC Graz 28 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “1 Categories (i.e. ‘race’, gender) and systems (i.e. patriarchy, colonialism) are neither separate nor competing frameworks. 2 The effects of categories and systems are multiplicative and cannot be derived additively or independently from the effects of these individual systems or categories. They cannot be clearly separated. ‘race’ and gender should be conceptualized not as ‘race+gender’, instead they should be discussed as ‘gendered racism’ or how ‘gender is racialized’ 3 Categories and systems cannot be ranked in terms of importance or influence. For example, we should not think in terms of ‘race’ having a greater influence than gender or sexuality on Latina’s lives because these influences are inseparable, imbricated, and mutually coexist. 4 Categories and systems are neither reducible to nor interchangeable with one another. That is, we cannot simply reduce questions of racism or white privilege to matters of class. 5 All social frameworks and categories permeate, influence, align, and intermingle in all social relations (eg reproductive rights, cancer research, family structure, job discrimination).” (Bailey p. 67) Bailey then notes that intersectionality cannot do everything and may sometimes cause problems. (Bailey p. 68) BELL, Mark (2007): Direct Discrimination, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar et al., NonDiscrimination Law, Hart Publishing, Oxford and Portland. Zusammenfassung Section 2.3.1 Causation and Comparators, 205-207. Bell argumentiert die Grundfrage des Vergleichs mit der Frage des “Warum” einer Ungleichbehandlung (Benachteiligung, less favourable). Entscheidend ist, ob die Unterscheidung aufgrund eines verbotenen Unterscheidungsmerkmals oder auf anderen, zB funktionalen, Gründen beruht. Der Aristotelische Grundgedanke „Gleiches gleich zu behandeln“ liegt dem Ansatz zugrunde, dass in einer vergleichbaren Situation ohne Berücksichtigung irrelevanter Merkmale zwei Personen gleich zu behandeln sind. Entscheidungen sollten daher fair und vernünftig (rational) sein und auf Verdienst (merit) beruhen. Bell diskutiert drei Probleme: 1. Gleiches gleich zu behandeln ist relativ inhaltsleer. Was ist gleich, dh womit (mit wem) soll verglichen werden? Wer ist die richtige Vergleichsperson? ETC Graz 29 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Was ist die vergleichbare Situation? Beide Fragen sind eng verknüpft, bedingen sich bis zu einem gewissen Grad (die vergleichbare Situation hat Einfluss auf die Wahl der Vergleichsperson). 2. Die Vergleichsperson wird die „Normperson“ (Maßmensch). Die Normperson könnte zB die Repräsentantin der herrschen Struktur oder Organisationskultur sein (Referenz auf Fredman p. 98). Die Normperson verstärkt zugrunde liegende Ungleichheitsstrukturen. 3. Die Schwierigkeit, eine Vergleichsperson zu finden (zB Schwangerschaft). Eine Vergleichsperson wird in der Literatur nicht unbedingt für notwendig erachtet: Diskriminierung sei eine soziale Praxis, Mitglieder von Merkmalsgruppen seien aufgrund spezifischer Zuschreibungen diskriminiert, daher seien auch Vergleiche nicht unbedingt erforderlich (zit. Bamforth). Bell argumentiert, dass eine direkte Diskriminierung häufig ohne Vergleich evident ist. BUTLER, Judith (2000): Appearances Aside, California Law Review 88, 55-63 Butler draws a distinction between a concept of identity which is separable from appearances and one which is not. She thinks anti-discrimination law tries mistakenly to work with both of these ideas at once. She thinks Post’s (Post 2000) sociological approach puts appearance as central to personhood, whereas the dominant approach he criticises assumes that there is a transcendent self, beyond appearance and also that there is an ontological status that preexists any social status. (Butler p. 56) Judges have a choice to endorse this idea of the essential worth of a person (that pertains to persons as such) – “a Kantian soul with deontological value” - , or to look at technical skill “an instrumental capacity, at which point the person is understood as an analogical relation to a set of functions”. (Butler pp. 56 – 57) Butler points out that the functionalist approach is still tied up with appearances as the skills are judged and observable. (Butler p. 57) Both deny persons as social beings. (Butler p. 58) She says that Post wants “...to consider instead the way in which antidiscrimination law ought to presuppose the person not only as one who is, by definition, engaged in a set of social practices, but one who might be said to be a social practice, one whose ontology is that of an ongoing and revisable social practice or set of social practices.” (Butler p. 58) So there is no person prior to engaging in social practices. Butler then goes on to question whether Post’s view of gender and gender stereotypes and discrimination is too broad, and all encompassing. (Butler pp. 60 – 61) Is gender coextensive with its stereotype? ‘Unclear’ says Butler at p. 61. ETC Graz 30 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Butler then goes on to question how law can abstract a person away from their characteristics such as gender and ‘race’ – if a person is constituted by these social practices. (Butler p. 61) Butler thinks Post’s description of social reality is too conservative and actually reinforces stereotypes even while asking the law to challenge them. (Butler p. 62) Butler discusses assessing someone’s suitability for a job: “...it is not a matter of blinding myself to how the person appears, but, rather, deciding what ought to count about that person for the job in question from within the observational realm in which that person appears ... Thus, it is not a question of blinding oneself to how a person appears, but a question instead of how the way in which a person appears blinds one to the worth and capability of the person.” (Butler p. 63) BURRI Susanne, SCHIEK Dagmar (Hg.) (2009): Multiple Discrimination in EU Law: Opportunities for legal responses to intersectional gender discrimination? European Network of Legal Experts in the Field of Gender Equality, European Commission, Directorate-General for Employment, Social Affairs and Equal Opportunities, Unit EMPL/G/2, Theme - Equality, Action against Discrimination: Legal Questions, July 2009, vgl: http://ec.europa.eu/social/BlobServlet?docId=3808&langId=en This paper is a strong summary of the current state of affairs in the EU in acting on ‘multiple discrimination’ (which, as they define it, includes ‘intersectional discrimination’). Burri and Schiek analyze ‘multiple discrimination’ first and foremost as a feminist issue. That is, they are interested in ‘multiple discrimination’ primarily in terms of how it affects women. Statistically this may very well account for the majority of intersectional discrimination. However, there is also no obvious reason why this cannot apply to other intersectional “hotspots”. They point out that “intersectionality” is used to capture the thoroughly blended nature of discrimination when it is due to more than one ground and these grounds cannot be separated: “‘Intersectional’ discrimination would refer to such discrimination against women where the influence of various grounds cannot be disentangled, e.g. discrimination through denying ethnic minority women or women with disabilities the right to bear children. Those using the term ‘intersectional disadvantage’ often indicate a wish to move beyond intersectionality (Hunter & Simone de 2009).” (Burri and Schiek p. 3) The contrast is “compound” or “additive” discrimination where the grounds are separable. (Burri and Schiek p. 3) ETC Graz 31 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. They believe “multiple discrimination” is the overarching term and use it themselves due to it having already gained wide acceptance in UN and EU documents. (Burri and Schiek pp. 3 – 4) “Intersectional discrimination” means both more severe and also more specific (Burri and Schiek p. 4) – that is, more than one ground and to a smaller group of people. “Intersectionality” was originally used in legal and political discussions (Burri and Schiek pp. 4 -5). It has since been adapted to other purposes, including being caught up in controversy regarding identity politics. It remains controversial. The EU law in particular is a problem for intersectional analysis, as the hierarchy of grounds issue is especially prevalent here. (Burri and Schiek p. 5) They identify two sources of problems that EU law has dealing with multiple discrimination (so that includes intersectional discrimination). First, there are problems based on the fact that it is basically transplanted UK (and Dutch) law, conceptually speaking. (Burri and Schiek p. 6) Burri and Schiek argue that the non-systematic nature of common law is a likely source of difficulty for the EU here. (Burri and Schiek p. 6) Second, there are problems stemming from the competing conceptual theories underlying EU law (a result of its development): “The values informing these layers include enhancing transnational competition between individuals, supporting individual mobility and engendering European employment markets, protecting against social exclusion, furthering group identities and numerous others. Contradictory values will sometimes lead to clashes of norms within the field. The problem of establishing hierarchies at the expense of gender equality and in favour of racial and other equalities could, for example, be traced to conflicts between a more socio-economic and a more human rights based approach to equality law (Nousiainen 2009).” (Burri and Schiek p. 7) So far the ECJ has not really dealt with discrimination cases as cases of multiple/intersectional discrimination as such. (Burri and Schiek pp. 7 - 8 including case names) In these cases discrimination was considered without (explicit) reference to gender and the possibility/probability that this dimension contributed to the discrimination in question. The only case where there was a rather weak attempt made at this being Lindorfer. “Multiple discrimination” is not used in legally binding provisions, but is used in European Community’s non-discrimination policy and some directives. (Burri and Schiek p. 9) Proposed and recent amendments (Burri and Schiek pp. 9 – 10) seem to contain some problems: intersection of gender and ‘race’ omitted and discrimination within employment not considered. (Burri and Schiek pp. 10 – 11) There are some concerns that moving to a multiple discrimination framework will actually diminish the acknowledgement of gender-based discrimination. (Burri and Schiek p. 11) But ETC Graz 32 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. some predictions have also suggested the opposite: that this will enhance understanding and recognition of gender based discrimination. (Burri and Schiek p. 12) The discussion of cases put forward to demonstrate multiple discrimination shows that some could have been dealt with on only one ground and with others there was a choice about which combination of grounds was chosen. (Burri and Schiek p. 14) In the UK case of Bahl v Law Society [2003] I.R.L.R. 640; [2004] I.R.L.R. 799 the court refused to discuss intersectional discrimination. (p 15) Instead, both forms of discrimination had to be proved independently. This greatly reduced the number of available comparators and made the claim very difficult to maintain. Burri and Schiek suggest either using a fictional comparator or that the claimant should have been allowed to use mixed statistics (“outlining the combined relationship of age and gender”) or else the “non-statistical approach to indirect discrimination which is provided for by the EU Directives on non-discrimination”. (Burri and Schiek p. 16) In regard to national legislation, multiple discrimination is not always explicitly acknowledged. It may, however, be implicitly acknowledged, although Burri and Schiek still see a number of barriers to the law recognising/acting on multiple discrimination. (Burri and Schiek p. 18) Bahl is cited as prime example of the failure of the comparator approach, which is called “the most difficult barrier to overcome”. (Burri and Schiek p. 18) There are two grounds, so there are two comparators needed – one for each ground. The comparator approach was arguably imported into domestic systems in continental Europe from UK via Community legislation. Another big problem is that different grounds have different applicable legislation and so, for example, different standards of proof. (Burri and Schiek pp. 18 – 19) Two big reasons to acknowledge multiple discrimination: “First, there are cases where the discrimination is such that it is only experienced by persons who are ‘at the intersection’ of two grounds. For example, only women (not men) with disabilities or from specific ethnic groups are subjected to involuntary abortions. Or, to give another example, gender stereotypes about attractiveness and age intersect, which results in specific detriments for older women on the labour market. Some legal orders have difficulties acknowledging this kind of intersectional discrimination at all because the concept of multiple discrimination is alien to them (Ireland, UK). In many legal orders it is difficult to establish a case of intersectional discrimination, which is why a number of experts raise the problem of proof. Second discrimination on more than one ground has a stronger effect of exclusion than discrimination on only one ground. For example, a woman who is bullied away from her workplace on grounds of ‘race’ and ethnicity will also suffer intersectional discrimination in finding a new occupation. Accordingly, as many experts also stressed, multiple ETC Graz 33 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. discrimination can be considered as causing more harm and should attract higher damages or more severe other consequences.” (Burri and Schiek p. 20) The UK is an example of a country that needs community legislation. (Burri and Schiek p. 21) “The UK and Irish experts make a convincing case that, within the specific legal tradition of their countries, multiple discrimination cases are either not acknowledged or not sanctioned adequately. The UK expert recommends the explicit inclusion of multiple discrimination in the concept of non-discrimination in Community law. The Irish expert requests clarification that discrimination on two or more compound grounds can be investigated and proven together. For these legal traditions, a positive obligation on Member States to make sure that the problem is tackled is seen as necessary.” (Burri and Schiek p. 22 footnote omitted) The definition of ‘multiple discrimination ’is helpful, particularly for countries such as the UK. (Burri and Schiek pp. 22 – 23) Part II Report on Austrian situation – Burri and Schiek pp. 27 - 28 • Multiple discrimination is explicitly prohibited, but no definition is given. (Burri and Schiek p. 27) • It is taken into account for compensation. (Burri and Schiek p. 27) • An illustration is given. This also shows that discrimination on more than one ground cannot give rise to cumulative claims for compensation. (Burri and Schiek p. 27) • No court case law yet, but one hearing by the Equal Treatment Commission (which cannot impose sanctions). Grounds of sexual harassment and ethnic origin were addressed separately – grounds from different legal provisions Para 6(1)1 and Para 21(1)1 of the Equal Treatment Act respectively. (Burri and Schiek p. 27) • Most interesting point is that Commission stated that sexism and racism often appears combined (so they acknowledged intersectional discrimination). However, not much more was said about it. (Burri and Schiek p. 28) Report on United Kingdom – Burri and Schiek pp. 125 - 127 “Multiple discrimination” not used in any legislation and the phenomenon is not addressed. (Burri and Schiek p. 125) Bahl v Law Society (Bahl v Law Society [2003] I.R.L.R. 640 and [2004]I.R.L.R. 799). The Employment Tribunal originally found that Dr Bahl had been discriminated against as a black woman (so intersectional), but this was overturned by the Employment Appeal Tribunal, and the Court of Appeal rejected Bahl’s appeal. Elias J ruled that the tribunal erred ETC Graz 34 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. in law ‘in failing to distinguish between the elements of alleged ‘race’ and sex discrimination’. The court ruled that the tribunal had failed: ‘to identify what evidence goes to support a finding of ‘race’ discrimination and what evidence goes to support a finding of sex discrimination. It would be surprising if the evidence for each form of discrimination was the same (D) In our judgment, it was necessary for the [employment tribunal] to find the primary facts in relation to each type of discrimination against each alleged discriminator and then to explain why it was making the inference which it did in favour of Dr. Bahl on whom lay the burden of proving her case.’ (Burri and Schiek p. 125) This means that under English law, “Dr Bahl would have had to make separate claims under the Race Relations Act 1976 by reference to the treatment of real or hypothetical white women, and under the Sex Discrimination Act 1975 by reference to Black men. If the discriminatory treatment which she alleged was intersectional, that is, specifically connected with her identity as a Black woman, the RRA and SDA claims could each readily be defeated by evidence relating to the employer’s non-discriminatory treatment of Black men and white women respectively.” (Burri and Schiek p. 125) So, in English law, claimants must find single grounds of discrimination and no intersectional, combined claims look possible. (Burri and Schiek p. 126) The comparator – whether real or hypothetical - remains a major problem . (Burri and Schiek p. 126) BURRI, Susanne (2011): Promises of an Intersectional Approach in Practice? The Dutch Equal Treatment Commission’s Case Law, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union Non-Discrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate, 97-110. Die niederländische Equal Treatment Commission (ETC) beschäftigt sich seit 1994 mit Diskriminierungsfällen und hat seitdem die EU-Vorgaben übernommen, ohne spezifische nationale Features einzuführen. Auch das maßgebliche Gesetz (Dutch Equal Treatment Act) folgt in seiner Struktur den EU Vorgaben. Die ETC versucht bei jeder Möglichkeit eine intersektionale Herangehensweise zu wählen. Keine der rechtlichen Grundlagen erwähnt Mehrfachdiskriminierung explizit. Bevor Burri auf die Fälle eingeht, erläutert sie noch einige Spezifitäten des niederländischen Gesetzes. (Burri S. 101 f.) Sie diskutiert drei Fälle, die Intersektionen beinhalten. Seit 1994 hat die ETC nur ein Mal explizit von Intersektion gesprochen, nämlich in der Entscheidung 2007-43, im Fall eines iranischen Mannes, der Diskriminierung auf Grund von Religion und „Rasse“ vorbrachte. Die ETC verband beide Gründe, da es sich um eine ETC Graz 35 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. simultane Interaktion beider Gründe handelte, die zu zusätzlicher Benachteiligung führte. Jedoch gab es im Endeffekt keine Hinweise auf Diskriminierung, da die ETC zum Resultat kam, dass einzig der Mangel an Arbeitserfahrung entscheidend für die Nichtanstellung war. (Burri S. 104) In der Entscheidung 2006-256 handelte es sich um eine Antragsstellerin, die Diskriminierung aufgrund von Behinderung und ethnischer Zugehörigkeit vorbrachte. Sie sah sich benachteiligt durch einen Einstufungstest im Betrieb, der statt schriftlich plötzlich mündlich (und nicht in Braille) durchgeführt wurde. Die Diskriminierung wurde festgestellt, weil mündliche Prüfungen für blinde Personen mit Migrationshintergrund schwerer zu bewerkstelligen seien als schriftliche. Dieser Fall ist ein klares Beispiel für intersektionale Diskriminierung. (Burri S. 104 f.) Neben diesen Fällen werden von Burri auch Fälle über compound discrimination diskutiert (Burri S. 106 ff.) Zusammenfassend stellt Burri fest, dass die ETC nur wenige Fälle intersektional behandelt und meist nur einen einzelnen Grund zur Betrachtung heranzieht. Jedoch gibt es Indizien, dass die ETC sich für Intersektionalität interessiert und weiter in diese Richtung arbeiten wird. (Burri S. 109 f.) CZECH, Philip, SALINGER Ulrike (Hsg.) (2011): Diskriminierung – Grundrechtsverletzung oder Kavaliersdelikt. Das Gleichbehandlungsrecht in der Praxis, Menschenrechte konkret, Band 3, Salzburg Silvia Ulrich bietet in ihrem umfangreichen Beitrag „Die unionsrechtlichen Grundlagen des Diskriminierungsschutzes seit dem Änderungsvertrag von Lissabon“ einen Abriss über die geltende EU-Rechtslage zum Nichtdiskriminierungsrecht, wobei insbesondere die Grundrechtecharta und deren Gleichheitsgarantien umfassend erörtert werden. Nach Darstellung des sekundärrechtlichen Diskriminierungsschutzes wird untersucht, ob die unionsrechtlichen Bestimmungen in Österreich ausreichend umgesetzt wurden. Kritisch wird die Entwicklung der Schadenersatzregelungen beleuchtet, die zu keiner Zeit ambitioniert in Richtung der vom europäischen Richtliniengeber geforderten „Abschreckung“ ausgestaltet wurden. Die Novelle 2011 ist, wie Ulrich folgert, nur als kleiner Teilschritt auf dem Weg zu einem effektiven Diskriminierungsschutz zu sehen – die Fragmentierung des Diskriminierungsschutzes bleibt fortbestehen. Als größtes Hindernis zu einem adäquaten Diskriminierungsschutz bleibt die Hierarchisierung zwischen den Diskriminierungsmotiven bestehen. Ulrich liefert einen wesentlichen Beitrag zum Verständnis und zur praktischen Anwendung von Primärrecht im Bereich des Gleichbehandlungsrechts. Die Gleichbehandlungsanwältinnen Birgit Gutschlhofer und Ulrike Salinger setzen sich mit dem Gleichbehandlungsrecht in der außergerichtlichen Praxis auseinander. Einer kurz gehaltenen Einführung zum geltenden österreichischen Gleichbehandlungsrecht folgt eine ETC Graz 36 Literature Review detaillierte Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Schilderung der Arbeit der Gleichbehandlungsanwaltschaft Gleichbehandlungskommission samt Schilderung plakativer Fälle, und die der wichtige Klarstellungen und Hilfe zur Beurteilung von Diskriminierungsfällen bieten. Geht es im ersten geschilderten Fall um eine Ungleichbehandlung aufgrund des Familiennamens durch ein Finanzamt hinsichtlich Gewährung der Familienbeihilfe und die Überprüfung der Umsetzung der von der Gleichbehandlungskommission empfohlenen Maßnahmen, behandeln Gutschlhofer und Salinger im zweiten Fall eine Altersdiskriminierung bei der Begründung eines Arbeitsverhältnisses. In einem weiteren Fall wird das Diskriminierungsverbot bei Assoziierung am Wohnungsmarkt besprochen. Im Fall der unterschiedlichen Tarife für Frauen und Männer bei öffentlichen Transportmitteln sprechen die Autorinnen grundsätzliche Fragen des Diskriminierungsschutzes an: Ist die Benachteiligung von Frauen beim Einkommen ein hinreichender Rechtfertigungsgrund für eine Ungleichbehandlung nach dem Alter? Fallen Begünstigungen im Sozialschutz unter die Ermächtigung zu positiven Maßnahmen nach dem Gleichbehandlungskommission Gleichbehandlungsgesetzes Gleichbehandlungsgesetz? liegt vor. kein rechtmäßiges Gutschlhofer und Salinger Nach Ziel Ansicht im geben der Sinne einen des äußerst brauchbaren Überblick über die Bandbreite praktischer Fälle und die Reichweite des außergerichtlichen Rechtsschutzes samt Argumentationsmustern für eine erfolgreiche Rechtsdurchsetzung. Im Beitrag von Thomas Majoros wird die in der Praxis höchstrelevante Frage des immateriellen Schadenersatzes bei Diskriminierung untersucht. RA Majoros diskutiert anhand einer umfangreichen Judikaturauswahl zu Belästigungsfällen die Probleme der Bemessung des immateriellen Schadenersatzes. In Hinblick auf die Vorgaben der EUAntidiskriminierungs-Richtlinien, nach denen die Entschädigungen wirksam, verhältnismäßig und abschreckend sein müssen, entwirft Majoros einen Kriterienkatalog, nach dem die Bemessung erfolgen sollte. Behindertengleichstellungsgesetzes Er führt aus, wie Dauer der dass die Diskriminierung, Regeln des Schwere des Verschuldens, Erheblichkeit der Beeinträchtigung oder Mehrfachdiskriminierung auch in Fällen, die unter die anderen Gleichbehandlungsgesetze fallen, anzuwenden sind. Zur geforderten Abschreckung sei es notwendig, dass die Entschädigung über den Ausgleich des erlittenen Schadens hinausgeht. Ein wesentlicher Parameter ist daher die wirtschaftliche Leistungsfähigkeit des Diskriminierenden, wobei dieser seine wirtschaftliche Leistungsfähigkeit zu belegen haben wird. Der Grad des Verschuldens ist nachvollziehbar ein weiteres Kriterium. Schließlich wird die Bemessung des ideellen Schadens auch auf die Folgen für das Opfer abzustellen haben. Insgesamt sollte die Höhe des Schadenersatzes im Verhältnis zu den im Gesetz genannten Mindestbeträgen stehen. Majoros gibt damit ein ETC Graz 37 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. konkretes Werkzeug zur Ermittlung und Begründung des zu begehrenden Anspruchs zur Hand. Anschließend befasst sich Petra Smutny mit der Bedeutung von Beweisfragen im Gleichbehandlungsrecht, da es als Ausnahme zu den allgemeinen zivilprozessualen Beweisregeln, Beweislasterleichterungen vorsieht. Anschaulich wird die Problematik aufgerollt und erörtert und auch aus europarechtlicher Sicht beleuchtet. Als größte Schwierigkeit in der Praxis sieht Smutny das Problem der Mehrzahl angebotener Motive, die alle eine gewisse Glaubwürdigkeit besitzen, aber kein ausschlaggebendes Motiv (allein) erkennbar ist. Dieses Problem hat insbesondere bei Mehrfachdiskriminierungen Auswirkungen, so kann dadurch eine Überschneidung von Motiven zur Ablehnung des Begehrens führen, weil kein verpöntes Motiv als ausschlaggebend erkannt wird. Smutnys Beitrag zeigt in ihrem Beitrag auf, welche Schwachstellen in den Vorbringen zu vermeiden sind, um die Erfolgsaussichten im Prozess zu maximieren. ETC Graz 38 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. CARLES; Isabelle, JUBANY-BAUCELLS, Olga (2010): GendeRace. The Use of Racial Antidiscrimination Laws. Gender and Citizenship in a Multicultural Context. Final Report, vgl.: http://genderace.ulb.ac.be/rapports/GENDERACE%20FINAL%20REPORT%20sent.pdf Executive summary Importantly, this report starts from an understanding of identity as having multiple aspects and of discrimination being complex. (GendeRace p. 7) “GendeRace advances the view that social relations based on gender and racialised identities or ethnicity influence the perception and use of antidiscrimination laws. Whilst both EU and national institutional frameworks may provide numerous responses through action and conflict resolution, the project demonstrates that multiplediscrimination based on racialised identities and gender remains inadequately addressed.” (GendeRace p. 7) “A clear message arises from our results - that better awareness of civil rights must be promoted and that existing resources for the making of complaints must be expanded, especially for women. The development of a legal definition and a specific methodology of multiple discrimination could allow an intersectional approach for dealing with claims/complaints. In addition, we identify a clear need for inclusion of a gender perspective within the treatment of discrimination cases and provision of specific assistance and services according to the needs of the claimant/complainant.” (GendeRace p. 7) Key Findings • Racialised discriminations are often gendered • Gendered differences exist around access to and use of resources • Cases of multiple discrimination are not identified and treated as such Recommendations To improve the treatment of multiple discrimination: At the European level • For explicit reference to be made to multiple discrimination as an especially vulnerable form of discrimination within the new European Directive. • For the development of an operational definition of multiple discrimination that meets the standards set out in the European Union’s ‘Charter of Fundamental Rights’, Article 21 ETC Graz 39 Literature Review • Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. For the inclusion of a clause allowing complainants to lodge a complaint on several grounds within the framework of a single legal proceeding At the national level • To implement a specific legal methodological framework incorporating sociological and socio-historical contexts • That civil society (trade unions, women’s ethnic minority and professional organisations) in cooperation with lawyers and experts develops litigation strategies and class action as a method to bring gendered and racialised discrimination to the fore • To involve legal experts in the development of case law so that the implementation of cases based on multiple discrimination may impact the legal framework • To implement awareness-raising and professional training on anti-discrimination laws for legal advisors and counsellors, paying special attention to cases of intersectional discrimination • To inform victims of the existence of multiple grounds of discrimination (GendeRace pp. 9-10) There is a need for standardised statistics on (multiple) discrimination: At the European level • The adoption of the same criteria and indices for data collection, data recording and public availability by national equality bodies. • The publication of cross sections of data on gender and other social categories by EU agencies addressing information on the situation of groups subject to discrimination At the national level • The adoption by organisations and institutions of common methods of collection at national and local level to allow a national overview • The introduction in registration systems of socio-demographic data on complainants to identify discriminated sub-groups. (GendeRace p. 11) Part 1: Setting the Scene Chapter 1: Rationale, Approach and Development Introduction Equality before the law and protection from discrimination is a human right. (GendeRace p. 15) “Currently we can identify a number of official documents and studies commissioned by the EC as well as further publications by researchers, lawyers, numerous NGOs and other academics in the field that show the progress that there has been in this field in ETC Graz 40 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. the last decade. It is particularly since the year 2000, that the European Union has worked towards the development of a new legal framework for equality, which started before then with the European Community law prohibition on discrimination based on sex and nationality. With the adoption of the Article 13 of the Amsterdam Treaty, the EU has enlarged its competence in the field of antidiscrimination. Based on this, the EU adopted two new directives in that year, which broadened the scope of prohibited discrimination by adding ‘race’ and ethnic origin, religion and belief, disability, sexual orientation and age to sex and nationality. Recently, further efforts have been made to extend discrimination on the grounds of sex: two new directives have been adopted, one on gender equality in employment, the other on occupation and provision of goods and services. And, in 2006 a Recast Directive (Directive 2006/54/EC) was adopted to bring together a number of Directives in the Gender discrimination field”. (GendeRace p. 15 – footnote omitted) The report uses ethnic minority women as an effective example of the intersectional experience. But it does acknowledge other kinds of intersectionality. (GendeRace pp. 15-16) The report notes that there are not sufficient legal instruments and policies in place to protect/assist vulnerable groups even though their vulnerability and disadvantage has been acknowledged. (GendeRace p. 16) “Despite the Community’s statement within the Race Directive of its intention to eliminate inequalities and promote equality between women and men, EU policies and legal framework against discrimination are fragmented, with grounds of ‘race’ and gender addressed by separate directives and programmes. Consequently, the ground of sex as a ground for discrimination is excluded from the 2000 antidiscrimination directives and from the programme to combat discrimination. Similarly, the question of multiple discrimination is insufficiently addressed at the national level. Whilst the Commission does oblige member states to provide an evaluation of the impact of the implementation on women in its report on the implementation of the Directive 2000/43/EC, none have done so at the time of publication.” (GendeRace p. 17 – footnotes omitted) For the GendeRace project, ‘intersectionality’ is defined as “U the articulation of multiple discriminations focusing on the question of gender and racialised identities or ethnicity at different levels of the process of discrimination.” (GendeRace p. 17) “To this aim, at the outset we advance the view that social relations based on gender and racialised identities influence the perception and use of antidiscrimination laws. We postulate that men and women experience different kinds of discrimination, reacting in different ways to the phenomenon and this is often connected to other discriminatory experiences in their daily lives, which may be related to structural and institutional ETC Graz 41 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. discrimination. The institutional framework provides different responses according to gender, in terms of action and conflict resolution. However, this does not imply that multiple discrimination based on racialised identities and gender is adequately addressed.” (GendeRace p. 17) The report notes the single-ground focus of anti-discrimination law (and also institutions) and that this has a bad effect on people suffering from intersectional discrimination – it is more difficult to claim under the law and also makes some of the discrimination invisible. (GendeRace p. 18) 1.2 Specific Objectives The project’s objectives are: • “To deepen understanding of the impact of gender on the experience of discrimination based on racialised identities or ethnic origin; • To improve the knowledge of the combined effects of racism and gender discrimination in order to reveal the various forms of specific discrimination experienced by women; • To progress understanding of the impact of gender on the treatment of complaints; • To improve knowledge of the motivations underlying the use of the law and of the complainants expectations; • To test key theories concerning the effects of a ground-specific approach to antidiscrimination legislation on the treatment of multiple discrimination based on racialised identities or ethnic origin and that of gender; • To develop practical tools to assess the effectiveness of policy and practice in the field of antidiscrimination to take into account the intersectional dimension of discrimination.” (GendeRace p. 18) 1.3 Methodological Approach and Framework The report is aware of three different terms being used to categorise complex discrimination – multiple, additive and intersectional – and gives definitions for all three: “Multiple discrimination occurs when an individual experiences discrimination on several grounds. We understand compound or additive discrimination as that of discrimination occurring on more than one ground in the same instance with discrimination on the one ground adding to the discrimination on the other ground to create an added burden. Intersectional discrimination occurs when two or more grounds of discrimination interact concurrently. However for the latter, the grounds are inseparable and the discrimination taking place cannot be captured wholly by examining discrimination solely on one ground.” (GendeRace p. 19) ETC Graz 42 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. 1.4 Fieldwork Illustrations of Multiple Discrimination The report notes that in cases of possible multiple discrimination, courts usually deal with each ground separately. So courts ask: “Is there ‘race’ discrimination?” Yes/No. And then “Is there sex discrimination?” Yes/No, rather than “Is there sex-race discrimination?” The problem is that it can be very difficult to prove a single ground in cases of multiple/intersectional discrimination. They provide two illustrations here that may be useful: “For example, a restaurant may refuse to employ a black woman as a waitress. The woman claims that this is discrimination precisely because she is a woman AND because she is black, and this may deemed as multiple discrimination on grounds of gender and ‘race’. If the court looks at the grounds of gender and ‘race’ separately, it will not find discrimination. The restaurant employs both men and women as waiters, so it is not treating women less favourably than men. It also employs black men and thus does not treat black people less favourably. Only if the two grounds are taken together will the discrimination be identified. So in this case the black woman would only have a chance of success if she could claim discrimination on a combination of grounds. Another clear example would be a driving school which refuses to employ older women: there would be no gender or age discrimination because they employ both men and women and older men as driving instructors. But an older female applicant is turned down because of the combination of age and gender. If she cannot claim discrimination on the combined grounds, she will have no remedy in law.” (GendeRace p. 20) Two French cases A French boxer was refused entry to a flight even though he had his paperwork in order. The paperwork situation was a little unusual, involving an emergency passport etc, but it does seem that he should have been let on the flight and so the refusal certainly raised the question of racial discrimination. It seems that the airline employed profiling and thought that as the boxer was of a male of North African origin, that he was a safety risk (potential terrorist). (GendeRace p. 21) The other case relates to a woman refused entry to a training course due to wearing a headscarf. The course was run by a private organization which prohibited all visible religious symbols. “This demonstrated refusal or conditional discrimination in providing access to goods or services on the grounds of religion.” (GendeRace p. 21) “In France, the prohibition of religious symbolism is applicable only to schoolchildren or students in secondary schools in compliance with the principle of non-discrimination. In addition, civil servants are required to maintain complete neutrality. The HALDE had to ETC Graz 43 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. repeat in several deliberations that these are the only limits set out by the law under the fundamental principle of religious freedom, which historically guarantees the principle of separation between Church and State. However, this case was only dealt with by the HALDE as discrimination based on religion. The gender aspect was overlooked while it could have been interpreted as a form of multiple discrimination based on both religion and gender.” (GendeRace p. 22) Two cases in Spain ‘La Nena’: A Roma woman was refused access to a widow’s pension although she was married for almost 40 years and had never worked outside the home. The marriage was a traditional Roma ceremony and not entered in the public record. Her claim was refused until it made it to the European Court of Human Rights. It was dealt with as racial discrimination but her legal advisors described it as multiple discrimination as it was crucial that she was not only Roma but also that she was a woman. (GendeRace p. 22) The Beauty Solomon case: A woman with Spanish residency and of Nigerian origin was physically and verbally attacked by Majorcan police officers. Her complaints were not acted upon so the case is now going to the European Court of Human Rights as a case of specifically multiple discrimination – the first ECHR case to be so defined. (GendeRace p. 23) A German case A woman was denied access to training as she wore a headscarf. She was told that no women wearing a headscarf would be employed, so there was no point her doing the training. (It was teacher training and no headscarves are allowed in schools – some states at least have an explicit ban.) (GendeRace p. 23) Two cases in Bulgaria A Roma woman and business owner was accosted by a parking official: “The officer insulted her based on her ethnic origin and as a conclusion ‘recommended’ that she ‘go back to her horse and cart!’ According to the victim, the insults arose not only by the fact that she was a Roma woman but also by the fact that her car was expensive. This stirred envy in the officer as many stereotypes depict Roma as lazy and poor. According to the victim, the officer was provoked by the fact that a Roma woman appeared to have achieved good social status, a view most insulting for the complainant.” (GendeRace p. 24) In another case a schoolteacher, a man, complained about being dismissed. He had worked in the school for thirty years (but was still some years away from retirement). His claim is that ETC Graz 44 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. he was dismissed for being an older man. For one thing, he claims the perception is that men can find a job more easily. And for another, his age meant that he did not have children at home to support. His claim of unequal treatment is based on gender. (GendeRace p. 25) Two cases in the UK A black woman bullied by a white male colleague and also students following the example of the man: “For example, when he asked her where she was from and she told him, he replied: ‘so, you are one of those people who commit fraud’. She was asked why she couldn’t go back to her own country (although she has the same nationality as him); remarks were made that people with plaited hair do not wash their hair. And, one of the students said: ‘I used to have a childminder like you’. The male colleague did treat black male colleagues in a different way and did not make the same remarks to them. This is clearly a case of intersectional discrimination/harassment based on the combination of ‘race’ and gender, taking place because she was a black woman. The colleague and the students would not have treated a white female colleague or a black male colleague or a white male colleague in the same way.” (GendeRace p. 25) In the second case an African woman working in a restaurant was treated badly by the white male general manager when she became pregnant and so needed more rest and to avoid heavy lifting (which was in line with the company’s stated policy of the appropriate treatment of pregnant women). She was not paid for absences resulting from ante-natal appointments (even though this was required by law) and also had her shifts reduced without consultation. She then found out a white waitress was also pregnant and had been given better conditions (the conditions that that the African woman had asked for). After finding out about this, the African woman was finally convinced that her treatment was a case of discrimination. It also seems to be intersectional discrimination as the white male manager got along well with the white women and the black men. (GendeRace p. 26) Two cases of multiple discrimination in Sweden A woman was pushed and harassed by a female bus driver for wearing a veil. It was an unprovoked racial attack. The authors note that it was also really intersectional, but it is only being dealt with as a racial complaint. (GendeRace p. 26) The second example is of a Finnish Roma woman. She dressed traditionally and notes that discrimination occurred every day – for example, she was followed in shops and told that she would be unable to get a job. The specific incident happened when she was at a conference in a hotel and the hotel staff questioned her use of the in-house coffee machine. She showed that she had keys to the room etc but was still looked at with suspicion. (GendeRace p. 26) ETC Graz 45 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Chapter 2 National Contexts and common trends of the EU framework 2.2 The European social fabric in relation to racism and gender discrimination There are various protected minorities in Europe. The group that suffers the most consistent discrimination is the Roma. (GendeRace p. 33) Immigrants in general seem to be the most vulnerable to discrimination. And the status as ‘immigrant’ can still apply in terms of the perception in the general population even when the people have citizenship. (GendeRace p. 33) The authors give extra attention to the position of immigrants in some specific countries: France, Germany, United Kingdom, Spain and Sweden. (GendeRace pp. 34-36) Kurzzusammenfassung deutsch Genderace ist ein Programm, das sich mit „Gender and citizenship in a multicultural context“ beschäftigt. Das Projekt wurde von 2008-2010 im 7. Rahmenprogramm der EU abgewickelt und im März 2009 auf der Konferenz in Leeds vorgestellt. Das Projektvolumen beläuft sich auf knapp eine Million Euro. In fünf Ländern (UK, Frankreich, Deutschland, Schweden und Bulgarien) wurden die Intersektionen zwischen Gender und „Race“ untersucht, es wurde der Umgang mit Intersektionalität besprochen und auch Interviews durchgeführt. Es wurden 914 Fälle und 120 in-depth Interviews mit betroffenen Männern und Frauen analysiert. Weiters wurden 60 Interviews mit Stakeholdern, NGOs und Sozialpartnern geführt. Im Final Report finden sich die im Projekt verwendeten Definitionen zu Discrimination, Intersectionality etc. (Carles S. 31) Die Studie beschäftigt sich eingehend mit dem Bericht „Bekämpfung von Mehrfachdiskriminierung“ der Europäischen Kommission, analysiert das Buch von Schiek und Chege, sowie auch jenes von Grabham. Außerdem wird Sandra Fredman ausführlich zitiert: “Finally, other US courts recognised that discrimination against black women can exist even in the absence of discrimination against black men or white women. This led to the arguments that multiple discrimination should be restricted to a combination of only two of the grounds. To date the impact of the other grounds for discrimination have been ignored. The result is both artificial and paradoxical. The more a person differs from the norm, the more likely is she to experience multiple discrimination, the less likely is she to gain protection.” (Fredman, zitiert in Carles S. 104) Im fünften Kapitel werden die Ergebnisse der Interviews zusammengefasst. In den fünf Ländern wurden folgende (übereinstimmende) Erkenntnisse gemacht: - Frauen sind viel öfter Opfer von rassistischer oder sexueller Belästigung - Mehrfachdiskriminierung wird nur selten von den Opfern als solche identifiziert ETC Graz 46 Literature Review - Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Diskriminierung innerhalb einer Gruppe wird nur sehr selten als eine solche wahrgenommen. - Männer werden vermehrt in Freizeitbereichen diskriminiert (Bars, Nachtklubs und Restaurants). - Es gibt gemeinsame geschlechtsbezogene Stereotypen – Männer die aus einer ethnischen Minderheitengruppierung stammen werden oft als sexistisch und aggressiv wahrgenommen, während Frauen aus diesen Gruppen als passiv und devot wahrgenommen werden. (Carles S. 123) COLLINS, Hugh (2003): Discrimination, Equality and Social Inclusion. The Modern Law Review 66, pp. 16 – 43, vgl.: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1097547 Anti-discrimination laws cannot be reduced to equal treatment. (Collins p. 16) Rather, there are three deviations from a principle of equal treatment: 1) Different treatment. The example of pregnant women is given. They are not to be treated as men. 2) Equal treatment is not permitted when it causes indirect discrimination or has “disparate impact” 3) Preferential treatment of certain groups is permitted (Collins pp. 16 – 17) Collins notes that substantive equality is often introduced here to account for these derivations. The problem then becomes “Uto restrain or confine the force of a substantive conception of equality.” This is needed so that it does not counteract the principle of equal treatment. (Collins p. 17) Europe uses a “proportionality” test to balance these two visions of equality, but this leaves the tension in tact: “Wherever the line is drawn, a decision can always be criticized as displaying either a slavish adherence to the equal treatment principle or a dangerous sacrifice of the principle. The tension remains between, on the one hand, an aim of ensuring equal treatment for all citizens regardless of certain characteristics such as sex and ‘race’, and on the other hand, an aim of achieving a more equal distribution of welfare or resources among all citizens that may require in some instances different treatment on the grounds of those same characteristics.” (Collins p. 18) Collins now turns to discuss the different approaches that can be taken to resolving this tension. (Collins p. 18ff) ETC Graz 47 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. One approach is to define substantive equality narrowly so that it hardly ever clashes with equal treatment. Collins thinks “equality of opportunity” provides an example of this. However, insofar as it has any content in regard to distributive justice, it must still come into conflict with procedural justice, and the same tension arises. (Collins pp. 18 – 19) A second approach would be to limit the equal treatment principle so that there was hardly ever a clash: “For example, it might be proposed that equal treatment should be rigorously observed in hiring decisions, but with respect to training and other' outreach' measures, equal treatment should be sacrificed in the pursuit of a substantive goal such as fair equality of opportunity.” (Collins p. 19) However, the law allows for equal treatment across the board and on what ground could this be altered? (Collins p. 19) A third approach removes “equal treatment” by redefining it as “equal worth”, “equal respect” or “treatment as an equal” which all allow for different treatment as long as this does not involve “disrespect of any group”. Collins is concerned, however, about abandoning equal treatment altogether and notes that the current state of law would not allow this. (Collins pp. 19-20) The final approach Collins considers is that of reducing the equal treatment to an instrumental rule: “This interpretation identifies a distributive goal as the dominant aim of the legislation, and regards equal treatment as a useful guide to how the aim of the law should be implemented, though whenever the substantive goal requires different treatment, the principle of equal treatment should be ignored.” (Collins p. 20) Again, Collins notes that the current anti-discrimination laws take equal treatment to be a dominant principle. (Collins p. 20) From the above approaches Collins concludes: 1) An account of the aims of anti-discrimination law must give an important role to the equal treatment principle 2) The distributive aim of the legislation explains those cases when different treatment is required 3) An additional principle “equal respect”/”equal worth” should be added to supplement the equal treatment principle 4) The distributive aim of the legislation will, at times, clash with the principle of equal treatment 5) “The final lesson to be drawn is that it may be possible to define a distributive goal that entails the use of equal treatment as its operational principle, but which also sets limits to its operation by reference to the distributive goal. The two main difficulties ETC Graz 48 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. confronting such an interpretation of the aims of the anti-discrimination legislation are to define an appropriate distributive goal and to explain why this goal requires considerable weight to be attached to the equal treatment principle.” (Collins p. 20) Collins thinks that more explicit discussion about the concept of equality may help resolve the situation. (Collins p. 21) He now turns to examine social inclusion. Social Inclusion Collins chooses the term “social inclusion“ partly to avoid sounding too idealistic and strongly socialist. (Collins p. 22) He states that social inclusion is an aim or principle of justice that is often mistaken for an egalitarian notion of distributive justice. The difference is that social inclusion “Udoes not seek the same or broadly equivalent outcomes for citizens. It concentrates its attention not on relative disadvantage of particular groups in society, but rather on the absolute disadvantage of particular groups in society. The objective is not some notion of equality of welfare, but one of securing a minimum level of welfare for every citizen.” (Collins p. 22) Social inclusion is also not equivalent to “equality of resources” for two reasons: The first is that it is more targeted (so this is the same reason given above for why social inclusion is not equivalent to distributive justice in general). It only aims to redistribute resources to particular and particularly disadvantaged groups. The second difference, which Collins thinks is crucial, is that social inclusion is about outcomes: “It is not enough under the aim of social inclusion to give a bigger share of resources or opportunities to disadvantaged groups, and leave them to choose whether to take up the possibilities they provide. Social inclusion is committed to the achievement of outcomes, not just life-chances.” (Collins p. 23) The outcome sought “Uis to improve the welfare of disadvantaged groups” and this is understood broadly to mean “well-being” which includes goods (e.g. food) as well as opportunities (education, work). (Collins p. 23) Collins claims that this vision of welfare is both subjectivist and objectivist. (Collins p. 23) Social inclusion demands that governments provide not just material goods, then, but nonmaterial opportunities and this requires: “Ufirst, that the social organization of these activities permits everyone to enter them without insurmountable barriers, and secondly, that each person enjoys the ability to choose between a range of possible goals in relation to these activities.” (Collins p. 24) The aim of social inclusion is, in fact, social cohesion. It is a theory about creating harmony and integration in society. (Collins p. 24) ETC Graz 49 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Social inclusion has paternalistic, coercive aspects. Here Collins uses employment as an example, where both incentives to work and disincentives not to work are applied: “Moreover, it is insisted that nearly everyone can work, provided that individuals receive appropriate training and education, and that employers dismantle unnecessary exclusionary rules. This coercive element distinguishes the principle of social inclusion from even the broadest versions of equality of opportunity, which leave individuals with the freedom and the responsibility to make their own life-choices, including indolence.” (Collins p. 25) Again, social inclusion’s emphasis on the role that non-material goods play in well-being distinguishes it from egalitarian welfares’ policies. Social inclusion does not allow for a job to be traded for the same money paid out in welfare payments, as a job is part of well-being in ways that cannot be reduced to money. (Collins p. 25) Collins then briefly outlines the historical context for social inclusion, claiming it arose in late 20th century Western in response to the existence of a problematic, disenfranchised element existing in welfare societies. (Collins pp. 25 – 26) Collins identifies four pillars of anti-discrimination laws from the perspective of social inclusion: “Uhow the social problem to be addressed by anti-discrimination laws is conceived within the policy of social inclusion; how social inclusion justifies deviation from the equal treatment principle; the methods of proof of unlawful discrimination; and the extent of the requirement for positive discrimination in the pursuit of social inclusion. This analysis enables us to identify the extent to which a social inclusion justification may explain the aims and the content of the current law, though it also provides a critical perspective on possible inadequacies in the legislation.” (Collins p. 26) Structural disadvantage Anti-discrimination laws address not just direct discrimination (equal treatment) but also structural or systemic disadvantage for protected groups. “The notion of structural disadvantage combines two elements: first, an appreciation that there are patterns of disadvantage or that there are groups that seem to be disproportionately and persistently in worse positions; and second, that there are certain permanent arrangements, practices, institutions and social structures that produce this outcome. The way in which we define the nature and sources of structural disadvantage provides a framework for the ambit of antidiscrimination laws.” (Collins p. 26) Collins then sets out three elements of the problem of structural disadvantage and discusses each in turn: 1) The composition of the disadvantaged groups ETC Graz 50 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. 2) The nature of their disadvantage 3) The nature of the structures that tend to produce that disadvantage (Collins p. 26) Disadvantaged groups Collins claims that equality justifications for anti-discrimination laws lack a determinate way to constitute groups for comparison. Social inclusion does a better job of this: “The question is whether the group is one that in practice has been disproportionately socially excluded compared to the population as a whole.” (Collins p. 27) “Notice as well that social inclusion is not interested in whether the group is classified by unalterable genetics, socially constructed qualities, or legally imposed characteristics, factors which are sometimes used to determine the scope of discrimination laws under equality justifications. Nor is it interested in whether the group is regarded with disrespect.” (Collins p. 28) Nature of disadvantage Again, Collins thinks that social inclusion does better than equality in picking out relevant disadvantages. (Collins p. 28) In particular, he thinks that understanding social inclusion as the underlying drive of anti-discrimination laws, helps make sense of the emphasis on employment and why it is the distribution of jobs that matters, rather than just the economic benefits of having a job – so, again, the idea is that the same money paid in welfare is not as good. (Collins pp. 28 – 29) Structures “Both formal and informal institutional arrangements of our society tend to maintain existing distributive patterns, even once direct discrimination is eliminated.” Here Collins cites women being primary care-givers to children as an arrangement that disadvantages them in the labour market. (Collins p. 39) Women are disadvantaged through the combination of the informal arrangement that they are primarily responsible for child-care, combined with the formal arrangements of employment. Collins notes that the law “Uquestions the validity of the institutional rules, though it leaves untouched and unquestioned the informal social norms.” (Collins p. 30) Collins notes here that the equality justification seems to cause problems as it means that the anti-discrimination laws rely on stereotypes in order to show structural, indirect discrimination: “Thus in Clymo v Wandsworth Borough Council, a rule against job sharing the post of librarian was held not to be discriminatory against women, because the claimant had had the choice to pay for full-time child-care. As soon as the court or tribunal denies or ETC Graz 51 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. rejects the social stereotype – in this instance women typically stay at home to take care of young children – the legal challenge to institutional discrimination begins to fall apart.” (Collins p. 30 - footnote omitted) “The ideal of equality respects the choices of individuals about how they should lead their lives, but says the law should insist upon equal respect for those choices. Respect for those choices means that the law should not question social norms in so far as they are conventions and patterns produced by the choice of individuals. Under this equality justification, the prohibition against institutional discrimination should concern only those rules that, though formally neutral, have in their application a disparate adverse impact on certain groups as a result of attributes of those groups which they have not chosen.” (Collins p. 31 – footnotes omitted) Social inclusion, however, is not neutral in regard to the chosen goals. “The social norms and conventions are themselves a target for discrimination laws, if they have the effect that the groups who make such choices are thereby excluding themselves from employment.” (Collins p. 31) Examining a rule against job sharing on the basis of social inclusion would reveal that parents of young children may need part time jobs for their well-being. A rule against jobsharing obstructs those who need part-time work from entering the labour market. In terms of social inclusion the law is discriminatory if it has an exclusionary effect. (Collins p. 31) “It is possible to detect such a change in the new test for indirect sex discrimination in employment. The amended Sex Discrimination Act 1975 section 1(2)(b) drops the former element that asked whether a disproportionate number of women cannot comply with the hiring rule, and asks merely whether the rule has a detrimental effect for a considerably larger population of women, thus avoiding the issue of choice and social convention.” (Collins p. 31 – footnotes omitted) Proving discrimination Viewing anti-discrimination law as based on an equality principle requires a comparative approach to proof. It is often impossible to find a man (or member of the relevant majority group) in similar circumstances, so a hypothetical comparator must be created. “This legal construction is often difficult to build, because a member of the majority or privileged group is unlikely to have experienced structural disadvantages in a similar way, so that it is hard to envisage how members of this groups could find themselves in sufficiently similar circumstances for a fair comparison to be made.” (Collins p. 32) Social inclusion, however, does not demand a comparator: “The policy of social inclusion asks for proof that the rule or practice tends to reinforce the exclusion of an individual member of an excluded group or most members of the ETC Graz 52 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. excluded group. For example, if the employer’s rule forbids part-time work, this rule reinforces the exclusion of any groups such as single parents that may require parttime jobs. Even if it is demonstrated that other groups are similarly or equally adversely affected by the rule, the fact that this particular excluded group is disadvantaged by the requirement is sufficient to provide a basis for a challenge to the rule.” (Collins p. 32) Collins notes that the comparator test, based on the equality justification, is the dominant approach to proof in anti-discrimination law. However, the exact notion of equality being used is often disputed. He identifies the statistical approach as the source of this dispute: “No doubt much of the difficulty here can be attributed to a combination of the lack of precise statistical information combined with the complexity of the test. This test requires a comparison between the ratios of the privileged group to the protected group in two statistical pools. The equal treatment principle tends to confine the pools for statistical comparison, whereas a substantive equality of results principle points to the relevance of a broadly composed pool of comparison, usually consisting of the labour market as a whole. In the case of a hiring condition such as a particular educational qualification, for instance, the focus of the equal treatment principle is on whether the condition disproportionately adversely affected a protected group within the set of job applicants. The relevant statistical comparison under this approach is the proportions between privileged group and disadvantaged group in the pool of job applicants compared to the proportions in the pool of those employed. From the perspective of equality of results, however, the relevant statistical pool should be defined at least as those available in the labour market who could satisfy all the requirements for the job apart from the disputed educational qualification. It is the proportions between privileged and disadvantaged groups who can and who cannot satisfy the condition that serves as the comparison for establishing indirect discrimination.” (Collins pp. 32 – 33 – footnotes omitted – some useful case citations in footnotes) Social inclusion supports selecting the broader pool of statistical comparison, but it “Ddoes not focus on the statistics for the labour market as a whole, unless the job concerned requires minimal skills, because its concern is with those who possess the skills to benefit from the job or those who could acquire them with training.” (Collins p. 33) Collins argues that thinking in terms of social inclusion may help understand two other problems of the comparative approach to proof. 1) The problem of interpreting statistical differences: “The test for discrimination in EC law is not one of statistical significance in a technical sense, but rather one that adopts a formula that there must be disadvantage to a ‘substantially higher proportion’ of the protected group. The puzzle posed by that test is why it detracts from the commitment to equality, which should require merely a ETC Graz 53 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. test of statistical significance. There may be pragmatic considerations at work hereD But an additional explanation D may be that the legislation implicitly acknowledges that its distributive aim has to be more focused on rules that have a considerable exclusionary effect, and has to refrain from assessments of the merits of every rule that produces results that deviate slightly from a normal distribution.” (Collins p. 33) 2) The problem for indirect discrimination claims of the exclusionary effect of a combination of rules. “For example, an employer may use two hiring conditions such as a formal educational qualification and a skill acquired through work experience. D The problem may arise that, although any one hiring condition may not create a substantial difference in the composition of the comparative pools, a combination of two or more may have a significant exclusionary effect. There is a danger that under the approach based on equality, an employer may be able to reject the inference of indirect discrimination by insisting that each hiring requirement should be viewed in isolation.” (Collins p. 34) Collins thinks that social inclusion explains why this method of analysis is unsatisfactory: “Social exclusion is often the product of a combination of factors, such as being a member of a minority group in a particular neighbourhood. A disadvantaged group is therefore often identified in theories of social exclusion by more than one criterion. The aim of social inclusion thus perhaps explains our intuition that the method of analysis that examines each hiring condition in isolation is unsatisfactory, because it does not appreciate the multi-faceted sources of disadvantage in many instances.” (Collins p. 34) Direct discrimination and a justification defence Using social inclusion, the direct comparative test is eliminated, but a justification defence needs to be introduced. At the moment, this is basically restricted to indirect discrimination, but Collins claims that it must apply to direct discrimination too. This is not possible at the moment because of the equal treatment principle which “Ucreates a strong presumption against the possibility of justifying intentional discrimination.” (Collins p. 34) Social inclusion, however, can “Utolerate a broader range of considerations, provided that the justifications are compatible with the aim of social inclusion.” (Collins p. 34) Collins discusses the Disability Discrimination Act 1995 as an example of a law that does not use the comparative approach and is based more on social inclusion than equality. The specific example is of a hiring rule that restricts employment based on passing a medical test, but the person with the disability cannot pass it because of the disability. “It is irrelevant that the hiring rule applies equally to person without a disability, and it is not necessary to ETC Graz 54 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. prove disparate impact. Once it is shown that the rule has excluded a disabled person, the question is not whether there was unequal treatment, but whether the rule is justified in the sense that the reason for the rule is both material to the circumstances of the particular case and substantial.” (Collins pp. 34 – 35 – footnotes omitted) This justification test is further refined in s5 (2), which creates a duty on the employer to make “reasonable adjustments” to those arrangements that put the disabled person at a disadvantage. It is, in short, a duty to treat disabled persons differently (so, again, not the equality principle). (Collins p. 35) What is considered to be a “reasonable adjustment” is guided by the statute and an elaborate Code of Practice. The problem for the tribunal is to balance the cost to the employer with the exclusionary effects of the hiring rules. (Collins p. 35) In James v Eastleigh Borough Council pensioners could swim for free at the pool, but the age for the pension was lower for women than men. On the basis of equality, this is a problem, but social inclusion may explain it. The group under consideration is pensioners as such – “Dthe excluded group can be defined by reference to the pattern of social exclusion – persons of pensionable age.” (Collins p. 36) The Judicial Committee, however, upheld the claim of sex discrimination, as the argument for equal treatment was compelling. Positive Action Equality of treatment finds positive action difficult to account for, and the tests of “strict scrutiny” and “proportionality” are quite difficult to meet. (Collins p. 36) If social inclusion is considered instead, then “...employers should be sensitive to difference and make reasonable adjustments, in order to enable members of excluded groups to overcome obstructions to their obtaining work suitable for their skills and capability. This duty requires employers to consider amongst many things how the workplace is organised, how jobs are structured, and how the skills and capabilities of the workers could be improved, with a view to the reduction of barriers to employment for excluded groups.” (Collins p. 37) Collins again cites the Disability Discrimination Act 1995 as an example of this approach. (Collins p. 37) Social inclusion does not demand quotas. (Collins p. 37) Can anti-discrimination laws be interpreted in terms of social inclusion and include this positive duty when appropriate, or do they forbid difference of treatment outright? Collins thinks it is possible (although he does go on later to discuss ways in which it is not an exact match): “In a claim for indirect discrimination, once the indirect discriminatory effect of a hiring rule is revealed by statistical evidence, the employer must justify the rule on business grounds to avoid a successful claim of discrimination. The justification standard ETC Graz 55 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. currently used in cases of indirect discrimination is under EC law a test of proportionalityD.” (Collins p. 37 – citation for this is Bilka-Kaufhaus GmbH v Weber von Hartz C-170/84 [1986] ECR 1607 ECJ; EC Directive 2000/78, Art 2(2)(b), 2002/73, new Art 2(2).) The way that this test has been applied in the UK, however, seems to have made it a little weaker. Hampson v Department of Education and Science [1989] ICR 179 CA: “Ua requirement to balance objectively the discriminatory effect of the rule against the reasonable needs of the party imposing the condition. This justification defence requires the employer to discover and reveal the potential costs of eliminating the hiring rule in rule in the same way that the duty of accommodation functions as an ‘information-forcing rule’. Then the court must balance those costs to the employer against the exclusionary impact of the rule.” (Collins pp. 37-38) The Hampson test “Uwas approved and described as an application for the EC test of proportionality by Lord Nicholls in Burry v Midland bank plc [199] ICR 859, HL 870, and by Sedley LJ in Allonby v Accrington and Rossendale College [2001] ICR 1189 CA 1200, though there seems to be a clear difference between a test of necessity and a mere balancing of interests.” (Collins footnote 73, p. 38) London Underground Ltd v Edwards (No 2) [1997] IRLR 157 EAT (affirmed [1999] ICR 494 CA) – the employer introduced a new shift-system, which resulted in a single parent resigning. The court held that London Underground could have “Umade arrangements which would not have been damaging to their business plans but which would have accommodated the reasonable demands of their employees.” (Cited Collins p. 38) Under the EC test of proportionality the key question “Uis often whether the employer’s rule is necessary in the sense no other rule with less adverse impact on the excluded group would satisfy the business needs of the employer. Arguments about justification in indirect discrimination claims amount to more than an individualized claim for adjustment, because the employer is required to justify the adverse impact of the rule on an excluded class, not merely on a particular job applicant.” (Collins p. 38) In the footnote Collins notes that this “Utest of proportionality is also being applied under the Human Rights Act 1998, eg Wilson v First Country Trust Ltd (No 2) [2001] EWCA Civ 633, [2001] 3 WLR 42 CA” (Footnote 78, Collins p. 38) In terms of current law not exactly expressing the social inclusion aim, Collins thinks that the “Ucentral difference concerns the potential width of justifications for indirectly discriminatory rules.” (Collins p. 38) This is because the aim of social inclusion would allow for justifications beyond business considerations, such as in Northern Ireland, having a rule to favour unemployed persons, would also indirectly discriminate against Protestants, but would go to assist the aim of including the Catholic community in employment. (Collins pp. 38-39) ETC Graz 56 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Courts do not always have broad discretion in these matters. Sometimes the legislation is too specific for that and here Collins cites the legislation relating to maternity and parental leave rights. Although, in this case, there is more discretion under the legislation dealing with time off for family emergencies, which, Collins thinks, “Ucan be regarded as a determination of the requirement of reasonable adjustment for parents, with their underlying goal being in part the reduction of social exclusion.” (Collins p. 39) Priority not equality Four features to seeing anti-discrimination law in terms of social inclusion: 1) The primary target “Uis the allocation of jobs to groups that suffer persistent disadvantage in the labour market.” 2) The proof of disadvantage should be evidence of disadvantage combined with membership of a protected group “Uwithout the need to prove comparative greater disadvantage than other groups.” 3) A broad justification for direct and indirect discrimination is possible, based either on furthering the aims of social inclusion or “Ua claim that the discriminatory rule only excludes those people who could not take advantage of the employment opportunity”. (Collins p. 39) 4) It requires positive action: “Ua duty of reasonable adjustment.” (Collins p. 39) Collins thinks new developments in anti-discrimination laws, ‘fourth generation duties’, fit into the social inclusion picture. (Collins p. 40) Collins emphasizes that social inclusion cannot be used to explain all anti-discrimination laws, but he does think it is useful in those cases where different treatment is required. It can help justify departures from the rule of equal treatment. (Collins p. 40) Social inclusion is distinct from equality of welfare and equality of opportunity. However, it is compatible with the aim of social inclusion for equal treatment to operate as the normal rule. Indeed, equal treatment often furthers the aim of social inclusion. (Collins pp. 40 – 41) Collins thinks equal treatment has such importance in anti-discrimination laws for two reasons: 1) Equal treatment is required by the principle of respect for individual dignity or individual worth. And this principle is expressed in Art 14 of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms. (Collins p. 41) 2) Equal treatment is a dominant constitutional principle in Western legal system. “The political goal behind anti-discrimination legislation becomes translated in the operations of the legal system as a rule that like cases should be treated alike. DWhatever the political aim behind anti-discrimination legislation, whether it comprises equality of results, equality of opportunity, or social inclusion, that aim has ETC Graz 57 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. to be modified to comply with the principle of equal treatment in order for it to be accommodated with integrity within the legal system.” (Collins p. 42) These reasons help explain why the laws do not match up with the aims of social inclusion exactly; for example, that men get equal protection even though they would not be classed as a protected group. (Collins p. 42) So there are two aims to anti-discrimination laws: equal treatment and the distributive justice aim. The distributive justice aim can often be understood in terms of social inclusion. Using social inclusion would give a more determinate standard for the legitimacy of positive discrimination laws than is currently the case: “It suggests that deviations from equal treatment should be permitted where the discriminatory measure is necessary to achieve the result of social inclusion for members of a group that are presently largely excluded.” (Collins p. 42) Thinking in terms of social inclusion also provides grounds for criticizing the current laws, such as the case of free entry to swimming pools for pensioners when there are different pension ages for men and women. On the basis of equal treatment, direct discrimination was found, but what aim was this furthering? Social inclusion suggests that a deviation from equal treatment may have been justified in this instance. (Collins pp. 42-43) DEGENER, Theresia (2011): Intersections between Disability, Race and Gender in Discrimination Law, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union NonDiscrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate, 29-46. Die Intersektionalitäten zwischen „Rasse“, Gender und Behinderung müssen laut Degener in der rechts- und sozialwissenschaftlichen Forschung erst entwickelt werden. (Degener S. 29) Außerdem sind kaum Daten zu multidimensionaler Diskriminierung im Bezug auf „Rasse“, Gender und Behinderung vorhanden. Degener spricht die Hierarchisierung der einzelnen Diskriminierungsgründe an. So sind in Deutschland die Standards für „Rasse“ und Gender strikter als jene für Behinderung. Diese Hierarchisierungen in Deutschland korrespondieren mit den Hierarchisierungen in den EU Richtlinien. (Degener S. 31) Degener gibt einen Überblick über den Umgang mit Diskriminierungen an den Intersektionen von „Rasse“, Gender und Behinderung im Recht der Vereinten Nationen und den UN – Konventionen und „Überwachungsorganen.“ (Degener S. 33 ff.) Positiv wird die UNBehindertenkonvention erwähnt, da diese Mehrfachdiskriminierung ausdrücklich normiert. (Degener S. 36) Daraufhin geht Degener auf die Europaratsdokumente wie z.B. die EMRK und die Europäische Sozialcharta ein. Abschließend wird das geltende Antidiskriminierungsrecht der EU untersucht. Anschließend an die europäischen und ETC Graz 58 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. internationalen Betrachtungen werden ausgewählte nationale Beispiele analysiert, z.B. hat die Australische Human Rights Commission das Thema der intersektionellen Diskriminierung aufgegriffen. Ebenso hat die US Equal Employment Opportunity Commission 2006 „Guidance Notes“ zum Thema intersektionale Diskriminierung veröffentlicht. Auch das Diskussionspapier der Ontario Human Rights Commission von 2001 wird erwähnt. (Degener S. 43) Zusammenfassend stellt Degener fest, dass es kaum Daten zu den Folgen von Diskriminierungen an den Intersektionen von „Rasse“, Geschlecht und Behinderung gibt (Degener S. 44), weswegen auch die öffentliche Wahrnehmung gering ist. Selbst die Betroffenen wissen oft nicht, wie sie die erlittene Diskriminierung benennen sollen. Obwohl viele der gerichtsanhängigen Fälle Züge von Intersektionalität aufweisen, werden sie von den RechtspraktikerInnen oft als single-ground Fälle vorgebracht. DEUTSCH, Francine M. (2007): Undoing Gender, Gender & Society 21, 106-127, vgl.: http://www.smu.ca/academic/arts/sociology/bios/documents/DeutschUndoingGender.pdf Ausgehend vom doing gender Ansatz nach West/Zimmerman stellt sich Deutsch die Frage, wie dieser Prozess umgekehrt werden kann. Für Deutsch scheint der Ansatz, Ungleichheit durch soziale Interaktionen hervorzubringen, so wie ihn West/Zimmerman darstellen, hoffnungslos. Deutsch sieht soziale Interaktionen aber auch als Chance für Widerstand gegen Herrschaftssysteme. (Deutsch S. 107) Doing gender wirkt stärker als Sozialisierung. (Deutsch S. 107) Gender ist etwas Dynamisches, das in Interaktionen immer wieder hervorgebracht wird. Daher ist hier auch Widerstand gegen bisher herrschende Strukturen denkbar. Doing gender zeigt auch die Schwächen deterministischer Erklärungsversuche (z.B. dass Männer weniger Hausarbeit machen, weil sie mehr Geld verdienen als Frauen und daher mehr Macht besitzen. Männer erledigen aber auch weniger Hausarbeit, wenn sie weniger verdienen als ihre Frauen). (Deutsch S. 108) Gender ist konstruiert, folglich kann es dekonstruiert werden. (Deutsch S. 108) Deutsch kritisiert das Wort doing, das den Fokus auf das Kreieren von Unterschieden statt auf das Abschaffen ebendieser legt. (Deutsch S. 109) Schwerpunkte der Forschung sind Hausarbeit, das Verhalten von Frauen in typischen Männerberufen, Verhalten von ForscherInnen und Beforschten in Interviewsituationen ETC Graz 59 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. (Deutsch S. 111 f.): Sie setzen sich mit dem Verhalten entsprechend von Normen auseinander (Deutsch S. 113). Neue Betrachtung von Interaktionen: - Interaktionen als Möglichkeit Geschlechterungleichheiten zu reduzieren. (Deutsch S. 114) - Gender kann in Interaktionen auch irrelevant sein. (Deutsch S. 116) - Doing difference muss nicht immer (benachteiligende) Ungleichheiten hervorbringen. (Deutsch S. 117) - Zusammenspiel von struktureller Ebene und Interaktionen bei Veränderungen. (Deutsch S. 117) - Interaktionen als Vorbild von Veränderung. (Deutsch S. 120) Deutsch spricht sich dafür aus, den Begriff doing gender durch undoing gender zu ersetzen (Deutsch S. 122), um Interaktionen ins Zentrum zu rücken, die Genderungleichheiten reduzieren. DIETZE, Gabriele, HORNSCHEIDT, Antje, WALGENBACH, Katharina, PALM, Kerstin (2007): Gender als interdependente Kategorie. Neue Perspektiven auf Intersektionalität, Diversität und Heterogenität, Opladen, Verlag Barbara Budrich. Walgenbach kritisiert in ihrer Einleitung den doing gender/doing difference Ansatz als zu verkürzt (Walgenbach et. al. S. 50): Es gibt eine wechselseitige Beeinflussung von Strukturen und sozialen Interaktionen. Historische und materielle Aspekte von Ungleichheit müssen mit einbezogen werden. Nach Walgenbach (Walgenbach et. al. S. 56) gibt es strukturelle Dominanzverhältnisse, welche die gesellschaftliche Realität fundamental auf materielle und diskursive Weise bestimmen (die Wahrscheinlichkeit auf welche Schule man geht, ob man sich ungestört fortbewegen kann etc.). ETC Graz 60 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. EUROPEAN UNION AGENCY FOR FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS (FRA) (2010): Data in Focus Report. Multiple Discrimination, EU-MIDIS, European Union Minorities and Discrimination Survey 05, vgl.: www.fra.europa.eu/fraWebsite/.../EU_MIDIS_DiF5-multiple-discrimination_EN.pdf Es werden neun Bereiche untersucht (FRA S. 7): - Arbeitssuche/Arbeitsmarkt - Arbeitsplatz - Wohnungsmarkt - Medizinisches Personal - Soziale Einrichtungen - Schule - Cafés, Restaurants, Bars oder Clubs - Beim Betreten eines oder in einem Geschäft - Kontoeröffnung oder Kredit Männer werden häufiger als Frauen diskriminiert und erleiden zudem auch öfter Mehrfachdiskriminierung (FRA S. 14). FREDMAN, Sandra (2002): Discrimination Law. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Equality: Concepts and Controversies Fredman begins by discussing the different kinds of equality and, in particular, the way that equal treatment can lead to unequal outcomes while unequal treatment may be necessary to achieve equality. (Fredman p. 2) She points out that these different views of equality are, in turn, driven by different views of justice: consistency on the one hand, and substantive justice on the other. (Fredman p. 2) Unequal treatment may be necessary, then, in order to address substantive, underlying equality in terms of education, wealth etc. She points out that the choice between these different kinds of equality is really a choice of values or policy: “Equality could aim to achieve the redistributive goal of alleviating disadvantage, the liberal goal of treating all with equal concern and respect, the neo-liberal goal of market or contractual equality and the political goal of access to decision-making processes. It is striking that, despite the widespread adherence to the ideal of equality, there is so little agreement on its meaning and aims.” (Fredman p. 2) She also points out that there can be a tension between equality and difference, but that this is not necessarily so. (Fredman pp. 2-3) ETC Graz 61 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. She also points out that equality can be in conflict with other values such as freedom – for example freedom of speech in the sense that someone might want to be free to make racist comments etc. (Fredman p. 3) The Principle of Equality Fredman cites Locke as epitomising the blossoming of liberal ideology and the accompanying rise in the importance of equality. (Fredman p. 5) This equality was, however, selective. Women, people of different ‘races’, Jews etc were excluded often and in important ways. (Fredman p. 5) In a standard, yet nonetheless controversial move, she ties the exclusion of these groups to equality’s link to rationality. That is, we are equal because and insofar as we are rational. If some groups were shown to be more emotional and irrational, then they lost their claim to equality. (Fredman p. 5) Formal equality or equality as consistency Fredmen cites Aristotle for “like cases should be treated alike”. (Fredman p. 7) Fredman raises a few problems with this: 1) When are like cases really alike? And this links to the point that not all distinctions are discriminatory – such as people being distinguished on the basis of income level for tax purposes. (Fredman p. 7) 2) It is only a relative principle – for example, if an employer treats both men and women equally badly, there is no sex discrimination. Also, it can be satisfied by levelling down so that if a swimming pool denies entry to non-whites, it could just close down rather than admit non-whites. (Fredman p. 8) 3) The need to find a comparator, which requires us to consider people in the abstract – absent ‘race’ or sex. In fact, what this amounts to, is that the ‘universal individual’ is really a white, middle-class, able-bodied, Christian, heterosexual male. (Fredman pp. 8-9) 4) The treatment of difference- “...there is no requirement that people be treated appropriately according to their difference.” (Fredman p. 10) 5) It is extremely individualist. It argues that individuals are treated on their merits, but this has meant that all group characteristics, and what they contribute to an individual’s identity, have been discounted. (Fredman p. 10) Equality of Results There are also problems with this idea. Are the relevant results: ETC Graz 62 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. 1) the impact on the individual? 2) the representation of the group? – so that, for example, if an organisation does not have a reasonable number of people from a minority group a presumption of discrimination is raised; 3) the proportionality of minority groups in organisations should be in line with their distribution in the general population. Anything less is discrimination. This does not examine why this disproportionality existed. (Fredman pp. 11-13 ) Equality of opportunity This can be seen as a middle-path between equality of treatment and equality of results, which aims to equalise the starting point. (Fredman p. 14) This can be further refined into either a procedural or substantive equality of starting position – the former emphasis removing procedural barriers, the latter “...requires measure to be taken to ensure that persons from all sections of society have a genuinely equal chance of satisfying the criteria for access to a particular social good.” (Fredman p. 15) A value driven approach “Equality laws have traditionally been founded and legitimated on grounds that they further the liberal goals of State neutrality, individualism, and the promotion of autonomy.” (Fredman p. 15) Fredman argues that this is highly problematic, especially as it ignores the importance and constitutive power of group membership. (Fredman p. 16) She then investigates some alternatives: Dignity Many jurisdictions have used dignity as their basis for equality. (Fredman p. 17) Fredman points out that “dignity” can be defined in various ways to make it strong or weak. (Fredman p. 19) Remedial and Restitutionary Aims “In this more historically specific sense, equality is aimed at compensating individuals for the detriment caused by prejudice and the ongoing effects of past discrimination.” (Fredman p. 19) Distributive Justice “A third value underlying equality is more explicitly redistributive, aiming not just to redress previous disadvantage but to achieve an equal distribution of social goods.” (Fredman p. 20) ETC Graz 63 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Participative Democracy “Given that past discrimination or other social mechanisms have blocked the avenues for political participation by particular minorities, legal rights, particularly equality laws, are needed both to compensate for this absence of political voice and to open up the channels for greater participation in the future.” (Fredman p. 22) The Scope of Discrimination Law Which groups ought to be protected and how far should this protection reach (only in the public sphere etc)? (Fredman p. 66) Grounds of discrimination Defining the grounds of discrimination: who decides and how? Fredman makes a couple of good points about the power-play that is involved in the decision of who should be protected from discrimination and why. For example, if it is left to popular opinion, there is the danger that the very people who most need attention may miss out (a majoritarian-type concern). (Fredman p. 67) She outlines three responses: 1) [A] “U broad open-textured guarantee, stating simply that all persons are equal before the law, without specifying any particular grounds. This approach takes the decision out of the political process, and instead leaves it to judges to decide when a classification is prohibited.” (Fredman pp. 67-68) 2) “Ulegislation containing an exhaustive list of grounds. This contrasts with the first approach in that the choice of ground is made wholly within the political process with no discretion left to the judges.” (Fredman p. 67) 3) “Ua list of grounds of discrimination, but indicates that the list is not exhaustive. D This approach gives judges some discretion to extend the list according to a set of judicially generated principles; but judicial discretion is bounded by the existence of enumerated grounds.” (Fredman p. 68) Searching existing categories: semantics or substance Fredman gives a brief outline of the status of anti-discrimination law in the UK and the EU. (Fredman pp. 68-69) The main point is that coverage is not complete; rather it varies from ground to ground and also from group to group. (Fredman p. 70) This has caused people to try to bring themselves within the established grounds even if it seems to be a bit forced. Fredman cites a few examples: sexual orientation has had to be argued for as a kind of sex discrimination; and Sikhs, Muslims, Jews and Rastafarians have had to claim discrimination based on ethnic origin because religion is not included. (Fredman p. 70) ETC Graz 64 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. The leading case (at the time of writing) in the UK for ethnic origin versus religion was Mandla v Lee [1983] 2 AC 548 (HL). (Fredman pp. 70-71) Fredman then discusses the ECJ’s approach to sexual orientation as a basis for a discrimination claim: “Uit held that discrimination could only be established if the complainant had been treated less favourably than a person of the opposite sex on grounds of sex (not sexual orientation). Deverything then depends on who is chosen as the comparator. If a gay woman is compared with a heterosexual man, there may well be discrimination. But if a gay woman is compared with a gay man, the opposite conclusion can be reached. In Grant v South West Trains, the ECJ held that the relevant comparator was not a heterosexual, but a homosexual man. Since a man living with a male partner was treated in the same way (ie equally badly) as the woman living with a woman partner, she could not complain that she had been treated less favourably than a similarly situated man. It was therefore held that there was no discrimination on grounds of sex.” (Fredman p. 73 – citation omitted) Generating Protected Grounds: Judicial Principles Fredman examines the way various jurisdictions have dealt with discrimination legislation that is made of non-exhaustive lists. (Fredman p. 76 ff) This has not always produced consistent results. In particular: “Courts in most jurisdictions have been concerned to prevent the equality guarantee from reaching to the basis of the capitalist society – namely inequalities of wealth. For example, in a US case, the system of funding local schools by local property taxes was challenged on the grounds that this discriminated against poor districts, whose property taxes were not of the standard of the richer areas, and therefore whose schools were correspondingly less well resourced. The US Supreme Court held that none of the traditional indicia of suspectness applied: there was no history of purposeful unequal treatment or political powerlessness. It is difficult to see why this is the case.” (Fredman pp. 79- 80) Judicial bias was also evident in the reluctance of courts to see that there had been discrimination against women until the 1970s – until then unequal treatment was seen to be OK. (Fredman p. 80) Scope of Discrimination Law Sex, ‘race’ and disability discrimination In the UK: “Existing ‘race’ and sex discrimination laws apply only to education, employment, and the provision of services. D The Disability Discrimination Act is similarly limited to ETC Graz 65 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. specific areas, namely employment, the provision of goods, facilities and services, premises, education, and transport.” (Fredman p. 83) Fredman also notes that there are significant exceptions, even within these areas. (Fredman p. 83) In terms of ‘race’ discrimination the exceptions relating to policing seem particularly problematic and some steps were taken to address this. (Fredman p. 84) The Human Rights Act 1998, incorporating the ECHR Article 14 of the ECHR (the dependent one) has been incorporated into UK law through the HRA, but Protocol 12 (the independent one) has not. (Fredman p. 86) EU Law EU law is driven by the fact that it was interested in discrimination that could affect “Uthe creation of a European-wide labour market.” (Fredman p. 89) FREDMAN, Sandra (2005): Double Trouble – Multiple Discrimination and EU Law in: European Anti-Discrimination Law Review, Issue No. 2, October 2005, 13-18 Fredman erwähnt anfangs, dass die meisten Personen eine multiple Identität haben; wir alle haben ein Alter, ein Geschlecht, eine sexuelle Orientierung und eine ethnische Zugehörigkeit. Bei manchen kommt noch eine Behinderung oder eine Religion hinzu. Dies bedeutet, dass Diskriminierung auch aufgrund mehrerer Gründe auftreten kann (Fredman, p. 13). Fredman verweist auf die Entwicklungen zum Thema der Mehrfachdiskriminierung in den USA und auf Kimberlé Crenshaw. Weiters führt Fredman kurz in das Thema und die Problematik der intersektionellen Diskriminierung ein (Fredman p. 13f). Die synergistische Beschaffenheit von Diskriminierungen machte es schwierig, Politiken und Gesetze so auszuformulieren, dass sie Mehrfachdiskriminierung adäquat adressieren. RichterInnen und Gesetzgeber waren vorsichtig im Umgang mit dem Thema, um nicht die „Büchse der Pandora“ zu öffnen (Fredman p. 14). Abgesehen von wenigen Ausnahmen waren die US – Gerichte vorsichtig, da sie eine Flut an Klagen von allen möglichen ‚Untergruppen‘ (zB Frauen mit Migrationshintergrund, o.ä.) fürchteten. So wurde in den USA festgehalten, dass sich Mehrfachdiskriminierung nur auf 2 Gründe beziehen dürfe. Das Resultat ist paradox, weil es darauf hinaus läuft, dass eine Person umso mehr sie von der Norm abweicht, desto weniger Chancen hat, Schutz zu erlangen (Fredman 14). Ebenso führt die synergistische Beschaffenheit von Mehrfachdiskriminierung laut Fredman dazu, dass es kaum brauchbare Statistiken hierfür in den Staaten gibt, da ‚Untergruppen‘ nicht erfasst werden. Insofern bleiben Personen, wie etwa MigrantInnen mit Behinderung, in den Statistiken ‚unsichtbar‘ (vgl Fredman p. 14). ETC Graz 66 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Als wahrscheinlichste Opfer von Mehrfachdiskriminierung nennt Fredman Roma- und Sintifrauen, wie eine Studie aus Deutschland zeigte.2 Fredman diskutiert die Frage, wie man Mehrfachdiskriminierung im EU Recht verankern kann. Die Erfahrungen aus den USA haben gezeigt, dass man dazu tendiert, Nichtdiskriminierungsrecht so zu verstehen, dass eine Diskriminierung jeweils eindeutig in eine Kategorie fällt. Jedoch zeigt das internationale Menschenrechtssystem andere Ansätze auf. Besonders wird hier die 4. Weltfrauenkonferenz in Beijing 1995 hervorgehoben (Fredman, p. 16), da dort darauf hingewiesen wurde, dass Alter, Behinderung oder sozioökonomische Position zu Barrieren für Frauen werden können. Auf der EU Ebene bietet die Erweiterung der Diskriminierungsgründe neue Möglichkeiten für die Anerkennung von Mehrfachdiskriminierung, jedoch schaffen die Strukturen der Richtlinien einige mögliche Hindernisse. Das erste ist die Aufteilung in mehrere Richtlinien, ebenso die abschließende Liste an Diskriminierungsgründen, die dem EuGH die Möglichkeit zur Ausweitung der Liste an Diskriminierungsgründen nimmt. Dies steht im Kontrast zu Art. 14 EMRK, der eine offene Liste an Diskriminierungsgründen vorsieht. Jedoch können neue Subkategorien geschaffen werden, da die Präambeln der Richtlinien Hinweise zur Mehrfachdiskriminierung geben (Fredman, p. 16f). Laut Fredman wäre die Schaffung einer nicht abschließenden Liste an Diskriminierungsgründen vermutlich der einfachere Weg zur Anerkennung von Mehrfachdiskrminierung gewesen, wie es auch in manchen Mitgliedsstaaten umgesetzt wurde. Als schwierigeres Problem bewertet Fredman die unterschiedlichen Anwendungsbereiche der Richtlinien und die unterschiedlichen Schutzniveaus in der Arbeitswelt und in den sonstigen Bereichen. Dies würde es unter Umständen einem älteren Angehörigen einer ethnischen Minderheit erschweren, Diskriminierung im Bereich des Wohnungsmarktes geltend zu machen. Ein möglicher Weg wäre der, dass die innerstaatlichen Regelungen über die Maßgaben der Richtlinien hinausgehen und umfassenden Schutz für alle Diskriminierungsgründe bieten. Dies wurde etwa in Belgien gemacht (Fredman, p. 17). Das Erkennen von Mehrfachdiskriminierung ist auch im Bereich der positiven Diskriminierung und der Positive Actions wichtig. Hier würde es dazu dienen, dass die am meisten benachteiligten Mitglieder einer Gruppe durch Actions erreicht werden könnten (Fredman, p. 18). Fredman betont abschließend, dass die Anerkennung von Mehrfachdiskriminierung ein wichtiger Schritt in die richtige Richtung ist. 2 EU Monitoring and Advocacy Program/European Roma Rights Center, Shadow Report Commenting on the fifth periodic report of the Federal Republic of Germany submitted under Article 18 of the United Nations Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (2004). ETC Graz 67 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. FREDMAN, Sandra (2010): Positive Duties and Socio-economic Disadvantage: bringing disadvantage onto the equality agenda, European Human Rights Law Review, 290-304. Fredman befasst sich mit dem UK Equality Act 2010, der die Einführung einer positiven Verpflichtung von Behörden zur Beachtung von Gleichstellung aufgrund des sozioökonomischen Status – genauer: sozio-ökonomischer Benachteiligung – vorsieht. Obwohl Fredman sich nicht explizit mit Mehrfach- oder intersektionaler Benachteiligung oder Diskriminierung im Aufsatz beschäftigt, gibt das Papier einige wichtige Hinweise auf diese Themenfelder: Mehrebenenansatz; Hinweise auf Single-ground Fokus der Rspr; Probleme der klassischen juristischen Beurteilung und der Rechtsschutzschwächen; Substantieller Gleichheitsbegriff durch Menschenrechtssystem; Capability approach zu social in/exclusion nach Sen. Traditionell werden Verteilungsungleichheit und Ungleichheit, die auf unerlaubten Unterscheidungsmerkmalen Geschlecht, „Rasse“ usw beruhen getrennt voneinander betrachtet. Die Berücksichtigung Gleichbehandlungsrecht hat von Kontroversen sozio-ökonomischer und Benachteiligung Unsicherheiten in der im Diskussion hervorgebracht, zB über eine mögliche Einschränkung oder Verwässerung der Wirksamkeit hinsichtlich der Diskriminierungsbekämpfung aufgrund der „traditionellen“ Gründe (Anm. Immutability). Allerdings wird die Abgrenzung zwischen beiden Formen von Ungleichheit immer problematischer, weil es wichtige Zusammenhänge zwischen beiden gibt (Hinweis Intersektionalität). Diese Zusammenhänge zu ignorieren würde Maßnahmen auf beiden Seiten negativ beeinflussen. Verteilungsmaßnahmen und Gleichbehandlungsmaßnahmen („status-based“) sollten daher nicht isoliert voneinander gesetzt werden. (p 2). Der Zusammenhang ist bidirektional. Armut ist nicht nur ein Phänomen von Verteilungsungleichheit, sie hat auch stigmatisierende Effekte, wie sie sonst eher den „Status“ Ungleichheiten zugeschrieben werden. Wenn es zu Stigmatisierung kommt, verstärkt sich die Armutstendenz. Umgekehrt haben Verteilungsmaßnahmen auch Einfluss auf die „Status“ Ungleichheit. Hinweis auf Intersektionalität ist zB, dass Maßnahmen, die auf dem Haushaltseinkommen beruhen, die Frage außer Acht lassen, ob dies auch den Frauen im Haushalt nützt. Der Zusammenhang von sozialem Hintergrund und Statusungleichheit aufgrund des Geschlechts oder der ethnischen Zugehörigkeit – insb. Hautfarbe – ist immens. Fredman geht damit bereits auf verschiedene Arten von Intersektionalitäten ein: Zwischen individuellen „Merkmalen“ („Status“) – Gender und ‘race’; zwischen Kategorien – class, ‘race’ and gender; zwischen Ebenen – Strukturebene (class) und individueller Ebene als auch zwischen Repräsentationen (Rollen, Stigmata) und Strukturebene (p. 3). Ein Abschnitt des Aufsatzes befasst sich mit sozio-ökonomischer Benachteiligung als Diskriminierungsgrund. In mehrerlei Hinsicht hat dieser Diskriminierungsgrund eine andere ETC Graz 68 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Qualität. Die gängige Rechtsprechung hat Anerkennungsprobleme: Armut ist nicht mit „Rasse“ vergleichbar: Während die Zugehörigkeit zu einer ethnischen Minderheit „discrete and insular“ sei, ist das bei Armut nicht der Fall. Allerdings wird Armut als Diskriminierungsgrund in Kanada unter dem Aspekt diskutiert, dass Armut oft jenseits der Kontrolle des Individuums begründet liegt und es daher ein unfairer Unterscheidungsgrund sei. Ein weiterer Qualitätsunterschied ist die notwendige Asymmetrie. Bei Verteilungsfragen geht es um Nachteile. Regeln sollten nicht dazu führen, dass privilegierte Personen positive Maßnahmen für Unterprivilegierte anfechten können. (Anm: der Verhältnismäßigkeitsmaßstab wäre jedenfalls anzuwenden). Ein weiterer Unterschied ist in der Frage zu sehen, ob eine Ungleichbehandlung aufgrund des sozio-ökonomischen Status stattfindet oder ob der Status selbst die Ungleichbehandlung darstellt. Im ersten Fall könnte die Unterscheidung tatsächlich gleich wie alle anderen verpönten Unterscheidungsmerkmale gehandhabt werden, im zweiten Fall stellt sich die Frage gänzlich anders: wer hat Schuld? Die Gefahr besteht, schnell in einen ideologischen Kontext zu geraten, nämlich hat die Gesellschaft (und als Repräsentant derer der Staat) eine Verantwortung für Gleichstellung (equality) und Verteilungsgleichstellung? Fredman geht offensichtlich davon aus. Das CESCR Komitee ebenfalls: Im 20. General Comment (E/C.12/GC/20) wird verlangt, dass Vertragsstaaten „economic and social situation“ als Diskriminierungsgrund untersagen, darüber hinaus verlangt CESCR Gleichstellungsresultate und nicht lediglich prozessorientierte Standards (p. 4). Fredman gibt eine knappe und präzise Darstellung der Einschränkungen des „complaintsled“ Modells: Es obliegt dem Opfer, sich gegen Diskriminierung zu wehren, das kann mühsam und teuer sein, daher bleiben viele Fälle ohne Beschwerde. Der Rechtsschutz ist retrospektiv, ereignisorientiert und individualisiert. Was verlangen sozio-ökonomische Gleichstellungsbestimmungen? Resultate, Chancengleichheit oder angemessene Berücksichtigung von Auswirkungen auf Betroffene? (Diskussion S. 5). Das UK Recht sieht lediglich prozessorientierte Vorgaben vor („it is about to promote equal opportunities – achievement is not required“), angemessene Berücksichtigung solle behördlichen Entscheidungen vorangehen, Entscheidung unterliegen einer diesbezüglichen Rechtfertigungspflicht. Transparenz und Verhältnismäßigkeit müssen gewährleistet sein. Die Entscheidung hat die Notwendigkeit zur Förderung von Chancengleichheit festzustellen, nicht jedoch ein bestimmtes Ergebnis herzustellen. Zur Feststellung von Chancengleichheit schlägt Fredman Sen’s Capability Approach vor (p. 6). [Anm: Die Einführung von sozialen Kategorien führt nahezu automatisch und „natürlich“ zu einer Öffnung des Single-ground Ansatzes, aufgrund der unterschiedlichen Qualitäten, des Zusammenspiels von sozio-ökonomischen und anderen Gründen und durch die Tatsache, ETC Graz 69 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. dass sozio-ökonomische Gründe eher struktureller Ursache sind und damit indirekte Diskriminierung darstellen mit den direkten Gründen interseggieren.] In der Diskussion über den Ausschluss von Asylwerberinnen und anderen argumentiert Fredman mit dem Menschenrechtssystem bzw. dem materiellen Gleichheitsbegriff: Die Rechte auf Wohnen und auf soziale Sicherheit können unter Art 8 bzw. Art 1, ZP1 subsumiert werden, dann trifft ein Land, welches diese als Rechtsanspruch normiert, auch das Diskriminierungsverbot des Art 14 (p. 8). Was ist nun die Verpflichtung? Offensichtlich geht es nicht um einen Diskriminierungsgrund „sozialer Status“ (class im engeren Sinne), sondern um die Ungerechtigkeit von Ungleichheit. Das ist nicht klagbar, aber eine indirekte Diskriminierung kann von den Gerichten geprüft werden, dabei haben die Entscheidungsbehörden klarzulegen, ob sie den sozialen Status der durch die Entscheidung betroffenen Personen angemessen berücksichtigt haben (p. 10). FRERICHS, Petra (2000): Klasse und Geschlecht als Kategorien sozialer Ungleichheit, Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie 52, 36-59, vgl.: http://www.springerlink.com/content/h5g3954485718256/fulltext.pdf Frerichs bezieht sich auf das von ihr durchgeführte Forschungsprojekt “Klasse und Geschlecht”. Klasse und Geschlecht sind zwei zentrale Strukturkategorien moderner Gesellschaften. Daneben führt Frerichs noch die Kategorie der Ethnizität an: Klasse und Geschlecht begründen soziale Ungleichheiten (unterschiedliche Positionen in der Arbeitsteilung und beim Zugang zu Ressourcen). Darüber hinaus wird durch die Kategorie Ethnizität eine „wir und die anderen“ Ab- und Ausgrenzung begünstigt, die auch über Klassen hinweg erfolgt. Zur Verquickung von Klasse und Geschlecht gibt es zwei Generalhypothesen: Geschlechtsklassenhypothese (Klassen existieren in geschlechtsspezifischen Ausprägungen und Ausdifferenzierungen, Männer und Frauen bilden differente Klassenstrukturen) und Klassengeschlechtshypothese (jede Klasse hat ihre eigenen Vorstellungen von Geschlecht). (Frerichs p. 40) Interviews mit vier Paaren in verschiedenen sozialen Positionen wurden durchgeführt. Abgefragt wurden Kindheit, soziale Herkunft, Lebenslauf, Lebenszusammenhang und Lebensstil, um daraus Rückschlüsse auf den Habitus der jeweiligen Person ziehen zu können. (Frerichs S. 40) Die Paare sollten sich in ihrem Kapitalvermögen deutlich voneinander unterscheiden. Arbeiterpaar, Angestelltenpaar, Lehrerpaar und ein Managerpaar. Interviews wurden getrennt, aber zur gleichen Zeit in den Wohnungen der Befragten geführt. Interviews waren offen und dauerten etwa fünf Stunden. Daneben wurde ETC Graz 70 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. alles das möglicherweise von Relevanz war (Kleidungsstücke, Einrichtung, Haltung und Verhalten der Befragten) notiert. Zusätzlich führten die Befragten über den Zeitraum von einer Woche ein Zeitverwendungs- und Ausgabenprotokoll. (Frerichs p. 41) Zusätzlich wurde ein quantitativer Teil mit einbezogen (Frerichs p. 42). Die Geschlechtsklassenhypothese zeigt hier, dass Frauen in vergleichbaren beruflichen Positionen durchwegs gleiche oder höhere Bildungsabschlüsse haben als Männer, beim Einkommen liegen sie allerdings weit unter den Männern. (Frerichs p. 45) Interviews wurden nach Grundmuster der Habitusformen bei Vorstellungen vom “guten Leben” ausgewertet. Dadurch konnte auch die Klassengeschlechtshypothese bestätigt werden (Die interviewten Paare weisen gemeinsame Wertmuster, Orientierungen und Geschmacksausprägungen auf). (Frerichs p. 56) GOLDBERG, Suzanne B (2009): Intersectionality in Theory and Practice in: GRABHAM, Emily, COOPER, Davina, KRISHNADAS, Jane and HERMAN, Didi (Hg.) (2009): Intersectionality and beyond: law, power and the politics of location, Oxford, Routledge-Cavendish. Goldberg uses the term ‘intersectional’ broadly to cover additive claims and maybe all multidimensional claims. Goldberg begins by pointing out that intersectionality runs into problems as it seems to drift into smaller and smaller units of intersection. (Goldberg p. 7) The article’s real contribution, however, comes from its attempt to discuss intersectionality in terms of law cases, lawyering, legal strategies and other practical matters. In short, it seems that those US law reform organisations that work with what might be described as intersectional claims, couple a conceptually conservative approach with innovative practical strategies: “Although advocates share with theorists a desire for a world free of identity-based harms, the bulk of their work, including their cross-identity projects, treats identity categories as stable and embraces widely recognized distinctions among them rather than attempting to destabilize their boundaries. When viewed through the theorists’ vision, advocates’ aims seem far less transformative and radical than they might otherwise appear. At the same time, however, advocates work with these purportedly stable categories in litigation in strategic, instrumental, and dynamic way, suggesting that the variable and contingent use of identity categories may be as important to our understanding of identity as the content of the categories themselves. More specifically, concentrating on the multiple roles and functions of identity categories may be a useful move for new ETC Graz 71 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. theorizing about how the meaning and boundaries of identity categories take shape.” (Goldberg, p. 126) Intersectional claims are shaped by the needs of the advocacy groups even before they reach the courts. Some of this is second-guessing what will succeed in court, but some of it is simply that groups want to take on claims that advance their particular interests. Note that these groups tend to be single-issue/single-identity groups, and in a way that rather mirrors the law’s ideas about this – for example, treating these categories as stable even though they can actually be broken down in a number of ways for different purposes. (Goldberg p. 125) Groups may work together, however, to address different aspects of an intersectional claim. (Goldberg p. 127) Goldberg suggests a few preliminary reasons to explain why legal advocacy groups continue to work in the single-identity framework: 1). Although identity is complex, the singlecharacteristic approach is still socially salient (Goldberg p. 130). 2) By the time intersectionality had become a mainstream concern, these single-characteristic groups were already set up and working. This is related to other issues such as how funding is allocated and the need for new groups to present themselves in a certain way in order to fit into the current legal advocacy landscape (Goldberg pp. 130-131). 3) Law itself has a single-identity focus, so it makes sense for advocacy groups to work with it as well. (Goldberg p. 132) However, as noted above, sometimes groups do work together to address more than one characteristic in an intersectional claim. Goldberg notes that the question of resources is often critical here, (Goldberg p. 133) but she also identifies the “expressive functions” as being of equal importance: “Specifically, a leading function of amicus briefs is to communicate an organization’s position, not only to the court but also to constituents and the broader public.” (Goldberg p. 133 – reference omitted) Groups will, then, balance the costs and benefits in terms of funds and reputation in order to decide whether to participate in cross-category actions. Goldberg identifies four interrelated “interests” that shape cross-identity relationships, which she then proceeds to discuss in some detail: 1) The legitimation interest 2) The civil-rights friendly environment interest 3) The mutual interests in effective antidiscrimination law 4) The overlapping identities (Goldberg p. 136) Goldberg points out that the reasons for advocacy groups taking on cross-identity claims are not really aligned with intersectional theory. That is, the focus is on interests rather than identity theory. (Goldberg p. 143) ETC Graz 72 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. She goes on to note, though, that theory and practice are now converging, at least to some extent. (Goldberg p. 143) “Broadly speaking, cross-identity practice may signal ways to move beyond the challenge that infinite complexity has posed for efforts to create a grand theory in this area. At the same time, intersectionality theories offer important challenges for identitybased advocates’ relatively passive acceptance of the existing identity categories paradigm.” (Goldberg pp. 136-137) Intersectional theory is not all good news for advocacy groups, though, as it puts into question their reliance on stable identity categories and so makes these claims less firm in legal terms: “To determine whether a party before the court is entitled to a remedy, for example, a judge must first decide whether that party falls within a protected category. If the category lacks clear boundaries, this task becomes difficult, if not impossible, for a court to fulfil.” (Goldberg p. 144) Advocacy groups could be thought of as using identity issues when and insofar as it suits them to achieve their ends. (Goldberg p. 144) “Identity theorists might also explore the move made in intersectional practice – especially in connection with the overlapping identities interest – away from the problematization of identity categories and toward expanding the conceptualization of existing antidiscrimination principles to broaden restrictions on would-be discriminators. A move in this direction could nicely compliment ongoing efforts to deconstruct the ways in which identity categories are used systematically to subordinate marginalized populations.” (Goldberg p. 145) And on the other side: “Advocates can likewise benefit from the insights of intersectional theorist, who have observed, repeatedly, that to accept overly simplistic categories is to obscure lived experience. Current cross-identity practices, as outlined above, do little to contest the law’s tendency toward oversimplification.” (Goldberg, p. 145) This does not sound particularly useful, however, until Goldberg spells out the long-term benefits in the conclusion: “As identity theory suggests, well-rounded protection can be achieved only by pressing courts to understand the analytic error in treating identity categories as independent of one another. By demonstrating, time after time, in brief after brief, that an individual does not exist as a person with a ‘race’ in isolation from sex or sexual orientation, for example, advocates could go a long way toward pushing back against and perhaps even redirecting the judicial orientation toward simplification. Courts have little incentive to do this themselves ... But if advocates were even to avoid some of the unnecessary ETC Graz 73 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. reification of identity boundaries ... the project of cross-identity litigation would be more profoundly transformative of the law and, likely, more protective of broader, more complex identities.” (Goldberg pp. 145-146) In short, the conclusion seems to be that it is up to advocates whether to be an active part of the acknowledgement of intersectional theory and/or the complexity of identity, or whether to take a conservative approach and continue to work largely within the single-identity framework. GRABHAM, Emily (2009): Intersectionality: Traumatic Impressions, in GRABHAM, Emily, COOPER, Davina, KRISHNADAS, Jane and HERMAN, Didi (Hg.): Intersectionality and beyond: law, power and the politics of location, Oxford, Routledge-Cavendish. Grabham discusses intersectionality primarily in terms of identity and whether it rather paints itself into a corner, even while avoiding some traditional, limiting essentialist accounts. (Grabham pp. 183 – 185) She hopes to overcome this through a reconsideration of Wendy Brown’s analysis of “pain” and “injury”.3 “I argue that by investigating ‘trauma’ as the mundane experience of subjects under liberalism, it is possible to develop a picture of intersectionality which does not rely on governmentally produced identity categories.” (Grabham p. 186) Grabham outlines the case-study of M, in which she attempted to craft an intersectional discrimination claim, but with limited success. This particularly raised the question of how and whether the law can deal with more complex versions of identity. (Grabham pp. 188-189) Grabham now turns to the question of trauma and Brown’s theory that identity constructions contribute to subservience and patterns of powerlessness. (Grabham p. 189) Brown uses the concept of ‘resentment’ (in a recognisably Nietzschean way): “All liberal subjects are situated within a realm that promises them equality – promises them the conditions in which they can realise their dreams, and presumes that they have the capacities to do so, but which is actually underpinned by a variety of social inequalities that prevent them from achieving this.” (Grabham p. 189) Identity constructed through resentment is locked in a relation with the oppressive conditions against which it struggles – it is dependent on these conditions to exist and so has real problems in overcoming them. (Grabham pp. 189 – 190) Nietzsche’s advice was to ‘forget’ but Brown instead argues for a shift from ‘being’ to ‘wanting’. (Grabham p. 190) 3 Wendy Brown (1995) States of Inquiry: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity, Princeton University Press, New Jersey ETC Graz 74 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Grabham argues that presenting intersectional claims to the legal sphere is an expressions of resentment – externalising the pain etc. (Grabham p. 190) Further, she thinks intersectionality is conceptually conservative in that it relies on the axes (the categories) existing outside of particular combinations. (Grabham p. 191) “On the one hand, intersectionality analysis is presented as a challenge to abstract and depoliticised theories of identity formation... On the other hand, many forms of intersectional analysis, and especially the way that I applied intersectionality to law in M.’s case, do not interrogate social positions as effects of power.” (Grabham pp. 191192) And further: “Viewing intersectional analysis in the context of the genealogy of identity claims in liberal society gives us more of an understanding, why it has not had the radical effects in discrimination law that we might have wished for. If single-ground rights claims are based on disciplinary identities, then intersectional rights claims (and many forms of legal intersectional analysis) are no less bound to these categories. Using more categories in legal analysis, or focusing on the intersections between legal categories, does not of itself challenge the regulatory function of liberal identity.” (Grabham p. 192) Intersectionality becomes merely a new kind of identity recognised at law, rather than challenging the law’s restrictive use and ideas of identity in a fundamental way. (Grabham pp. 192-193) “Not only does intersectionality analysis in law fail to challenge categories, therefore, it actually deepens and extends the law’s impetus towards the regulatory production of identities. Intersectionality, on these terms, helps to produce the legal ‘truth’ of inequalities through classification.” (Grabham p. 193) Grabham now turns to Ann Cvetkovich’s work on trauma.4 In short, “Cvetkovich presents a sex-positive approach to trauma, which focuses on the experiences of women, queers, butches, femmes and Aids activists.” (Grabham p. 194) “Where resentment aims to overcome the hurt, find a ‘culprit’ and displace the hurt through assigning it to an external site..., Cvetkovich’s examples of trauma combine responses to the hurt of anger and aggression with counter-cultural sexual practices or politicised music, comedy or writing.” (Grabham p. 196) She then discusses Sara Ahmed’s work on impressions.5 “In effect, impressions describe how emotions are socially and historically mediated, and how they reside outside the individual subject.” (Grabham p. 197) And further: 4 Ann Cvetkovich (2003) An Archive of Feelings: Trauma, Sexuality and Lesbian Public Cultures Duke University Press, Durham NC 5 Sara Ahmed (2004) The Cultural Politics of Emotion Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, UK ETC Graz 75 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “Impression, as combinations of sensation and emotions, shape the movements of our bodies towards and away from objects and each other in ways that replay racism, colonialism and rigid gender norms.” (Grabham p. 198) Tying this to intersectionality: “...if emotions function as affective economies, then paying attention to the impressions that subjects make on one another can allow for a political reading of encounters that goes beyond the individual subject and beyond the law’s construction of individuals through disciplinary identities. With this in mind, describing M.’s experience in legal terms as ‘intersectional’ invokes her identity as a Tran’s woman and a lesbian but it says nothing about the productive force of the encounter between her and her colleague in aligning her body, through hate and fear, as a threat.” (Grabham p. 198) Grabham now moves to her conclusion: “Intersectionality has been an important contribution to feminist legal theory, in particular, leading to much work that interrogates the silences, invisibilities and oppressive effects of law on racialised subjects in particular. Yet the more disciplining aspects of intersectionality discourse have been overlooked. Intersectionality is now arguably the product of the law’s classifying impulse to the extent that focusing on the ‘intersections’ has merely resulted in the disciplinary production of more identities.” (Grabham, p. 199) And: “However, by investigating trauma as a mundane state of being, produced across physical and emotional encounters, it is possible to approach the complexity of inequalities without prioritising governmentally produced identity categories and without thereby contributing to the production of ‘new’ categories.” (Grabham p. 199) Grabham notes that she is “...not necessarily interested in what this ‘means’ for the conduct of legal cases.” (Grabham p. 199) ETC Graz 76 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. HANNETT, Sarah (2003): Equality at the Intersections: The Legislative and Judicial Failure to Tackle Multiple Discrimination, 23 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1, 65-86 A) The suggestion is that discrimination should be thought of in terms of disadvantage rather than difference. (Hannett p. 9) As an illustration of the comparator problem she cites the case of a homosexual airman who had to resign. He had to be compared to a lesbian and then it was seen that the treatment would have been the same and so no discrimination was found. Hannett mentions some signs of change in this area at least – so simple sex discrimination is possible and, in the case of pregnant women, there is no need for a ‘pregnant man’ as a comparator: “In Webb v EMO Air Cargo (UK) Ltd the House of Lords held that less favourable treatment on the basis of pregnancy must generally amount to discrimination on the basis of sex, with no need for comparison with a man.” (Hannett p. 11) Concise summary (footnotes omitted): “The underpinning ideology of the anti-discrimination statutes, formal equality, or equality of treatment, may be insufficient to tackle such disadvantage. The statutes are individualistic: they demand an individual claimant, and award an individual remedy. Inherent in the scatter-gun approach of current anti-discrimination law is the idea that ‘what is complained about is abnormal.’ This cannot provide acknowledgement or redress for institutionalized or structural discrimination. Similarly, the symmetrical nature of the statutes reflects the ideology of equal treatment: discrimination against men is as impugned as discrimination against women; discrimination against whites is as deserving of censure as discrimination against ethnic minorities. Accordingly, the ‘legislation is framed in terms of difference rather than disadvantage: it constructs the problem to be tackled as ‘race’ and sex discrimination, rather than as discrimination against and disadvantage of women and certain ethnic groups’. This model prevents a remedial response targeted at disadvantage. Thus although a united anti-discrimination statute may be one mechanism by which the problems of a claim of multiple discrimination can be alleviated, the difficulties of those who attempt to claim multiple discrimination are merely a further illustration of the lack of transformative potential of an anti-discrimination regime premised on equality of opportunity.” (Hannett p. 12) Hannett is, then, not in favour of symmetry in anti-discrimination laws. Also, she wants recognition of the structural, institutional aspects of discrimination, rather than simply focusing on the different personal characteristics of the person suffering discrimination. ETC Graz 77 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. B) Hannett unterscheidet nach Crenshaw zwischen additiver und intersektioneller Diskriminierung. Beide beziehen sich auf Diskriminierungen aufgrund unterschiedlicher sozialer Charakteristika. Erstere bezeichnet Diskriminierungen, die Individuen betreffen, die verschiedenen, diskriminierenden Praktiken ausgesetzten Gruppen angehören. Letztere entsteht durch eine unteilbare Kombination von unterschiedlichen Unterwerfungsmechanismen. Durch diese Form der Diskriminierung wird etwas Neues, Einzigartiges, von eindimensionalen Diskriminierungen Unterschiedliches. In einer essentialistischen Welt kann intersektionelle Diskriminierung nicht geklagt werden, schreibt Hannett (S 3). Der „allgegenwärtige“ weiße, männlich „Normkomparator“ und die Idee des „One-size-fitsall“, welche annimmt, dass Gruppen homogen sind und daher einheitliche gruppenspezifische Rechtsmittel existieren, macht (intersektionelle) Benachteiligungen „unsichtbar“ (hidden). Strukturelle Benachteiligungen sind inhomogen und dadurch werden spezifische intersektionelle Benachteiligungen übersehen. Hannett’s Beitrag ist trotz inzwischen geänderter Rechtslage von großer Bedeutung. Hannett analysiert anhand praktischer Fälle das Problem der Rechtsdurchsetzung in Fällen von Intersektionalität und strukturiert die unterschiedlichen Probleme. So argumentiert sie, dass im Fall des Zusammentreffens von direkter und indirekter Diskriminierung aus zwei unterschiedlichen „Gründen“, die indirekte Diskriminierung große Beweisprobleme aufwirft. Die einfache Regel, dass eine Bestimmung zu erfüllen, in der betroffenen Gruppe und in der Vergleichsgruppe gleich wahrscheinlich sein muss, ist praktisch kaum bestimmbar oder messbar, hängt von der Möglichkeit ab, eine Vergleichsgruppe definieren zu können und zeitigt in intersektionellen Fälle reine Zufallsergebnisse. Eine Kategorie von Fällen sind „under-inclusive cases“. Dabei sind Fälle zu unterscheiden, in denen (einzelne) „Gründe“ nicht vom Gesetz geschützt sind, das Zusammenfallen von Gründen nicht durch das Gesetz geschützt ist oder die Gerichte die Art des Schadens (type of harm) nicht dem geschützten Grund zurechnen bzw. den Zusammenhang oder die Kausalität ablehnen (S 8). Ist es wichtig, ob die tatsächliche Diskriminierung und diejenige, die vom Gericht festgestellt wird ident sind? Für Hannett ist dies eine grundlegende Frage der Gerechtigkeit von Rechtssprechung und ist mit „ja“ zu beantworten (S 9). Hannett schlägt vor, in intersektionellen Fällen, insbesondere in mittelbaren und strukturellen Benachteiligungen immer die Frage zu beantworten, wem die Benachteiligung nützt. Während formale Gleichheit symmetrisch ist, ist substantielle Ungleichheit asymmetrisch. Der qualitative Unterschied liegt in der historischen Benachteiligung durch die Diskriminierung, es ist eben ein sozialer Nachteil, kein Nachteil aus unmittelbarer Ungleichbehandlung (S 9). ETC Graz 78 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Die Vergleichsperson ist für Hannett ein prinzipiell zu überdenkendes Konstrukt. Erstens steht hinter den Vergleichen immer eine „Normperson“. Zweitens werden bei der Auswahl (zu) oft irrelevante Faktoren herangezogen und außerdem ist es nicht immer angemessen, (scheinbar) Gleiches auch gleich zu behandeln, wenn zB Faktoren zu berücksichtigen wären, die vor dem Gesetz jedoch formal keine anerkannten Faktoren sind. Hannett verwendet sexuelle Orientierung zur Erklärung ihrer Überlegungen. Sie bezeichnet Fälle von sexueller Orientierung zumeist als im- oder explizit intersektionell (mit Gender), womit sich freilich die Frage stellt, wer ist die Vergleichsperson, homosexuell vom anderen Geschlecht, heterosexuell vom gleichen Geschlecht oder die „Normperson“? JACOB, Jutta, KÖBSELL, Swantje, WOLLRAD, Eske (Hg.) (2010): Gendering Disability. Intersektionale Aspekte von Behinderung und Geschlecht, Bielefeld, Transcript Verlag. Wie Hutson ausführt (zitiert in Jacob et. al. p. 66), entsteht die Mehrfachverletzbarkeit aus den entsprechenden Gesellschaftsstrukturen heraus. Das heißt, eine Person mag mehrfach verletzbar sein, auch wenn sie es selbst nicht so wahrnimmt und auch wenn es nicht die Absicht des Gegenübers ist, sie zu verletzen. Zinsmeier zeigt auf (zitiert in Jacob et al p. 114 ff.), wie durch die intersektionale Analyse statistischer Daten die Häufigkeit von Diskriminierungsrisiken von bestimmten Bevölkerungsgruppen bestimmt werden kann. Nicht jede soziale Ungleichheit ist rechtlich relevant. Hierfür reicht es nicht aus, soziale Lebenslagen zu vergleichen (Jacob et al p. 118). Hierbei geht es um einzelne Handlungen. Nicht jede Ungleichbehandlung ist eine rechtliche Benachteiligung. Um die Intersektionalität einer betroffenen Person in einem speziellen Einzelfall ausreichend berücksichtigen zu können, wird es notwendig, statistische Daten mit einzubeziehen. Ein Beispiel wäre die gerichtlich angeordnete Sterilisation einwilligungsunwilliger betreuter Personen: Es müssen statistische Daten mit einbezogen werden, wer von solchen verordneten Sterilisationen besonders betroffen ist, und ein Vergleich mit der Entscheidung von einwilligungsfähigen betreuten Personen in vergleichbarer Situation gezogen werden. Zinsmeier legt außerdem dar, wo intersektionale Aspekte im deutschen Recht bereits berücksichtigt werden. ETC Graz 79 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. KERNER, Ina (2009): Alles intersektional? Zum Verhältnis von Rassismus und Sexismus, Feministische Studien 1/2009, 36-50, vgl.: http://www.feministische-studien.de/fileadmin/download/pdf/Kerner1_09.pdf Kerner unterscheidet im Bereich Rassismus und Sexismus drei Dimensionen: Eine epistemische Dimension (Wissen und Diskurse, Symbole und Bilder zu Rassismus und Sexismus), eine institutionelle Dimension (institutionalisierte Formen von Rassismus und Sexismus, die strukturelle Diskriminierung bewirken) und eine personale Dimension (Identität, individuelle Einstellungen, individuelle Handlungen und Interaktion). (Kerner p. 36) Rassismus und Sexismus sind komplexe Machtphänomene, sie funktionieren unter Rekurs auf körperliche Merkmale und sind daher naturalisierende Differenzzuschreibungen, etwa im Gegensatz zu Klasse. (Kerner p. 37) Um das Verhältnis von Rassismus und Sexismus darzulegen, schlägt Kerner vier Modi vor: Ähnlichkeiten, Unterschiede, Koppelungen, Verflechtungen/Intersektionen. (Kerner p. 38) 1. Ähnlichkeiten: Bei beiden werden kategoriale Unterschiede konstruiert. Verquickungen gibt es auch hier, indem z.B. Gehirne weißer Frauen mit denen nichtweißer Männer verglichen werden und beiden eine geringere Intelligenz zugeschrieben wird. (Kerner p. 40) 2. Unterschiede: Sexistische Geschlechternormen sind reproduktionszentriert (Kerner p. 42), d.h. sie sollen die Reproduktion steigern. Rassistische Diskurse über dieses Thema dienen dazu, Vermischungen zwischen “Rassen” zu verhindern. 3. Koppelungen: Sexistische Sorge um Reproduktion und rassistische Sorge um Homogenität können sich verknüpfen. Z.B. Förderung der Erhöhung der Geburtenrate von Inländerinnen und gleichzeitig restriktive Einwanderungspolitik. Oder auch die “Ethnisierung des Sexismus”, in dem die anderen als noch sexistischer als man selbst angesehen werden. (Kerner p. 44) 4. Intersektionen: Kerner entwickelt Intersektionen von Rassismus und Sexismus, die eine epistemische, eine institutionelle und eine personale Dimension umfassen. • Epistemische Dimension: vergeschlechtlichte rassifizierte Rassevorstellungen (z.B. Geschlechtsnormen Unterschiede und schwarzer Weiblichkeit im Vergleich zu weißen Frauen, aber auch Unterschiede in den Zuschreibungen zwischen schwarzen Männern und schwarzen Frauen). (Kerner p. 47f.) • Institutionelle Dimension: Ineinandergreifen der Bedingungen am Arbeitsmarkt, familiärer Strukturen und bildungspolitische Situation (daraus resultiert z.B. keine traditionelle Frauenrolle für Afroamerikanerinnen). (Kerner p. 48) ETC Graz 80 Literature Review • Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Personale Dimension: Verschränkung der Entwicklung von geschlechtlichen und personalen Identitätsprozessen. (Kerner p. 48) KLINGER, Cornelia, KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli (2007): Achsen der Ungleichheit – Achsen der Differenz: Verhältnisbestimmungen von Klasse, Geschlecht, „Rasse“/Ethnizität, in: KLINGER, Cornelia, KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli, SAUER, Birgit (Hg): Achsen der Ungleichheit. Zum Verhältnis von Klasse, Geschlecht und Ethnizität, Frankfurt. Klinger/Knapp schlagen zur Erforschung von Fragen sozialer Ungleichheit einen interkategorialen Ansatz vor. Die zentralen Fragestellungen sind demnach das Verhältnis von Kontinuität und Wandel in den Formen von Ungleichheit einerseits und das Verständnis der für die Gegenwartsgesellschaft relevanten Strukturgeber von Ungleichheit. Klinger/Knapp identifizieren dazu die Achsen von Klasse, Ethnizität und Geschlecht als unterschiedliche, aber miteinander in Wechselwirkung stehende Strukturzusammenhänge und plädieren für die Entwicklung einer integrierten und kategorial erweiterten Analyse von Ungleichheit. Sie betonen, dass Ungleichheit weder vorübergehende Erscheinung noch marginale Anomalie der Gesellschaft sind (p. 19). Ungleichheit ist funktional und besitzt systemischen und systematischen Charakter. Klinger/Knapp beziehen sich auf eine moderne kapitalistisch organisierte Gesellschaft. Diese Gesellschaft kann einerseits Gleichheit nicht herstellen und andererseits permanente und persistente Ungleichheit nicht begründen oder rechtfertigen. Weiters wählen sie drei Achsen der Ungleichheit, Klasse, Ethnizität und Geschlecht, weil diese alle Formen von Gesellschaften nachhaltig prägen. Die Auswahl erfolgt vor dem Hintergrund aktueller Problemlagen und weil die Achsen in die Geschichte der gegenwärtigen Gesellschaftsformation verweisen. Damit dienen sie als mögliche Unterscheidungen ebenso wie als tatsächliche, begründet in der historischen Gesellschaftsentwicklung (p. 27). Die Achsen der Ungleichheit sind Verhältnisse, in denen Personen leben. Klinger/Knapp verbinden drei Schulen miteinander, Ungleichheitssoziologie, Gesellschaftstheorie und Gender-, (neue) Class- und (Critical) Race-Studies, um „strukturierte Ungleichheit“ zu beschreiben, aber auch und vor allem zu erklären. Die theoretische Anbindung erfolgt an die Kritische Theorie, wobei der Ansatz um die systematisch integrierte Perspektive aller drei Achsen erweitert wird (p. 31). Damit argumentieren Klinger/Knapp für einen Ansatz auf der gesellschaftlichen Makroebene und wenden sich gegen die „Vereigenschaftlichung/Personalisierung und Privatisierung“ insbesondere des Geschlechts als eine „Einhegung“ eines gesellschaftlichen Spannungsverhältnisses (p.S 32). Geschlecht und „Rasse“ sind sozial konstruierte Kategorien und keine biologischen (biologistischen) „Natürlichkeiten“ (p. 33). Sie sind ETC Graz 81 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. gesellschaftliche Strukturgeber (p.S 34). Beide zusammen werden selten in Frage gestellt, alle drei Achsen gemeinsam wurden von der Theorie bis in die 1980er Jahre kaum behandelt, anschließend fand der Diskurs eher auf der individuellen (mikro- bis mesotheoretischen) Ebene statt. Dabei werden die Kategorien eher als Identitätskategorien aufgefasst und auf der Subjektebene angesiedelt. Die Frage steht im Vordergrund, wie die Individuen durch ihre Zugehörigkeit zu einem Geschlecht, einer Klasse oder einer Ethnie betroffen sind. Der Fokus liegt auf Identität und Diskriminierung und vernachlässigt die makrotheoretische Perspektive auf Achsen der Ungleichheit (p. 36). Die Eigenständigkeit der Kategorien und ihr Zusammenhang müssen gleichzeitig bestimmt werden (p. 37). Anmerkung: Wir finden uns wieder in der Problematik, ob Diskriminierungsrecht auch Gleichstellungsrecht ist (sein soll) bzw. wie weit es das ist. Als Gleichstellungsrecht hat der Fokus auf gesellschaftlich strukturierte Ungleichheitskategorien gerichtet zu sein, dann kann ein Gleichbehandlungsrecht im Einzelfall zur gesellschaftlichen Gleichheit beitragen. Als Gleichbehandlungsrecht muss es logisch und konsistent auf Ereignisse und Individuen, allenfalls auf Identitäten bzw. Identitätsmerkmale rekurrieren und symmetrisch sein, um dem formalen Gleichheitsgebot gerecht zu werden. Die Frage ist, ob eine Kombination möglich ist, tatsächlich handelt es sich ja um eine Kombination aus Gleichstellungs- und Gleichbehandlungsrecht, das nicht nur aufgrund des Hinweises, der durch das Verbot sowohl direkter als auch indirekter Benachteiligung gegeben wird. KNAPP, Gudrun-Axeli (2005): Intersectionality – Ein neues Paradigma feministischer Theorie? Zur transatlantischen Reise von Race, Class, Gender, Feministische Studien 23, 68-81. Begriffe der Gegenwartsdiagnostik sind aufschlussreich. In der feministischen Gesellschaftsanalyse taucht der Begriff der Paradoxie auf. Der Begriff Paradoxie hat den früher üblichen Begriff Widerspruch ersetzt. Dies kann entweder ein Hinweis darauf sein, dass sich gesellschaftliche Verhältnisse verändert haben oder bewusst geschehen, um einen Lern- oder Aufklärungsprozess in Gang zu setzen. (Knapp p. 2) Interessant und aufschlussreich sind Knapps Dilemmata (Knapp p. 8 f.): 1. Gleichheitsdilemma: Gleichbehandlung Ungleicher führt zur Fortschreibung von Ungleichheit, Differenz wird unsichtbar gemacht. 2. Differenzdilemma: Betonung von Differenzen schreiben Gründe für Diskriminierungen fort. 3. Identitätsdilemma: Annahme von Gruppen-Identitäten blendet Nicht-Identisches innerhalb einer Gruppe aus. Die Lösung dafür ist nach Knapp der Intersektionalitätsansatz. (Knapp p. 16) ETC Graz 82 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. KUHAR, Roman (2009): At the Crossroads of Discrimination. Multiple und intersectional discrimination, Peace Institute, Ljubljana, vgl.: http://www.mirovniinstitut.si/data/tinymce/Publikacije/Na%20kriziscih%20diskriminacije/At%20the%20Cro ssroads%20of%20Discrimination.pdf Diskriminierung wird als Praxis von Ungleichheit beschrieben. (Kuhar p. 15) In der EU sind sechs Diskriminierungsgründe im Vergleich zu einer Normperson festgelegt. Formen von Diskriminierung: Es gibt direkte und indirekte, individuelle und strukturelle Diskriminierung, Belästigung, soziale Exklusion, Viktimisierung, ethnic profiling, Diskriminierung durch Einrichtungen, Aufforderung zur Diskriminierung und Hassrede. Diskriminierung geschieht häufig auch über Sprache. (Kuhar p. 19 f.) Kuhar zeigt den Unterschied zwischen mehrfacher und intersektionaler Diskriminierung auf. (Kuhar p. 34 f.) Nach Verloo gibt es drei Dimensionen: Die Möglichkeit der Wahl, Sichtbarkeit und die Wahrscheinlichkeit der Veränderung. (zitiert in Kuhar p. 36) ForscherInnen führten 21 semi-strukturierte Interviews durch: Im ersten Teil konzentrierte man sich auf Intersektionalität von Identität, der zweite Teil fragte nach der Bedeutung einer bestimmten Identität im Umfeld der befragten Personen und nach konkreten Diskriminierungserfahrungen in Zusammenhang mit dieser Identität. Der dritte Teil versuchte intersektionale Diskriminierungserfahrungen aufzuzeigen. (Kuhar p. 62 f.) Die Personen wurden auch dahingehend befragt, wie ihr Leben wohl aussähe, wenn sie eine ihrer Identitäten nicht hätten. Im vierten Teil fragte man nach der Position der jeweiligen Person in ihrer Gruppe. Auch Kenntnisse über policies wurden erfragt (Kuhar p. 64). Darüber hinaus wurden Fokusgruppeninterviews mit ExpertInnen durchgeführt. ETC Graz 83 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Angst, Probleme Stereotype, Vorurteile Normperson Attribute zuweisen Person A “wir; positiv” Person B “die anderen; negativ” Distanz Soziale Exklusion Belästigung Viktimisierung Ethn. profiling Diskriminierung durch Einrichtungen Vorurteile werden bestätigt Self fulfilling prophecy LUTZ, Mark A. (2001): On the Norm of Equality, International Journal of Social Economics; 2001; 28, 10-12, 782 Philosophy has a number of different notions of equality. Here Lutz’s interest is in “descriptive” equality. The claim that humans are ‘by nature’ equal, points to the idea that there is a kind of “particular (non material) essence in the sense of an essential human characteristic that is said to be common to all persons.” (Lutz p. 783) Several different varieties of this approach exist: 1) The notion of a common humanity inherent to all. Lutz here cites Reck and Adler and references Kant: “’Humanity’ for him is not a person but in a person.” He also points out that this is linked to the next category of moral capacity. (Lutz pp. 783 – 784) 2) Human equality based on a common moral capacity. Again Kant, but not only Kant held this view. Rawls is a prominent modern day thinker in this group. Lutz also cites Coons and Brennan and their theory of “double equality”, which means that “a host ETC Graz 84 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. property that could in principle be variable by degree, but in fact is not so.” They propose that this “double equality” is our shared moral capacity. (Lutz p. 784) 3) Human equality based on equal human dignity. This is opposed to instrumental worth. It is thus differentiated from merit (Hayek) and rationality (in terms of rational capacity etc). Again Kant is a key historical thinker here, linking dignity to moral autonomy etc. As a more modern source of this idea, Lutz cites David Thompson’s use of G K Chesterton using the example of a penny: some pennies are dull, some are bright, but they all have equal value. (Lutz p. 785 – 786) 4) Human equality based on equal human rights. Equal human rights can be either based on natural law or on human equality. Locke is cited as the historical figure here for the natural law approach and Kant, again, for the approach that takes equal human rights to follow from the “metaphysical propositions of a common humanity, moral capacity and especially human dignity.” The Universal Declaration of Human Rights also takes this approach. (Lutz p. 786) In contrast to all of these, there is the human–equality-as-a-norm idea that grew during the 19th century, so that it is not an “asserted fact, but a postulated ideal ... based in convention, not nature.” (Lutz p. 786) In the 20th century this took on other forms such as Bernard Williams’ use of the linguistic method. “According to this social logic, ‘the proper ground for distribution of medical care is ill health: this is a necessary truth’” (Lutz p. 787) However, Lutz cites Guttmann’s objection of relativism. “For example, needs have not always been understood as rights to their fulfilment”. (Lutz p. 787) He also points out that pragmatism is a problem for equality as what if it does not promote other ends such as democracy or liberty? (Lutz p. 788) Posner cited as wanting law to do away with “relentless prating about such intangibles as the promotion of human dignity, the securing of justice and fairness”. (Lutz p788) “More constructively, on the perennial question of just what human beings ‘really’ are, we are told that it is an issue that can only be understood and argued within a particular community or tradition sharing a common language and culture of their own, that human equality must be conversationally , not ontologically based; that whatever objectivity that term has, will be owed to cultural uniformity rather than metaphysical reality; that there are no normative concepts enjoying specific meanings able to transcend time and place.” (Lutz p. 788) Lutz expresses real concern about using a pragmatist version of equality; leaving it up to chance that consensus can be reached: “If questions of equality cannot be guided by reasoned argument, they may have to be left to power and conquest.” (Lutz p. 788) The discussion then turns to the relation of descriptive equality to normative equality. Lutz suggests thinking of equality as a presumption rather than a postulate. (Lutz p. 789) ETC Graz 85 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “In law, a presumption is an inference that a fact exists, and is based on a prior establishing of other facts.” (Lutz p. 789) MAKKONEN, Timo (2002): Multiple, Compound and Intersectional Discrimination: bringing the experiences of the most marginalized to force, Institute for Human Rights, Åbo Akademi University, April 2002, vgl.: www.abo.fi/instut/imr/norfa/timo.pdf Makkonens Artikel ist so weit ersichtlich der erste, der versucht, die rechtlichen Möglichkeiten zur Bekämpfung von intersektionaler Diskriminierung auszuloten und Definitionen für die unterschiedlichen Formen anzubieten. Im ersten Teil wird ein konzeptioneller Rahmen entworfen und das Wesen des rechtlichen Diskriminierungsgedankens samt Formen, „Gründen“ und Motivationen bzw. persönlichen Bewältigungsstrategien beschrieben. Makkonen unterscheidet zum einen zwischen stereotypisierten Zuschreibungen und tatsächlichen Unterscheidungen als Begründungen für Benachteiligungen. Weiters unterscheidet er zwischen direkter, indirekter als auch institutioneller und institutionalisierter Diskriminierung. Letztere unterscheiden sich dadurch, ob sie eine Absicht verfolgen oder unabsichtlich wirken. Institutionelle Diskriminierung beschreibt er als Strukturen, die bestimmte Merkmale benachteiligen bzw. benachteiligende Effekte für TrägerInnen dieser Merkmale bewirken. (Anmerkung: im europ. AntiDiskriminierungsrecht werden strukturelle, institutionelle, indirekte und institutionalisierte Formen unter dem Tatbestand der mittelbaren (indirekten) Diskriminierung zusammen gefasst, die Diskriminierungsabsicht spielt dabei keine Rolle – im Übrigen auch nicht bei unmittelbaren Diskriminierungen). ereignisorientierten und Makkonen prozessorientierten unterscheidet Konzepten zum weiters hinsichtlich Verständnis von Diskriminierung. Makkonen unterstreicht, dass Anti-Diskriminierungsrecht vordergründig auf die ereignisorientierte Sicht abstellt, die prozessorientierte Sicht jedoch einen wesentlichen Zugang zum Verständnis von Intersektionalitäten und intersektionaler Diskriminierung eröffnet. (Anmerkung: unmittelbare Diskriminierung ist im Recht ereignisorientiert zu betrachten, der prozessorientierten Sicht wird theoretisch und praktisch durch den Chancengleichheitsansatz, positive Diskriminierung und den Gleichstellungsgrundsatz entsprochen, die Ansichten der europ Gesetzgeber sind dazu extrem unterschiedlich.) Makkonen stellt ein Modell von Diskriminierung als Zusammenhang von Vorurteilen, Stereotypen, Haltungen und Einstellungen mit dem tatsächlichen Verhalten vor. Vorurteile legten demnach die Tendenz einer Person zu diskriminierendem Verhalten fest. Abhängig von Situation und Kosten der Diskriminierung (Sanktion) findet diese dann statt (oder auch nicht). Dies überträgt sich gesellschaftlich: Haltungen führen zu Diskriminierung und zu ETC Graz 86 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. sozialer Distanz. Diskriminierung führt zu sozioökonomischen Unterschieden, diese wiederum führen zu sozialer Distanz und bestärken stereotypisierte Haltungen. (Anmerkung: Machtunterschiede werden im Ansatz nur implizit mitgedacht). Im Zweiten Teil bietet Makkonen Definitionsvorschläge an. Wenngleich diese logisch argumentiert sind, weicht Makkonen von den soziologischen wie auch rechtlichen Definitionen ab (Anm: Legaldefinitionen existieren bislang nicht, Makkonens Beitrag wurde vor Umsetzung des Anti-Diskriminierungsrechts in den Nationalstaaten verfasst). Der Artikel leistet jedoch einen wichtigen Beitrag zur Klärung der Konzepte, indem er auch den Unterschied von Intersektionalität, multipler Verletzlichkeit und intersektionaler Diskriminierung behandelt. Makkonen zeigt, dass weder im Menschenrechtssystem noch in den Sozialwissenschaften einheitliche Definitionen zu finden sind. Verschiedene Begriffe werden im Menschenrechtssystem für dieselben Phänomene verwendet. Makkonen schlägt folgende drei Definitionen vor: Als Mehrfachdiskriminierung bezeichnet er das Phänomen, dass eine Person aufgrund verschiedener Merkmale zu unterschiedlichen Zeitpunkten diskriminiert wird. Mehrfachdiskriminierung wird also im eigentlichen Wortsinn verstanden, bezeichnet also unterschiedliche Ereignisse. Als „verbundene“ Diskriminierung (compound discrimination) bezeichnet er, wenn in einem Ereignis eine Person aus mehreren Gründen, also gleichzeitig, diskriminiert wird. Auch dies ist im eigentlichen Wortsinn richtig, wird im Anti-Diskriminierungsrecht jedoch als Mehrfachdiskriminierung bezeichnet, wohingegen Makkonens Definition der Mehrfachdiskriminierung nicht als solche anerkannt wird, sondern als jeweils einzelne Diskriminierungsfälle behandelt werden. Als intersektionale Diskriminierung bezeichnet Makkonen das Phänomen, wenn eine Person aus verschiedenen Gründen diskriminiert wird, und die Überschneidung der Diskriminierungsgründe zu einer „neuen“ Form der Diskriminierung wird. Intersektionale Diskriminierung im engeren Sinn „verlangt“ eine „Interaktion der Diskriminierungsgründe“ (p. 10). Als vierte Kategorie nennt Makkonen noch die „überlappende“ (overlapping) Diskriminierung, wonach zu einem Zeitpunkt Diskriminierung aus voneinander unabhängigen Gründen erfolgt (diese Form wird auch als additive oder auch als kumulative (die Makkonen als sequentionelle behandelt) im Recht bezeichnet). Makkonen würdigt die Konzepte von Subordination, Verletzlichkeit und Benachteiligung, stellt jedoch klar, dass diese Konzepte Hinweise vor allem auf indirekte Diskriminierung sind, jedoch vom Tatbestand der Diskriminierung rechtlich zu unterscheiden sind. Im dritten Teil argumentiert Makkonen, warum intersektionelle Diskriminierung meist im Verborgenen bleibt und führt dabei zwei wesentliche Ursachen an. Erstens bezeichnet er die essentialistische Sicht auf Identitäten als Ursache für die Unsichtbarkeit von Intersektionalitäten durch „Ausblenden“ von „Mehrfachidentitäten“ (narrow understanding of ETC Graz 87 Literature Review identity). Zum Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Zweiten identifiziert er unter Berufung auf Crenshaw die Gruppenbildungsprozesse und ihre Abgrenzungsmechanismen (narrow understanding of the group) als wesentliches Element des „Single-Identity-Models“ und damit des Konzepts der „Single-Ground-Discrimination“. Der vierte Teil behandelt verschiedene Lebensbereiche, die Intersektionalitäten nahe legen und somit die Wahrscheinlichkeit für Mehrfach- und intersektioneller Diskriminierung erhöhen. Makkonen spricht sich jedoch insgesamt gegen den Ansatz aus, Diskriminierungen grundsätzlich als intersektional zu betrachten. Zwar hält er die „intersectional terminology“ für nützlich in der Analyse von Diskriminierungsfällen, sie sollte aber nicht andere, etablierte Menschenrechtskonzepte ersetzen. Andererseits erkennt er in einem antizipierten Opferverdacht durch die Wahrscheinlichkeit von Intersektionalität aufgrund der Überschneidung benachteiligter sozialer Positionen eine neue Gefahr von Stereotypisierung und Stigmatisierung. Im fünften Teil fasst Makkonen Stärken und Schwächen des Ansatzes zusammen. Wichtigstes Argument gegen das Konzept ist für Makkonen die Gefahr des „automatically presumed victim“ in die positive und negative Richtung, nämlich als Rechtfertigungsgrund für begangene Diskriminierung einerseits oder die angenommene Unglaubwürdigkeit der Opfereigenschaft von Personen, die nicht in das Schema intersektionaler Verletzlichkeit passen. Die mögliche Schaffung von „victim identities“ durch das Konzept ist ein weiterer Schwachpunkt des Ansatzes laut Makkonen. Allerdings relativiert er die Einwände dadurch, dass er feststellt, dass statistische Methoden alleine keine Lösung für die Beurteilung gesellschaftlicher Ungerechtigkeitskonstellationen darstellt. Dem stellt Makkonen zwei enorme Stärken des Konzepts gegenüber. Den revolutionären Blick des Ansatzes auf Diskriminierung und seine Auswirkungen auf das Verständnis von Diskriminierungen und Menschenrechtsverletzungen und die möglichen Auswirkungen auf effizientere Politik zur Bekämpfung von Diskriminierung auf gesellschaftlicher wie auch individueller Ebene. Im sechsten Teil untersucht Makkonen die (grundsätzliche und theoretische) Fähigkeit des Menschenrechtssystems, mit intersektioneller (und Mehrfach-)Diskriminierung umzugehen und in wie weit das Menschenrechtssystem Intersektionalität anerkennt (Stand 2002). Besondere Beachtung finden in der Analyse das Human Rights Committee (HRC), welches den umfassendsten Artikel zum Diskriminierungsgebot behandeln könnte (Art 26 ICCPR), CERD und CEDAW, welche das Problem von Mehrfachdiskriminierung und Intersektionalität erkennen und behandeln. Makkonen kommt zum Schluss, dass es bei einigen UN Bodies ein gewisses „Level of Awareness“ gibt und einige Aspekte tatsächlich ernst genommen werden. Die Frage, ob eine explizite Anerkennung durch Dokumente oder Beobachtungen der Bodies erforderlich ist, um im Menschenrechtssystem behandelt werden zu können, beantwortet Makkonen nicht abschließend. Er belegt auch nicht hinreichend, ob das ETC Graz 88 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Menschenrechtssystem „in principle“ fähig ist, mit anderen als dem Single-ground Modell umzugehen, gibt aber einige Hinweise dafür. Der siebente Teil bietet Schlussfolgerungen für die Anwendung bzw. deren Möglichkeit des Konzepts in der Rechtspraxis und Empfehlungen für Politik, Gesetzgebung, Wissenschaft und Praxis. MARCHETTI, Elena (2008): Intersectional Race and Gender Analyses: Why Legal Processes Just Don’t Get It, Social and Legal Studies 17, 155-174., vgl. http://sls.sagepub.com/content/17/2/155.full.pdf+html Marchetti argues that it is difficult to recognise categories of difference within a process that is “framed within an ideology that emphasizes objectivity and universalism” (Marchetti p. 155). This paper is written from an Australian perspective, but discusses issues of wider relevance. It uses the example of the Australian Royal Commission into Aboriginal Deaths in Custody to show that “Uthe dominant liberal ideology can, at times, operate to exclude racialized women.” (Marchetti p. 155) Marchetti points out that the law is reluctant to find substantive inequality at all and, when it does, it deals with it on the basis of only a single characteristic. (Marchetti p. 156) Marchetti also argues that “Uan intersectional approach is important because it circumvents the dangers of considering ‘race’ in isolation from gender when making legal determinations or when introducing new policies concerning Indigenous people.” (Marchetti pp. 156-157) The commission is an interesting case as it made quite an effort to be racially sensitive. However, it does seem to have excluded indigenous women; in other words, it could not work intersectionally. (Marchetti p. 157) Indigenous Women and the Royal Commission into Aboriginal Deaths in Custody The commission began with rather a narrow focus, but grew to include consideration of the underlying social, cultural and legal issues behind the deaths in custody. (Marchetti p. 158) The report was criticized, however, for ignoring the “Uprevalence of family violence within Indigenous communities” which resulted in the deaths of many more women than those that died in custody. (Marchetti p. 158) The report also failed to mention the “Uabusive and disrespectful manner in which Indigenous women are treated by the police; the inadequacies of the custodial experience for Indigenous women; the lack of trained Indigenous women to ‘investigate sexual offences’; the silencing of Indigenous female voices in court processes and lack of community input in ETC Graz 89 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. court to assist with social control; the over-representation of Indigenous women in relation to public order offences; and the imposition of harsher penalties on Indigenous women for minor offences.” (Marchetti p. 159) Explaining the Failure to take an Intersectional Approach Marchetti now goes on to explain the methods used to investigate why the Commission did not adequately deal with Indigenous women. (Marchetti p. 160) Seven reasons were found and these were divided into two categories: “(a) reasons that related to the struggle between ‘race’ and gender politics; and (b) reasons that were procedural in nature.” (Marchetti p. 160) ‘race’ and Gender Politics: Community (‘race’) Focus A majority of the interviewees felt that the report was about Indigenous people, ‘race’ as such, and that it was not about gender as a separate issue. (Marchetti p. 161) Women were involved in the commission process, but they brought up issues generally relating to indigenous people rather than specifically to women for various reasons, including not wanting to have more men locked up and not wanting to be blamed for this if it happened. (Marchetti pp. 161-162) Also, the officers of the commission did not ask about issues specifically relating to women. (Marchetti p. 162) Marchetti also notes an important point made by the anthropologist Bell: “Uwhen arguing for Indigenous self-determination, politics of ‘race’ become paramount and gendered perspectives are set aside as internal affairs.” (Marchetti p. 162) ‘race’ and gender Politics: The large number of male deaths and the deep disadvantage of young indigenous males There were more male deaths than female deaths in custody. This influenced the focus of the report and the female deaths were not treated as likely to be for different reasons, but merely noted as a subset of the total figure. (Marchetti p. 163) The idea emerged that young Indigenous males were more disenfranchised than Indigenous females. (Marchetti p. 163) This was accompanied by the often-used liberal division of life into public and private spheres. The thought then became that damage in the public sphere (no chance of employment) was much worse than anything that could happen in the private sphere (such as having a child taken away by the authorities). (Marchetti pp. 163-164) Marchetti notes that many of the interviewees think the focus might be different if the commission were held today, merely for the fact that many more women are now being locked up. (Marchetti p. 164) ETC Graz 90 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Procedural Reasons: The Terms of Reference A sizeable minority of interviewees thought that the problems specifically affecting women were not the business of the commission. (Marchetti p. 164) Marchetti thinks that this denies the fact that the terms of reference of the commission were open to considerable discretion in terms of their interpretation. For example, in the case of male deaths in custody, there was often a link to family violence that could have been investigated. (Marchetti p. 165) The commission also pointed out that finding a direct cause of the deaths in custody was not easy, as even a cause such as alcohol, which at first seemed simple, became more complex on closer examination as the links to colonization etc emerged. So, again, family violence etc could have been included in the investigation if the commissioners had wished. (Marchetti p. 165) Procedural Reasons: The legal procedures used to investigate the deaths The commission was focused on finding the “truth” of how the deaths occurred and this left little time to consider if conditions were different for Indigenous men and women. (Marchetti 166) The legal focus meant that factual, rather than sociological research was considered important and relevant. Also, consideration of cultural and social issues was introduced too late in the process to have enough of an impact. (Marchetti p. 166) Procedural Reasons: Deep colonizing methodologies The methods of the commission did not embrace “Indigenous cultural norms and understandings” but were rather “’deep colonizing’ methodologies” (Marchetti p. 166) The commission was ignorant, for example, of the reasons why Indigenous women may have only discussed issues of general importance, rather than those that specifically related to Indigenous women. (Marchetti p. 167) “The cultural pressure not to speak up and the fear of retribution were reinforced by community views which dismissed any mention of female-specific problems, such as family violence, as ‘radical feminist lesbian hairy legged talk’”. (Marchetti pp. 167-168) Procedural Reasons: Ideological Values of the Predominantly Male Senior People Appointed A sizeable minority of the interviewees noted a significant difference between male and female commissioners. (Marchetti p. 168) Most of the senior people were men from conservative backgrounds who adopted a legal methodology. (Marchetti p. 168) The few non-Indigenous women in reasonably senior positions may also have been under pressure to act like men. (Marchetti p. 168) There was also a lack of social science knowledge among the lawyers. (Marchetti p. 168) ETC Graz 91 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Procedural Reasons: Time and Resource Constraints The time limit meant that only basic issues could be dealt with and in a straightforward way. In particular, as issues such as family violence only emerged late in the process, there was no time to deal with them properly. (Marchetti p. 169) Conclusion: “The commission failed to adopt an intersectional approach “D unintentionally and largely as a result of the liberal legal ideology which was embraced by the inquiry. The commissioners conducted a predominantly legally directed investigation about ‘race’ without realizing that by doing so, Indigenous males would be favoured. ‘race’-centred politics (which Stubbs and Tolmie (1995: 129) describe as being ‘predominantly the narrative of men’) and the formalistic nature of liberalism structured the ways in which the terms of reference were interpreted, the ways in which evidence was gathered and interpreted, and the RCIADIC’s inability to use decolonizing methodologies (see Tuhiwai Smith (1999) for a discussion of how imperialism has directed the research agenda in colonized nations). ‘race’-centred politics and liberalism inadvertently worked together to erase the experiences of Indigenous women by making the experiences of the minority group (and, as a result, minority men), paramount.” (Marchetti p. 169) “In the course of a legal inquiry which contains questions of ‘race’, racialized women become invisible. The formalistic notions of equality associated with liberal thought tend to treat all members of a racialized group as being equally positioned. This positioning, however, tends to privilege male experience. D Men are viewed as leaders and builders of the next generation; women have children to keep them going and there is no expectation that they will be leaders and builders. The concerns of racialized women are put aside for the sake of saving racialized men from stateinflicted forms of violence and thereby saving the marginalized group as a whole. The process by which this occurs hinges on a liberal ideology that cannot see beyond the patriarchal and cultural values of the hegemonic state. It appears difficult for legal processes to escape the influences of liberalism in order to be able to make recommendations and determinations that include the experiences of people living at the margins of multiple identities. As Crenshaw (1989: 14) points out, ‘problems of exclusion cannot be solved simply by including Black women within an already established analytical structure’. Without a conscious effort to adopt an intersectional approach, there is little chance for the structures of law to be more inclusive. A conscious effort would require any process to include a number of ‘narratives and stories, accounts of the particular, the different, and the hitherto silenced’ (Harris, 1990: 615). Different dimensions of power, as they exist in the lives of both racialized women ETC Graz 92 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. and men, need to be made explicit if the position of the most vulnerable is to become known (Lucashenko, 1997). Such accounts, however, need to be actively sought by the inquirers, not just left to surface of their own accord. In order to achieve this, the processes used to obtain different narratives must be informed by culturally appropriate practices, something which legal systems tend not to do (Rose, 1996). Legal processes also require adequate resources and a sufficient amount of time for the collection and analysis of the different narratives. Ultimately, however, without a full appreciation of the risks involved in making recommendations and determinations that are not informed by an intersectional analysis, superficial changes to legal processes will simply continue to exclude the experiences of minority women.” (Marchetti pp. 169170) McCOLGAN, Aileen (2007): Reconfiguring Discrimination Law, Public Law, 74-94, vgl.: http://droitsocialupx.free.fr/articles/Mc%20Colgan%20reconfiguring%20discrimination %20law.pdf McColgan provides a very useful summary of the issues with uni-dimensional identity as used in anti-discrimination law. She sets out clearly the way in which people are viewed only in terms of their “different” characteristic and the way that this is put against a “neutral” norm. That means white people are ‘race’less, men are genderless or sexless, straight people have no sexual orientation etc. Discrimination law in the UK is undergoing reform. The Equality Act 2006 has put in place the framework for the establishment of the Commission for Equality and Human Rights; and Equalities and Discrimination Law reviews are under way (as of time of writing – 2007). (McColgan p. 1) Lots of issues raised that were/are in need of reform, including some related to intersectionality, such as the current need to choose single grounds and the existence of a hierarchy of grounds. (McColgan p. 1) Grounds-based approaches to discrimination The standard approach in the UK is a grounds-based approach and this is common in many countries. This approach has two key questions that are interrelated: 1) Which grounds are regulated? 2) How are these grounds defined? (McColgan p. 2) ETC Graz 93 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. McColgan notes that, in the UK, there used to be a choice only between the Race Relations Act 1976 and the Sex Discrimination Act 1975; this lead to a push for broader interpretations of ‘race’ and sex discrimination to allow other kinds of discrimination to fall under these Acts. As a result, religious discrimination was partly accommodated as ‘race’ discrimination, but sexual orientation was not accommodated as sex discrimination: “The point here is not that purposive, expansive interpretation of discrimination statutes is a matter for criticism. But the grounds-based approach may set in stone institutional solutions to problems of a previous era and the courts may be unwilling, or perceive themselves as unable, to shape interpretative outcomes so as to make such legislation fit for current purpose.” (McColgan p. 2) McColgan argues that the sex and ‘race’ discrimination acts were passed at a time when these issues were seen as important and the issues of discrimination based on religious grounds or because of sexual orientation were not. Mandla v Dowell Lee – “ethnic group” discrimination broadened the understanding of ‘race’ discrimination to include some groups but not all. Importantly, not all religious discrimination as such was included. Discrimination against Muslims or Christians was not included, but discrimination against Sikhs and Jews was. Thus, what was an expansive approach in 1983, to address a pressing social problem of the time, became a restriction later that prevented the law from addressing new, but related, social problems. (McColgan p. 2) Even when a long list of grounds, widely interpreted, is used (and here McColgan cites Ireland as an example along with the UK’s Disability Discrimination Act 1995), problems can emerge. The Disability discrimination Act has a three-part definition of disability which excludes those who are discriminated against on the grounds of perceived rather than actual impairments so that “Usomeone sacked because she was incorrectly thought to have cancer, or a heart condition, or because her partner was known to be HIV positive, would not fall within the protection of the Act.” (McColgan p. 3) The Race Relations Act protects against discrimination based on the “race” of a person’s partner or associates and this approach has been followed in other recent legislation relating to sexual orientation or religion, but the Sex Discrimination Act applies only to the claimant him/herself. (McColgan p. 3) Although there are ways around these problems, McColgan argues that grounds-based approaches have fundamental difficulties in dealing with the complexities of identity. (McColgan p. 3) The dilemma of unidimensionality McColgan quotes Nitya Iyer in support of her claim that grounds-based approaches always fail to capture the multi-dimensional nature of identity: ETC Graz 94 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “Once a characteristic is created as intrinsic to a group, and becomes its identifier, it is regarded as wholly constitutive of the group’s social identityD[and] the social identity constructed on the basis of this now ‘intrinsic’ difference is exactly the same for every member of the groupU”. (McColgan p. 4) “There is no such thing as an ‘unsexed’ black person or ‘homosexual’ or an ‘unraced’ woman or lesbian. Rather, according to Iyer, ‘other aspects of social identity are rendered indistinguishable from the background norm’, that is ‘[t]he particular set of social characteristics of the dominant social identity and its ideology Dagainst which categorizations of difference are made in anti-discrimination law.’ The purportedly ‘neutral’ is in fact not so, but conforms in all respects (except that of the single identifier) with the ‘background norm’: white, male, heterosexual, temporarily ablebodied, Christian or irreligious.” (McColgan p. 4 – footnotes omitted) A grounds-based approach thus involves splitting a person’s identity into classified, manageable aspects. A black woman = ‘race’ + gender, and so it is reasonable to discuss these aspects separately. (McColgan p. 4) The unidimensional approach in practice Degraffenreid v General Motors – judge dismissed a claim that specifically black women were discriminated against. If they could have shown that they were discriminated against as women or as African American, then they would have had a claim, but as neither white women nor black men were discriminated against as well, then they had nothing. (McColgan p. 4) Bahl v The Law Society – McColgan argues that this case shows that those suffering from intersectional discrimination must present themselves as only suffering from one kind of discrimination. (McColgan p. 5) Canada v Mossop Canada’s Supreme Court – a gay man was denied leave for the death of his partner’s father. He argued that the discrimination was based on his family status (which was covered by the legislation), but the Court held that this was discrimination based on sexual orientation which was not covered by the legislation. (McColgan p. 6) Pearce – The House of Lords ruled that a lesbian was not subject to gender discrimination, but rather discrimination based on sexual orientation which was not covered by legislation at the time. (McColgan p. 6) McColgan notes that it is very difficult for a gay man or lesbian to convince a court that workplace harassment is due to sex/gender rather than sexual orientation. (McColgan p. 6) Also, in regard to indirect discrimination- it is not sufficient to show that women of a particular ‘race’ are at a disadvantage, but that either women are disadvantaged compared to men, or ETC Graz 95 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. both men and women of that ‘race’ are disadvantaged compared to those of other ‘races’. (McColgan p. 6) Acknowledging complex claimants?: the “sex-plus” approach Degraffenreid was not widely followed in the US. Jefferies v Harris County Community Action Association – the court allowed “sex-plus”. McColgan thinks this approach is flawed but still an improvement on that of Degraffenreid and Bahl. In particular it was an advance in the matter of proof as it was not enough for the employer to show there was no discrimination against black men or white women. (McColgan p. 7) Black women have been rejected as being representative in cases of cumulative discrimination in class actions. That is, a black woman was held to be discriminated against because she was a black woman and so could not represent white women (Moore v Hughes Helicopter Inc). McColgan notes that “Uit misses the point that all women are ‘raced’, and that a white woman seeking representative status in a sex discrimination claim is no more characteristic of her black female colleagues than Ms Moore was of her white female colleagues.” (McColgan p. 7) Class actions are not common in the UK so this problem has not really emerged, however, McColgan does point out that the “sex-plus” approach defines white women as “unraced” which “Dhas profound repercussions for how ‘sex’ discrimination is conceptualised.” (McColgan p. 7) Even if we reconceptualise ‘woman’ to include race and ‘race’ to include women, this still does not fully account for the multi-faceted nature of identity (such as sexual orientation etc). At law, this is a real problem in terms of choosing or constructing the comparator. (McColgan p. 8) Problematising categories McColgan argues that “Uthere is nothing preordained about the categories to which things, or people, are assigned for the purposes of social or, indeed, legal organisation.” (McColgan p. 8) McColgan also points out that discrimination based on a mistake is just as disadvantageous – so somebody fired for the mistaken belief that he/she has AIDS is still fired. (McColgan pp. 8-9) Alternative approaches: lessons from Canada? McColgan is keen that any alternative to a grounds-based approach does not collapse into vacuity and she thinks that Canada may have the answer. (McColgan p. 9) ETC Graz 96 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Andrews v Law Society of British Columbia defined discrimination for the purposes of s15 of Canada’s Charter of Rights as: 1) a distinction (intended or otherwise) 2) based on grounds relating to the personal characteristics of the individual or group concerned, which 3) has the effect of imposing disadvantages or burdens not imposed on others, or of withholding access to advantages or benefits available to others. (McColgan p. 9 – footnote omitted) This required a focus on grounds as a preliminary stage but in Egan v Canada a dissenting judgment proposed an alternative test which suggested looking to the effects rather than the constituent elements of discrimination. (McColgan p. 10) Conclusion Denise Réaume advocates the adoption of an open list, pointing out that “Uin no other civil claim is it necessary to establish that there is a single, sufficient cause or explanation of the harm suffered in order to succeed. Normally, all that matters is that the alleged wrongdoing is a ‘but-for’ cause or necessary condition; the existence of multiple necessary conditions that come together to create the harm is no bar to recovery, especially when both causes are alleged to be unlawful behaviour and are combined in the behaviour of a single agent.” (McColgan p. 11 quoting Denise Réaume – footnote omitted) McColgan is unsure if this open list approach is workable. She points out that employers could be said to discriminate in the sense that they may not hire someone based on inadequate qualifications or low intelligence and that this could then be actionable as there is no general justification defence. It may also be necessary to define discrimination in terms of unfair or unjustifiable rather than different treatment. Also, McColgan sees this kind of approach as giving a lot more discretion to the judiciary and she is unsure whether they are trustworthy. (McColgan pp. 11-12) Instead, McColgan proposes a closed but expanded list of grounds which particularly takes into account multiply disadvantaged claimants. (McColgan p. 12) In terms of the casual requirement, McColgan suggests “Uthat a finding of discrimination requires only that the ground or grounds relied upon was a causal factor in the treatment challenged.” (McColgan p. 12) She also challenges the centrality of the comparator. (McColgan p. 12) “Any new legislation ought to contain a strong purpose clause which makes specific reference to the need to tackle the structural disadvantage suffered by particular groups, many of them at the intersection of protected and other grounds. Crucially, such legislation ought not to define terms such as ‘race’, ‘disability’, ‘sex’ and ‘sexual ETC Graz 97 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. orientation’, and it ought expressly to provide that treatment resulting from perceptions about the claimant’s membership of any group defined by reference to a protected ground, or his or her (lack of) conformity to characteristics associated with such a group, is covered by the prohibition on discrimination.” (McColgan p. 12) McColgan is still in favour of detailed statutory framework but, following Hannett, she advocates an approach based on disadvantage rather than difference. (McColgan pp. 12 – 13) McColgan again returns to the question of proof. For example, in Dresdner Kleinwert Wasserstein Ltd v Adebayo – when the black claimant could show that he was “at least as well qualified” as the white candidate selected for the post, the burden of proof would shift to the alleged discriminator to provide an explanation that would show no discrimination. McColgan is concerned, however, that this approach could lead to multiple claims following every promotion or appointment by all the unsuccessful candidates. (McColgan p. 13) One way around this, McColgan suggests, is to draw a formal distinction between those advantaged and those disadvantaged – so it makes a difference if it is a woman claiming sex discrimination in a dominantly male workplace etc. However, if a woman is appointed to a job in a dominantly male workplace, the non-successful males should not find it easy to claim sex discrimination. (McColgan p. 13) Another way of putting this is that McColgan thinks that the more open-ended discrimination claims become, the more asymmetrical they need to be, to stop absurdity. Finally, she thinks that it “Uis crucial that we move towards a definition of discrimination in terms of the exacerbation of disadvantage.” (McColgan p. 14) MIDDLEMISS, Sam and DOWNIE, Margaret (2009): Recent Changes in the Evidential Requirements in Indirect Sex and Race Discrimination Cases, International Journal of Law and Management 51, 367 – 373, vgl: www.emeraldinsight.com/1754-243X.htm This paper analyses the impact of recent case law on the evidential requirements of indirect ‘race’ and sex discrimination. They note that the law remains complicated and confusing here and that there are several hurdles to be overcome for a claim of indirect ‘race’ or sex discrimination to succeed. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 367) Indirect discrimination has different evidential requirements than direct discrimination. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 367) ETC Graz 98 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. The changing definition of indirect discrimination The starting point: Sex Discrimination (Indirect Discrimination and Burden of Proof) regulations SI 2001/2660 and Employment Equality (Sex Discrimination) Regulations 2005 Under the 2001 regulations “requirement or condition” under s1 of the Sex Discrimination Act 2 was replaced with the much broader “provision, criterion or practice” for important sections of the Act 1 (1), (2) (b) including employment. “The new definitions avoid the need to comply with the ‘absolute bar’ requirement in indirect discrimination casesD” (Middlemiss and Downie p. 368) The applicant has to show that the treatment complained of amounts to a “provision, criterion or practice”. “It may be a written or oral instruction or it could be part of a policy, procedure or collective agreement or be contained in a contract, letter or written particulars etc. It might refer to specific practices or be one of several criteria used. It could apply to just one employee or to a group of employees. It may even be sufficient to amount to a provision if the conduct complained of has happened on only one occasion. Common examples of PCPs include age limits, dress codes, refusal to allow part time working and imposition of mobility clauses.” (Middlemiss and Downie p. 368 – footnote omitted) The relevance of a particular pool for comparison Once the “provision, criterion or practice” is established, the applicant has to prove a “particular disadvantage”. The 2005 regulations removed some words, it may not be necessary to produce statistics to prove this, but statistics are likely to remain an important and commonly used method of establishing a “particular disadvantage”. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 368) This raises the question of the relevant pool for comparison. In Jones v University of Manchester [1993] IRLR 193 a 46 year-old woman was excluded as a student employment advisor because the university had an age limit of 27-35. The claim was that women students tended to be older and so the age range was discriminatory as fewer women could comply. The Court of Appeal rejected this and held the pool was all persons meeting the relevant criteria. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) The relevant pool is a matter of fact for the Employment tribunal to determine and they often want a broad pool. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) The courts have acknowledged that it is difficult to choose the correct pool. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) The Women and Equality Unit’s (2009) guide, Changes to Sex Discrimination Legislation in Great Britain: explaining the Employment Equality (Sex Discrimination) Regulations 2005, emphasises the usefulness of statistics in establishing “particular disadvantage”. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) ETC Graz 99 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Middlemiss and Downie think that the choice of comparator is more difficult in indirect ‘race’ discrimination as the Race Relations Act 1976 requires that the circumstance of the comparator must be the same or not materially different. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) Hanly v Norinchukin International – the case concerned the British workers being made redundant. The court held they could not use the Japanese workers on secondment from Japan as comparators as they were at no risk of dismissal. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 369) BMA v Chaudhury – on appeal the group for comparison was defined in such a way that nobody was in it. “It follows that there was no comparative disadvantage or advantage for any racial group and no indirect ‘race’ discrimination against members of the racial group to which Mr Chaudhury belonged.” (Middlemiss and Downie p. 370) Detriment The applicant must show that the inability to comply with the “provision, criterion or practice” caused him/her to suffer detriment as set out in the following cases: (Middlemiss and Downie p. 370) Ministry of Defence v Jeremiah [1979] IRLR 436 – “putting under a disadvantage” Schmidt v Austicks Bookshops Ltd [1977] IRLR 360 – it was not sufficient for a woman to be required to wear a dress under company rules. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 370) Ealing LBC v Gary [2001] IRLR 681 – detriment on basis of ‘race’ when an investigation into her behaviour took much longer than for others (the candidate was not aware of that at the time). Shamoon v Chief Constable of the Royal Ulster Constabulary [2003] IRLR 285 – Here it was a loss of right to carry out appraisal interviews. The House of Lords decided that an “unjustified sense of grievance” did not equal detriment. But the person did not have to suffer economic or physical consequences. However, if there were no economic or physical consequences then the “reasonable worker” test from Ministry of Defence v Jeremiah [1980] QB 87 had to be satisfied: “a detriment exists if a reasonable worker would or might take the view that the [treatment] was in all the circumstances to his detriment.” (quoted in Middlemiss and Downie p. 370) R exp Elias v S. of S. for Defence – “the focus is not on the difference in treatment on racial grounds, expressed or implied, it is on the evaluation of the disparate and adverse racial impact of the application of an apparently neutral and general provision, criterion or practice” (quoted in Middlemiss and Downie p. 370). Being forced to resign due to difficulty complying with a provision, criterion or practice would be evidence of detriment but the causal link needs to be established. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 370) ETC Graz 100 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Justification The defence of justification is often available for indirect sex and ‘race’ discrimination. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) Age discrimination – Employment Equality (Age) Regulations SI 2006/1031. Reg 3 – sets out the general objective justification defence for direct and indirect age discrimination. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) Ojutiku v MSC [1982] IRLR 418 CA – Court of Appeal - the standard for justification other than sex should be “what was acceptable to right thinking people as sound and tolerable reasons for adopting the practice in question.” (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) Bilka-Kaufhaus GmbH v Weber Von Hartz [1986] ECR 1607 – The approach of the ECJ here is now enshrined in statute. The standard of proof required – “the objective of the employer’s measure must correspond to a real need of the enterprise and the means used must be appropriate with a view to achieving that objective and be necessary to that end.” (quoted in Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) The employer must show that the action complained of was proportionate to achieving a legitimate aim. “The employer must demonstrate objectively justified factors which are unrelated to discrimination based on sex. The employer must show that there is real business need for the discriminatory outcome and the means chosen to achieve the outcome are suitable and necessary.” (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371 – footnote omitted) Hampson v Department of Education & Science [1989] IRLR 69 – • test for justification objective; • standard was the reasonable need of the undertaking; • the reasonable need might be (not confined to) economic or administrative efficiency; • Employment Tribunal must strike an objective balance between discriminatory effect of practice complained of and the reasonable need of the undertaking. R (on the application of Elias v Secretary of State for Defence [2006] IRLR 934 CA) – threepart test for proportionality: 1) Is the objective sufficiently important to justify limiting a fundamental right? 2) Is the measure rationally connected to the objective? 3) Are the means chosen no more than is necessary to accomplish the objective? A common justification employers try to use is health and safety. The British Airways case shows that this does not always succeed. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) Cost implications are another commonly attempted justification. “The ECJ has held that indirect discrimination cannot be justified by the aim of restricting public expenditure.” But private organizations can take cost into account. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 371) ETC Graz 101 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Conclusion Middlemiss and Downie note that the law remains complex and that the evidential burden on the claimant remains high. (Middlemiss and Downie p. 372) MORAWA, Alexander H E (2002): The Concept of Non-discrimination: An Introductory Comment, Journal of Ethnopolitics and Minority Issues in Europe Article 26 of the United Nations Covenant on Civil and Political Rights contains both positive and negative elements of discrimination. (Morawa p. 1) He begins by examining the negative elements of non-discrimination. Non-discrimination can be an accessory right (equality in regard to other substantive rights such as Article 14 of European Convention of Human Rights) or an independent right (demanding material justice such as Article 26 of the covenant and the new 12th Additional Protocol to the ECHR). (Morawa pp. 1 – 2) Morawa cites an important rule that is not often made explicit: “equal situations are to be treated equally and unequal situations differently”. (Morawa p. 2) Willis v the United Kingdom Eur Ct HR Appl 36042/97 “D[A] difference of treatment is discriminatory if it ‘has not objective and reasonable justification’, that is, if it does not pursue a ‘legitimate aim’ or if there is not a ‘reasonable relationship of proportionality between the means employed and the aims sought to be realised’”. “States will enjoy a certain margin of appreciation when adopting measures they deem necessary;'however, that margin will be quite narrow or, in other words, states would have to advance "very weighty reasons"" for their measures to survive judicial scrutiny, when a differentiation is based solely on what may be called a 'suspect criterion', such as ‘race’ or sex.” (Morawa p. 2) He then turns to free speech and the case of a journalist criticizing a politician requiring a broader interpretation of this than ordinary citizens. (Morawa pp. 3-4) He compares this to the case of a Basque politician and journalist, Mr Castells, who criticized the whole government. The court held that this requires an even broader right to freedom of expression. (Morawa pp. 4-5) Behind this differentiation of treatment is the importance of freedom of the press but also, Morawa suggests that politicians are less vulnerable to criticism and more powerful than ordinary citizens. (Morawa p. 5) Morawa goes on to cases of the judiciary “which is explicitly mentioned as an entity that can legitimately be protected against speech in paragraph 2 of Article 10. “ (Morawa p. 5) “It all boils down to the ‘proportionality’ and ‘reasonableness’ standards the Court speaks of in Willis, and to the extent of the ‘margin of appreciation’ a state may claim. Not every ETC Graz 102 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. distinction is prohibited, not absolute equality is required, but relative equality, or proportionality.” (Morawa p. 6) Morawa now turns to positive aspects of non-discrimination: “The 12th Additional Protocol to the European Convention adopted in 2000 elevates the 'European' right to non-discrimination firstly to an independent - no longer accessory - right and, secondly, to an at least somewhat positive obligation of states by stipulating that ‘the enjoyment of any right set forth by law shall be secured without discrimination on any ground such as sex, ‘race’, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other status.’ Thus, although it is ‘not intended to impose a general positive obligation on the Parties to take measures to prevent or remedy all instances of discrimination in relations between private persons,’ it may nevertheless under certain circumstances engage the responsibility of a state if it fails to provide adequate protection against discrimination stemming from non-state actors.” (Morawa p. 7, footnotes omitted) Again, Morawa identifies ‘vulnerability’ as the crucial factor in determining whether protection is adequate. (Morawa p. 7) X and Y v. the Netherlands: “a mentally handicapped sixteen-year old girl was sexually assaulted in a privately-run home for handicapped children, but neither she nor her father could press criminal charges against the perpetrator because a lacuna in domestic law prevented both the victim (who was not capable of signing a complaint herself) and her father (whose signature could not validly replace that of the victim) from formally initiating the proceedings.” In other words, the most vulnerable group – handicapped minors as victims of sexual assault – were prevented from filing criminal charges due to a gap in the law. The court, however, somehow avoided determining whether this was discrimination. (Morawa p. 8) Morawa raises the issue of affirmative action creating discrimination against other groups. (Morawa p. 10) “In sum, we may speak of three legal responses to different treatment: (a) where it is prohibited, (b) where it is permitted and, (c) where it is mandated. (a) Where situations are objectively equal, unequal treatment is prohibited, and so is equal treatment of situations that are different. For instance, men and women in Austria have "equal rights and duties [as] spouses, with regard to their income and mutual maintenance.' They both are eligible for (widow's or widower's) pensions after the death of their spouses. If widowers receive their pension payments only if they have no other source of income, while widows receive them irrespective of that, they are being discriminated against. By the same token, both nationals and foreigners lawfully ETC Graz 103 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. working in Austria contribute equally to the public social security schemes. If under such circumstances certain benefits are reserved for nationals that amounts to discrimination. In both cases, no reasonable and objective criteria exist that would justify a differentiation in treatment. (b) In many instances different treatment will be permitted. But even permissible differentiation faces its boundaries. It is, for instance, permissible to prescribe "differences between military and national alternative service and that such differences may, in a particular case, justify a longer period of service." But doubling the duration of the alternative service from 12 to 24 months solely to "test the sincerity of an individual's convictions" is not based on objective and reasonable criteria. (c) Finally, international law may mandate different treatment. That is the tricky part. The contributions in this special focus section will explore these issues further, especially those related to positive discrimination, affirmative action, and the protection of members of minority groups.” (Morawa pp. 10-11 footnotes omitted) NIELSEN, Ruth (2006): EU Law and Multiple Discrimination, CBS Law Studies, Copenhagen Business School, vgl. http://ir.lib.cbs.dk/download/ISBN/8791759013.pdf Problems and main perspective An initial point that is rather obvious but not always mentioned by others is that Nielson observes that different grounds of discrimination can be in conflict. For example, religion can be used to justify sexism etc. (Nielson p. 1 – citing the example of a case Leyla Sahin v Turkey, Application no 44774/98, where the rights of Turkish women were balanced against some Islamic practices) Nielsen notices the different historical developments of equality laws in the US and Europe, with the US (and UK) adopting ‘race’/ethnic anti-discrimination laws as one of their initial legislative anti-discrimination attempts alongside gender equality. In the EU, however, gender equality legislation came a decade before race legislation. (Nielson p. 2) Nielson outlines the development of intersectionality from its origins with African American women. (Nielson p. 2) She notes that in the EU nationality and gender where the only legal equality issues from 1958 for a period of about 40 years. (Nielson p. 2) Multiple discrimination was “Upractically not discussed in EU legal texts until the 1990’s. In the practical application of EU law by monitoring bodies, etc it is still mainly up to the national legal system whether or not multiple discrimination should be addressed.” (Nielson p. 3) ETC Graz 104 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “There is not much of an intersectionality approach in EU law apart from gendermainstreaming. One of the main answers in EU policy papers to the question how multiple discrimination should be tackled is by means of gender mainstreaming the fight against discrimination on any other ground (ethnic origin, religion, age, etc).” (Nielson p. 3) She identifies three main approaches of EU law to the issue of gender and society: 1) A gender-as a variable perspective - for example the US study that found black women got the worse price for cars, black men the next worse, then white women and white men got the best of all (Nielson p. 3); 2) A feminist standpoint perspective - for example, approaches that argue that women should be treated better (Nielson p. 3); 3) A late modern gendering perspective - for example, focusing “Uon the rules, institutions and processes through which gender is created and/or reconstructed. Gendermainstreaming is an example of a gendering process aimed at reconstructing genderD” (Nielson p. 4). “Gender equality is the opposite of gender inequality, not of gender difference, and aims to promote the full participation of women and men in society. Gender equality includes the right to be different. This means taking into account the existing differences among women and men, which are related to for example class, political opinion, religion, ethnicity, ‘race’ or sexual orientation, see further on the concepts below.” (Nielson p. 4 – footnote omitted) “There seems to be a trend at the EU level to treat some kinds of grounds of discrimination (eg ethnic origin) more favourably than others (eg religion). Experts on gender equality increasingly ask whether gender equality is becoming a second rank priority.” (Nielson p. 4 – footnote omitted) Overview of EU Law related to Multiple Discrimination From an Internal Market to a Fundamental Rights Perspective Early equality provisions were market orientated, but today equal treatment is protected by EU law mainly as a fundamental right. (Nielson p. 4) The Amsterdam Treaty (into force 1.5.1999) increased the number of articles dealing explicitly with gender equality from 1 to 5. This also signalled a growth of gender equality beyond the realm of employment law. (Nielson p. 5) Since the ruling in Defrenne (1978), the EU considers gender equality a fundamental right and general principle of law. (Nielson pp. 5 – 6 – footnote omitted) Free Movement within the Union ETC Graz 105 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. The EU Treaty guarantees the free movement of goods (Art 28), workers (Art 39), services (Art 49), and capital (Art 56) as well as freedom of establishment (Art 43) by prohibiting discrimination on grounds of nationality. (Nielson p. 6) Any discrimination on grounds of nationality is prohibited under Art 12. Art 18 allows every citizen of the union to move and reside freely within member states. Of course both of these have to be read in context. (Nielson p. 6) Note, too, that this is basically all confined to citizens of the EU. (Nielson pp. 6-7) The Ethnic Equality Directive (2000/43/EC) “The Ethnic Equality Directive (2000/43/EC) prohibits discrimination on the grounds of racial or ethnic origin, with a view to putting into effect in the Member States the principle of equal treatment. In the preamble to the Directive there is reference to the general human rights provisions. There is also explicit reference to the gendermainstreaming provision in Art 3(2) EC. The scope of the Directive is very broad.” (Nielson pp. 7 – 8) The list of areas (public and private) to which this applies is quite long. The Framework Employment Equality Directive (2000/78/EC) “The purpose of this Directive is to lay down a general framework for combating discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief, disability, age or sexual orientation as regards employment and occupation, with a view to putting into effect in the Member States the principle of equal treatment.” (Nielson p. 8) The ECJ in Mangold v Rüdiger Helm – “Uthe principle of non-discrimination on the grounds of age must thus be regarded as a general principle of Community Law.” (Nielson p. 9) As in the Ethnic Equality Directive (see above), the preamble mentions the fundamental rights background as well as mainstreaming, but the scope here is much narrower. (Nielson p. 9) The Gender Equality Directive (2004/113/EC) “Gender equality in employment and occupation is dealt with extensively in a number of legal texts including Treaty provisions and a number of directives. In 2004 the scope of the prohibition on ground of sex was extended to also cover access to and supply of goods and services.” (Nielson p. 9) Multiple Discrimination as a Specific Issue In recital 4 of a Community Action Programme launched by the Council of Europe, in reference to Art 3(2) EC it is mentioned that women were often the victims of multiple discrimination. (Nielson p. 9) In recital 5: ETC Graz 106 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “The different forms of discrimination cannot be ranked: all are equally intolerable. The programme is intended both to exchange existing good practice in the Member States and to develop new practice and policy for combating discrimination, including multiple discrimination.” (quoted in Nielson p. 10) This Programme ran from 2001-2006 and was meant to include a study on multiple discrimination. (Nielson p. 10) An annex to the programme also mentions multiple discrimination. (Nielson p. 10) Concepts of Discrimination Discrimination ILO law provides fairly comprehensive definitions of discrimination – it is concerned with the “Unullifying or impairing equality of opportunity or treatment in employment or occupation.” (Nielson p. 11) Direct Discrimination “Direct discrimination occurs where one person is treated less favourably, on grounds of sex, ethnic origin, or any other of the protected criteria than another is, has been or would be treated in a comparable situation.” (Nielson p. 12) Nielson then goes on to discuss cases of multiple discrimination. (Nielson p. 12) “Among women, pregnant women, single mothers and mothers of small children are probably those who are most exposed to discrimination.” (Nielson p. 12) Note that other articles suggest that it is migrant women (especially those from certain backgrounds) that are most vulnerable. “For men, sex discrimination often occurs in combination with age, eg discrimination against young men in car insurance or D discrimination against older men who have passed the pension age for women but have not reached the pension age for their own sex.” (Nielson p. 12) Nielson mentions the UK case, decided in the House of Lords, concerning free entry to a swimming pool for pensioners. (Nielson pp. 12 -13) Article 1(3) of the Directive on equal treatment in the provision of goods and services does provide an exception here to account, for example, for same sex session held in swimming pools. (Nielson p. 13) No defence against direct discrimination This is mostly true, however see above and also Article 6 of the Framework Equality Directive (2000/78/EC), which allows for direct age discrimination on certain conditions. (Nielson p. 13) ETC Graz 107 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Indirect Sex Discrimination Nielson notes that the current definition was influenced by an ECJ decision on the free movement of workers. (Nielson p. 14) “Indirect discrimination is in the current equality directive defined as situations where an apparently neutral provision, criterion or practice would put persons of one sex, ethnic origin, etc at a particular disadvantage compared with persons of the other sex, etc unless the provision, criterion or practice is objectively justified by a legitimate aim, and the means of achieving that aim are appropriate and necessary.” (Nielson p. 14) In Bilka the ECJ set out the three conditions to be met in order to justify indirect discrimination. “1) there must be a real need for the employer to apply the “suspect” criteria, 2) the means chosen by the employer must be necessary to achieve this goal, and 3) the means must be appropriate, ie there must be a reasonable proportion between end and means.” (Nielson p. 14) Harassment There is a distinction made between harassment and sexual harassment. (Nielson pp. 14 – 15) “Harassment (as different from sexual harassment) harassment occurs where unwanted conduct related to the sex, ethnic origin, etc of a person is exhibited with the purpose or effect of violating the dignity of a person and of creating an intimidating, hostile, degrading, humiliating or offensive environment.” (Nielson p. 14) Sexual Harassment “Sexual harassment is unwelcome physical, verbal or non-verbal conduct of a sexual nature.” (Nielson p. 15) Gendermainstreaming Definition(s) of the Concept of Gender Mainstreaming Nielson notes that “gendermainstreaming” is not clearly defined. (Nielson p. 15) Gendermainstreaming is addressed to law and policy makers at all levels. (Nielson p. 16) Article 3(2) EC creates an obligation for all Community actors to contribute to gender mainstreaming. There are considerable variations across countries. (Nielson p. 16) Methods of Gender Mainstreaming “Gender mainstreaming implies that the gender dimension is made visible and taken into account at an early stage of the planning and design of rules and policies before anyone has actually suffered discrimination so that sex discrimination (direct and indirect discrimination, harassment and sexual harassment) is prevented from happening. There is no general agreement on how this should be done. Different ETC Graz 108 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. actors use different methods, often of a socio-economic and not strictly legal nature.” (Nielson p. 17) Socio-economic methods Nielson cites the 3R method as it has been used in Sweden. (Nielson p. 18) Case law and academic legal literature Nielson argues for the usefulness of traditional legal sources such as case law and academic literature to make “Uthe gender dimension of a particular area of law visible”. (Nielson p. 18) Fragmentary duty to gender mainstream European law “The mainstreaming principle was first applied in the context of international development aid where it has been used since the mid 1980s.” (Nielson p. 19) The EU duty of gender mainstreaming EU has used soft law in the service of gender mainstreaming “Usince the early 1990’s in the field of employment and occupation and increasingly also in other fields such as development aid and research.” (Nielson p. 19) The Amsterdam Treaty reinforced the gender mainstreaming duty. See especially Articles 2 and 3. (Nielson p. 19) Also, see Article II-23 and Article III-3 of the draft Constitution for the EU. (Nielson p. 20) The ECJ Dory – AG Stix-Hackl argued that there is an obligation for the ECJ to interpret antidiscriminatory Community measures in light of the mainstreaming provision in Article 3(2) EC. (Nielson p. 20) National courts’ duty of gender mainstreaming under Community law Relevant cases – Colson and also Harz – obligation to interpret national law in conformity with Community law; and in Jongeneel Kaas the national courts were even described as community courts. Nielson concludes that national courts presumably have similar mainstreaming obligation to the ECJ. (Nielson p. 21) Positive action The Commission acknowledges that the equal treatment principle will not always be enough to overcome disadvantage and that sometimes positive action is necessary. (Nielson p. 21) Division of power between the EU and Member States Positive action is an option but there is no duty to undertake positive action. Positive action must also purpose a genuine equality purpose and not apply excessive means to achieve the (lawful) purpose. (Nielson p. 22) EU law Statutory positive action provisions in the EU law: ETC Graz 109 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. a) Article 141(4) EC which applies to working life b) Article II-23 of the draft Constitutional Treaty which applies to all areas of law including but not limited to employment. Nielson notes that this means that it is probably in accordance with EU law “Uto take positive action to support subgroups suffering from multiple discrimination.” (Nielson p. 23) The case law of the ECJ First, Nielson notes that Article 141(4) EC in the Amsterdam treaty overrides the old Article 2(4) of the Equal treatment Directive. (Nielson p. 23) Commission v France – women given special rights at work and this was allowed by French law. The Commission found that this was a problem for the Equal Treatment directive and France was ordered to amend its legislation. The main problem was that the law allowed for a too general exception and for an indefinite period. This was held to violate proportionality. (Nielson p. 25) Abrahamsson – this case addressed the interpretation of Article 141(4): “The ECJ confirmed that positive action aiming to promote women in those sectors of the public service where they are under-represented has to be considered as compatible with EU law. It clarified the conditions in which positive action can be applied and stated that the male and the female candidates must have equal or almost equal merits. The automatic and absolute preference of a candidate of the underrepresented sex who had a sufficient but lower qualification was by contrast incompatible with the principle of equal treatment.” (Nielson p. 25) Schorbus – in Germany preference was automatically given to men who had completed military service. (Nielson p. 25) The ECJ found that giving preference to persons who had completed military service was indeed indirect discrimination in favour of men, but that this provision was aiming to make up for the time lost to these men in their education etc. It was, therefore, objective and had equality as its aim and, being proportional, was not contrary to the Equal Treatment Directive. (Nielson p. 26) Lommers – Women were given priority in regard to nursery places in the Netherlands. Men could only get one if there was an emergency. This was held to be proportional and compatible with the Equal Treatment Directive. (Nielson p. 26) Nielson’s summary: “To sum up, the ECJ disallowed positive action measures in the Commission v France, Kalanke and Abrahamsson, and approved such measures in Marschall, Badeck, Schnorbus and Lommers. Positive action is unlawful if the measure is very general and applies for an indefinite period, or if the method selected is disproportionate to the aim pursued (Abrahamsson). There is considerable latitude for applying gender quota arrangements when appointing people to training places/positions (Badeck). Although priority may be given automatically to one sex as regards access to employment and ETC Graz 110 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. working conditions, eg nursery places (Schnorbus and Lommers), the opposite sex must not be excluded from all possibilities of obtaining a position or a working condition of the kind concerned (Kalanke, Marschall, Lommers). The general principle underlying ECJ case-law on positive action is that the principle of proportionality shall be observed. This means that any special measures that favour one sex shall serve a lawful purpose, they shall be appropriate and necessary for the attainment of this goal, and they must not go beyond what is necessary to attain it.” (Nielson p. 26) Enforcement and Monitoring of EU Equality Law Johnston – ECJ stated “Uthat all persons have the right to obtain an effective remedy in a competent court against measure which they consider to be contrary to the principle of equal treatment for men and women.” (Nielson p. 27) National Autonomy to Choose Remedies and Procedures In the absence of detailed EU rules, a lot is up to each Member State, for example, the choice of penalties, however “Utheir choice must be exercised with respect for the general EU law principles of equivalence, effectiveness and proportionality.” (Nielson p. 28) Commission v Greece – The ECJ set out the conditions for acceptable national rules. (Nielson p. 28) Article II-47 of the draft Constitutional Treaty provides for a right to an effective remedy and to a fair trial before a tribunal. (Nielson p. 28) Nielson notes: “A person who can only rely on the fundamental right not to be discriminated against on grounds of sex is, however, in a fairly weak position if she wants to enforce her right. If a door-step seller for example harasses a customer in her home the Directive on doorstep selling provides for no specific remedy but the national courts must follow the general principles of Community law and find an effective remedy.” (Nielson p. 29) Member States may also have to comply with Articles 7, 8 and 11 of the Directive of equal treatment in the access to and supply of goods and services. (The term “may” is used as this Directive had not been adopted yet and Nielson was not sure if it actually would be.) (Nielson p. 29) The principle of proportionality Colson – ECJ held that sanctions are necessary. No particular kind of sanction is required to implement the employment directives, but it should be “Usuch as to guarantee real and effective judicial protection. Moreover it must also have a real deterrent effect on the employer.” (Nielson p. 30) The principle of effectiveness ETC Graz 111 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Comet – where “UCommunity legislation does not specifically provide any penalty for an infringement or refers for that purpose to national laws, regulations and administrative provisions, Article 10 EC requires the Member States to take all measures necessary to guarantee the application and effectiveness of Community law.” (Nielson p. 30) Heylens – the ECJ found that there had to be a remedy of a judicial nature when a French Minister did not recognize a diploma. (Nielson p. 30) Johnston – the ECJ that this requirement is a general principle of community law. (Nielson p. 30) Colson – the ECJ found that a German rule providing for reliance damages was insufficient to act as a deterrent. (Nielson p. 31) The principle of equivalence UK – employers did not have to recognize voluntary trade unions: “The ECJ considered this state of law incompatible with the duty of the Member States to contribute to the effective application of Community law. In this case the UK treatment of information and consultation of employees in matters covered by Community law was the same as the treatment of information and consultation of employees in national matters not covered by Community law, namely a totally voluntary solution. The principle of equivalence was thus fulfilled but the principle of effectiveness was violated.” (Nielson p. 31) PAREKH, Serena (2007): Resisting “Dull and Torpid” Assent: Returning to the Debate Over the Foundations of Human Rights, Human Rights Quarterly 29, 754-778 Parekh divides common theories for the foundations of human rights into essentialist and non-essentialist, and then adds Hannah Arendt to the mix. Arendt discusses the impossibility of protecting human rights for the stateless in the time around the Second World War. (Parekh p. 756) Arendt was not a legal positivist, but she did think that human rights “...are made real only through human involvement and commitment, which can only occur within a political community.” (Parekh p. 757) She understood “the right to have rights” as the right to belong to humanity as part of a community, and she understood this both politically and ontologically. (Parekh p. 757) The contemporary debate on human rights The essentialist approach vs. non-essentialist approach: ETC Graz 112 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “The group labelled as essentialists are considered together because they base their justification of human rights on some essential feature of the human being or morality. Included in this camp are David Little, Jack Donnelly, and Amartya Sen. While there are certain advantages to this way of arguing, it is also particularly vulnerable to certain critiques outlined below. On the other hand, the anti-essentialists have explicitly sought ways to avoid an essentialist foundation for human rights. Michael Ignatieff, Richard Rorty, and Beth Singer derive three distinct ways of justifying human rights that do not rely on any essential property of human beings, nature, or morality.” (Parekh p. 763) The essentialist approach There were attempts to keep the language of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights neutral but, in the end, the assumption of the natural dignity of persons was included. (Parekh p. 763) David Little Parekh now discusses David Little’s account of the naturalness and objectivity of human rights in “The Nature and Basis of Human Rights”. (Parekh p. 764 ff) For Little “human rights are grounded upon moral norms which exist independently of human acknowledgement. D This view is based on a view of moral intuitionism – namely the wrongness of certain actions are so intuitively clear that they do not require further explanation or a theological ground to show why the action is wrong.” (Parekh p. 764) This rational intuitionalism is meant to be distinguishable from the sensational intuitionism of Hutcheson and Shaftsbury. (Parekh p. 765) Parekh questions whether all human rights violations are transparently wrong in this way and so rejects this approach as a suitable basis for human rights. (Parekh p. 765) Jack Donnelly Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice: “Donnelly argues for the universality of human rights which he understands as claims that are historically specific and contingent.” (Parekh p. 765) Donnelly discusses the possession paradox: “Dhaving human rights is only important when one is in some sense denied them.” In other words, this is the distinction between possessing a right and enforcing that right. (Parekh p. 766) Donnelly situates the source of human rights in “man’s moral nature” and says they are needed to sustain dignity (which he defines as the “inner (moral) nature and worth of the person”). As Parekh points out, this is a rather problematic position as Donnelly, is at the same time, suspicious of claims about human nature as such. “The problem with his view is ETC Graz 113 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. that to posit human rights emerge out of moral nature and inherent dignity is to posit a particular view of human nature, namely as being intrinsically moral and dignified.” It is difficult to see how this position can be reconciled with his claim that he is neutral in regard to a view of human nature. (Parekh pp. 766-767) Amartya Sen “Elements of a Theory of Human Rights”: “human rights are primarily ethical demands that can survive open and informed scrutiny.” (Parekh p. 767) Two aspects: first, human rights are primarily ethical rather than legal; second, they must be open to public debate, Rawlsian style. On the second point, they are, then, somewhat indeterminate and open to debate. (Parekh p. 767) “On the surface it is not immediately clear how Sen is an essentialist. What makes Sen an essentialist is that he seems to take for granted a kind of moral realism-that moral principles exist independently of human recognition or power relations, and that they simply need to be discovered. In other words, he is assuming that morality is in some way natural and independent of human action. Consequently his view is open to the usual critiques of moral scepticism. Sen does not take into account the argument that morality is a human convention that masks power relations, which is particularly important since his theory is intended to overcome scepticism.” (Parekh p. 767) Parekh also questions the public reasoning side of Sen’s view by pointing out that this is not neutral in regard to power relations and also that it gives too much importance to the role of reason. (Parekh p. 768) Summary of the essentialist positions “They have in common a reliance on metaphysical principles, though there is considerable variation in the principles on which they rely.” (Parekh p. 768) Parekh points out the advantage of essentialist views: they provide good reasons for human rights to be upheld. It also shows how human rights exist even when they are not recognized by institutions, so it is reasonable to demand them even when they are not legally enforceable. (Parekh pp. 768-769) Parekh also rehearses the common problems: can we really support claims about human nature or morality in this way and agree on the content? Parekh thinks these claims are, in fact, unsustainable in a “post-metaphysical environment” (Parekh p. 769) ETC Graz 114 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. The Anti-essentialist approach Michael Ignatieff For Ignatieff, human rights are political “Din the sense of being necessary for the adjudication of conflicts (although not necessarily to bring them to a resolution) and grounded on human history, not nature, the dignity of man, or morality. Ignatieff explicitly denies that there is something important about being human or having human dignity that is entitled to respect (as Jack Donnelly holds). According to what he calls a humanist position, there is nothing sacred about a human being and nothing that entitles us to ultimate respect. The only thing that can be said about human rights is that history has taught that they are necessary to prevent violence and abuse, and this is why they are needed.” (Parekh p. 769) Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry: He claims that human rights are like a secular religion, in that, being grounded in metaphysical assumptions; they are like an article of faith. He also thinks grounding human rights in human nature confuses “is” and “ought”. (Parekh p. 770) Rather than adopting a foundational approach, Ignatieff favours supporting human rights for what we know they can do for people. (Parekh p. 770) Parekh makes an interesting objection that if Ignatieff wants to hold that there is nothing special about humans, then it is difficult to see why we should bother with human rights to help them. (Parekh p. 770) Richard Rorty The starting point is deciding what counts as human because human rights violations are often inflicted on a group seen as less than human. (Parekh p. 770) He does not want to engage with foundational arguments but, rather, to make “human rights culture more self-conscious and more powerful.” (Parekh p. 771) “D [He] asserts that concern for human rights seems to come not from an increase in moral knowledge, but in hearing sad, sentimental stories. It is more efficient, he argues, if we concentrated our energies on ‘manipulating sentiments, on sentimental education.’ The purpose of such an education would be to encourage people to see others who are different than themselves as fully human.” (Parekh p. 771 – footnotes omitted) So Rorty is not interested in foundations and he wants human rights education to stop trying to be rational as it is a waste of time. (Parekh p. 771) Parekh points out, however, that Rorty does explain his own position in a rational manner. (Parekh p. 771) ETC Graz 115 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Beth Singer Singer rejects the a priori and essentialist accounts of human rights. “Instead she argues that human rights are conferred by a community through the establishment of norms and thus rights are not a priori or antecedent to membership in a community. This is because, in order for a right to be ‘operative,’ that is, for a right to exist, it must be institutionalized in a community.” (Parekh p. 772 – footnote omitted) If a right is not operative, this means that we think that persons should have this right, rather than that we have the right, but it is just not protected. (Parekh p. 772) “For Singer D human rights are characteristic of the communities in which they are operative, they are not the characteristics of persons, since rights are ultimately social institutions.” (Parekh p. 773) Parekh points out some gaps in Singer’s theory: “Singer does not explain why people enter this normative community in the first placeD. Further, she does not account for why we ‘ought’ to have human rights when we are denied them.” (Parekh p. 774) Summary of the Anti-essentialist positions • A refusal to employ metaphysical principles. • Not as forceful or convincing as essentialist theories. Arendt and the contemporary debate Parekh promotes Arendt’s position as a third way between essentialist and non-essentialist theories. She is non-essentialist in that she denies that we can know our essence or nature (and maybe even denies that we have such a thing). Instead, she sees us as conditioned beings and grounds human rights upon “the human condition, the conditions under which life is given to us.” (Parekh p. 774) Parekh claims that this does not “posit any natural features of human nature” (Parekh p. 775) Arendt is also distinct from non-essentialists: “For Arendt, human rights are the conditions which make possible human life, understood biologically and existentially, and consequently these rights are both important and necessary. Arendt's position, then, gives strong reason to believe in human rights without relying on a naturalistic conception of them. For Arendt, human rights which are created by determination create the possibility of both equality and distinction. For Arendt, equality is not something natural, but something for which we create the conditions. Yet equality is one of the conditions for political action-we can only act with others who are our equals. In this sense, the conditions for action rest upon human rights insofar as they guarantee our equality”. (Parekh p. 775) ETC Graz 116 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Conclusion Parekh expands on Arendt’s contribution to human rights: “For Arendt, the right to belong to a political community is primary for two reasons. First, it means that one's human rights can be protected by a government. Although they may exist in theory without government protection, Arendt's experience as a stateless person taught her that this step was no small part of the meaning of human rights. Second, belonging to a political community means that individuals have a place in the world where they can speak and act meaningfully. This means that life, in both its biological and existential sense, can be protected.” (Parekh p. 777) Importantly, Arendt’s theory makes it clear that stateless people need to be given the conditions under which their human rights can be realized (a political community) as a matter of utmost importance. (Parekh p. 777) Arendt also shows us why we need to be vigilant in relation to human rights. (Parekh p. 777) PATEL, Pragna (2003): Notes on Gender and Racial Discrimination: An urgent need to integrate an intersectional perspective to the examination und development of policies, strategies und remedies for gender and racial equality, vgl.: http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/csw/Patel45.htm Patel beschäftigt sich mit der Kombination von gender und „race“/ethnicity. Sie benennt die Schwierigkeiten einer lediglich eindimensionalen Sicht auf Diskriminierung. (Patel p. 9) Patel legt den Schwerpunkt auf häusliche Gewalt in Zusammenhang mit Einwanderungsrecht, Strafgerichtswesen und einem multikulturellen Ansatz. Gegen Ende des Artikels gibt Patel Empfehlungen für Regierungen und das UN System ab, um die Situation zu verbessern. ETC Graz 117 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. POST, Robert (2000): Prejudicial Appearances: The Antidiscrimination Law, California Law Review 88, 1 – 40, vgl: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/192# Logic of American Robert Post: Discussion of affirmative action (Santa Cruz ordinance). He claims that it was not about equality as such (in the sense of dragging everyone down to the same level) but, rather, about equality of opportunity, “...allowing all to compete on equal terms for the title of ‘best-qualified person’”. (Post p. 5) As the Santa Cruz ordinance was about discrimination on the grounds of appearance, Post also makes some observations about what this means in terms of self-expression and communication for both employer and potential employee: “The theme of self-expression, however, rests on the seemingly paradoxical notion that persons have the right both to use their appearance to communicate meanings, including messages of "threat," and simultaneously to require others to ignore these messages. If we concentrate on employment relationships, we can see that the selfdetermination of the employee must be set against the autonomy of the employer to present a particular image of her business.” (Post p. 5) The Santa Cruz ordinance tried to get around this by only banning discrimination based on those aspects of the candidate’s appearance that were beyond his/her control. The overarching ground the law tried to capture could be described as fairness. (Post pp. 5 – 6) Outlawing discrimination on the basis of appearance, however, seems very problematic as it is very vague, potentially very broad, and may lead to excessive government intervention. It may be described as the reductio ad absurdum of anti-discrimination law. (Post pp. 7 – 8) Summary of anti-discrimination law: “Antidiscrimination law in America characteristically presents itself according to a very definite logic. It is a logic that springs from a firm sense of the social reality of prejudice. Antidiscrimination law seeks to neutralize widespread forms of prejudice that pervasively disadvantage persons based upon inaccurate judgments about their worth or capacities.” (Post p. 8) Traits need not be immutable for discrimination to be unfair – for example, religion or marital status. (Post p. 8) Difference between judgments on a person’s worth and a person’s capacities: (Post p. 9) “Taken as a whole, American antidiscrimination law thus follows a simple but powerful logic. In the context of ‘race’-based discrimination, Paul Brest has authoritatively summarized this logic as an "antidiscrimination principle" that "lies at the core of most state and federal civil rights legislation," and that "disfavour[s] classifications and other decisions and practices that depend on the ‘race’... of the parties affected.' As a result, ETC Graz 118 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. American antidiscrimination law typically requires employers, except in exceptional and discrete circumstances such as affirmative action, to make decisions as if their employees did not exhibit forbidden characteristics, as if, for example, employees had no ‘race’ or sex. This is what underwrites the important trope of 'blindness" that "has played a dominant role in the interpretation of antidiscrimination prohibitions." (Post p. 11 – footnote omitted) Post questions how/whether it is possible for employers to act as if blind to all the characteristics of a person that would normally be relevant to everyday social life. (Post p. 12) Here Post discusses the Rawlsian “veil of ignorance” as something analogous and equally problematic. For Rawls this creates the “original position” from which we can view humans as rational beings with their own ends. (Post p. 12) Post points out that if anti-discrimination law is meant to strip people down to their intrinsic worth that this is no basis for comparison as our intrinsic worth is, by definition, equal. (Post p. 13) So, it cannot be that, rather antidiscrimination law wants people to be judged based on individual merit – in short, a person’s ability to perform the job. (Post p. 13) Another term used here is “functional rationality”. (Post p. 14) “For this reason, John Schaar has criticized the equality of opportunity celebrated by antidiscrimination laws as resting on a conception of the person that reduces her "to a bundle of abilities, an instrument valued according to its capacity for performing socially valued functions with more or less efficiency.” (Post p. 14 – footnote omitted) Post gives the example of orchestra auditions in the States where the auditionee is hidden behind a screen so that he/she is meant to be judged only on the sound produced. Four points from this: “First, it is no small irony that American antidiscrimination law, which springs from the noble liberal impulse to protect persons from the indignities of prejudicial mistreatment, should in the end unfold itself according to a logic that points unmistakably toward the instrumentalization of persons.” (Post p. 15) Second, it assumes that musicianship and job performance in general is not connected to gender. It assumes, in other words, that gender does not have an impact on the auditionee’s playing; that there is no “male” or “female” style. Third, the screen worked, in the sense that the number of women in orchestras increased. (This would seem to support the previously mentioned assumption.) Fourth, the screen could not continue into the actual employment – once the audition was over, the musician had to work with the orchestra is full view and could still be a victim of ongoing discrimination. Being a musician in an orchestra is not all about the music, but all aspects of the job. (Post pp. 15 – 16) ETC Graz 119 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Post wants to argue that “the dominant conception of American antidiscrimination law, distorts and masks the actual operation of that law, and by so doing, potentially undermines the law’s coherence and usefulness as a tool of transformative social policy.“ (Post p. 16) First Post points out that we have anti-discrimination laws on subjects like ‘race’ and gender as these matter to us, socially, in our cultural context. He then adds this to the fact that the law is also a social institution. Anti-discrimination law is, then, “... itself a social practice, which regulates other social practices, because the latter have become for one reason or another controversial.” (Post p. 17) Post then goes on to discuss sex discrimination as an example of the way the law tries to theorise itself in Rawlsian terms, but shows that it is really a social practice. He points out that we always encounter men and women, not non-sexed rational beings: “Sex is thus pervasively important in our understanding of the capacities of persons. This is as true for those who make and apply the law as it is for those whom the law seeks to regulate.” (Post p. 20) Post says that as we are not sexless, anti-sex-discrimination laws must mean that we are challenged to see sex differently, requiring us “to sever the connection between gender and some capacities, such as strength.” (Post p. 20) Post discusses the example of a security company that wanted an exception to allow discrimination and not hire women as guards because they argued that their customers considered women weaker and would therefore not use their company if they had women guards. This claims that gender is, in this case relevant to functional rationality and that functional rationality can reinforce traditional gender understandings. (Post pp. 20 - 21) “Sex blindness does not make sense unless these characteristics are understood to be fundamentally disconnected from functional rationality. The coherence of the dominant conception requires us to conceptualize the trait of musicianship as statistically distributed between the sexes, like the trait of physical strength”. (Post p. 21) It is not that women are necessarily worse as security guards; it is rather that the customers of the company think that they are. Therefore hiring women, even if just as strong as the male candidates, could hurt the company as its customers would be put off using them, as the customers may have the perception that women are weaker etc. Hence Post describes the problem as functional rationality rather than job performance as such. (Post p. 22) He points out that if the company is not profitable, that there are simply no jobs to perform, so he thinks that functional rationality takes precedence over job performance. What if functional rationality is affected by sex and gender? At least it sometimes is, says Post, so how about asking which capacities are not? Post then discusses Wilson v Southwest Airlines. The airline wanted an exception so that it would hire only attractive female flight attendants as this was crucial to its success as a ETC Graz 120 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. business. The court refused as it was an airline, so primarily a transport company rather than a business selling sex in some form. Sex was not relevant to employee capacities in a transport company. (Post pp. 22 – 23) Contrast this, however, with the case of Craft v Metromedia Inc, in which a female TV news anchor complained that she had to meet a higher and different standard of appearance to her male colleagues. The court held that the TV business expected presenters to dress to community accepted standards and that, in the conservative area in which this company operated, that included more feminine clothing for women etc. The court did not redefine the primary purpose of the business to clash with that argued by the company. So no distinction was made between “disseminating the news and the requirements of generating an audience” (Post pp. 24 – 25). Thus, the company could treat the anchor not as sexless, but as a woman, and so impose different drew code on her. A third case: Fesel v Masonic Home of Delaware Inc which refused to hire male nurse’s aides. (Post p. 25) Most of home’s residents were female and the aides had to do a lot of personal care. The court held that here the sex of the aide was crucial to job performance even though the preference for female aides was seen to rest on stereotypes. The stereotypes were seen as legitimate. (Post pp. 25 – 26) Contrast to Griffin v Michigan Department of Corrections, in which the court criticised the state for not allowing women to work in men’s prisons. The court stated that the policy was “...based on a stereotypical sexual characterization that a viewing of an inmate while nude or performing bodily functions, by a member of the opposite sex, is intrinsically more odious than the viewing by a member of one's own sex.“ (quoted in Post p. 27) What is the difference between these two cases? Post argues that this illustrates that as: “gender norms come to seem more fundamental to a court, it will be correspondingly more reluctant to disturb them. Norms that are fundamental are those that are significant and uncontroversial when seen from the perspective of those implementing the law.” (Post p. 28) Courts are very unwilling to stop employers imposing different standards of appearance, dress, grooming on the sexes as long as these are in line with community standards. (Post p. 29) Post contrasts the dominant perception of anti-discrimination law with his own, which he calls the sociological account. (Post p. 31) “According to the sociological account, antidiscrimination law must be seen as transforming preexisting social practices, such as ‘race’ or gender, by reconstructing the social identities of persons.' The sociological account does not ask whether "stereotypic impressions" can be eliminated tout court, but rather how the law alters and modifies such impressions.” (Post p. 31, footnote omitted) ETC Graz 121 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. It is not that the sociological account is always incompatible with the dominant account, (Post p. 31) but the sociological account can explain what is going on in court decisions in ways that the dominant account cannot – see, again, the previously discussed cases. (Post pp. 32 - 33) He also gives another personal appearance, grooming case Willingham v Macon Telegraph to show courts upholding sex-based differences in grooming standards as long as these conform to community expectations. (Post pp. 33 – 34) Because the dominant conception does not allow courts to discuss what is really going on, it also undermines the law’s “internal architecture and integrity” (Post p. 36) Also: “If the point of antidiscrimination law is to transform existing social practices, then courts must ask what purpose the law expects to accomplish by such transformations. The dominant conception systematically obscures this question.” (Post p. 36) And: “A virtue of the sociological account is that it has the capacity to tame this irresistible impulse to suppress explicit racial and gender classifications. If antidiscrimination law were to reorient itself around the project of purposively reshaping the social practices of ‘race’ and gender, explicit racial or gender classifications may or may not be suspect, depending upon whether they affect ‘race’ or gender practices in ways that are compatible with the purposes of the law.” (Post p. 38) Post thinks that Brennan managed this somewhat in United Steelworks v Weber and Johnson v Transportation Agency, by taking account of the historical context in those cases. (Post pp. 38 - 39) POTHIER, Dianne (2001): Connecting Grounds of Discrimination to Real Peoples’ Real Experiences, 13 Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 37 Pothier is in favour of retaining a grounds-based analysis. In support of her position in favour of specific, exhaustive grounds, she has an interesting historical example of a general call for “equality” being used in the American constitution to allow particular kinds of inequality to continue. That is, the general call for “equality” was less strong and demanding than if the grounds had been specified. (Pothier, p. 40) Introduction “The conclusion that emerges from this analysis is that a thorough understanding of the grounds of discrimination, including intersecting grounds, provides an opportunity for a more complex and richer understanding of equality of discrimination, which thereby enables anti-discrimination law to be relevant to real people’s real experiences.” (Pothier p. 39) ETC Graz 122 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Grounds of Discrimination: Distraction or Illumination? American Constitutional History shows a general ground of “equality” may actually have a limiting affect on discrimination claims. More limiting, that is, than when specific grounds are identified. (Pothier p. 40) Are grounds disconnected from real experiences? Pothier thinks, no, that instead grounds provide “U an important means of providing the necessary history and context of discrimination.” (Pothier p. 40) “Grounds of discrimination are not a purely legal construct. They reflect a political and social reality to which the law has, belatedly, given recognition.” (Pothier p. 41) Pothier critically discusses the approach of Canadian judge Justice L’Heureux-Dubé who prefers to move away from grounds to a more open definition of discrimination based on human dignity. The idea is to look at the impact (discriminatory effect) rather than the constituent elements (the grounds). Grounds would then become a secondary, rather than primary aspect of discrimination analysis. (Pothier p. 41) L’Heureux-Dubé also emphasizes the social vulnerability of affected individuals in determining whether discrimination has occurred. (Pothier 42) Pothier, however, wants to maintain grounds: “Using domestic workers as an example, the fact that they are predominantly immigrant women of colour is, in my assessment, of greater significance than simply background social context. The grounds of gender and ‘race’ are a crucial part of the explanation of why domestic workers have such poor working conditions and such weak legislative protection.” (Pothier p. 43) Human Rights Cases Grounds are central here. (Pothier p. 45) Gender Analysis British Columbia Government and Service and Employees’ Union v British Columbia (Public Service Employee Relations Commission) – Tawney Meiorin was laid off as a forest fire fighter after failing a fitness test (she had to run 2.5km in 11 min and she missed by 49 seconds). This test was likely to be more difficult for women than men. The Court decided the test was not a reasonably necessary occupation requirement. It had been designed based on the fire fighters working at the time which were mostly men. (Pothier p. 45) Pothier is critical of the judge’s attempt to play down the importance of grounds in reaching this decision. (Pothier p. 45) Disability Analysis The British Columbia (Superintendent of Motor Vehicles) v British Columbia (Council of Human Rights) – a bus driver was denied a license as there was a ban on anyone with a ETC Graz 123 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. certain eye condition holding such a license. The court emphasized that individual circumstances needed to be taken into account. (Pothier pp. 46 – 47) Quebec (Commission des droits de la personne et des droits de la jeunesse) v Boisbriand (City) – Pothier argues that this demonstrates how flexible a grounds-approach can be. These were three related cases where people were hired or fired based on medical conditions that were not producing any symptoms at the time. The employer wanted to avoid future problems. The ground in question was “handicap”; so the question was whether these people were “handicapped” or not. (Pothier p. 47) Again, Pothier thinks that analysis with regard to grounds is useful here: “The purpose of having protection against disability discrimination is not to give persons with disabilities a right to do things they cannot do. Rather, the dual purpose is to take proper account of what cannot be done owing to a disability as well as to give persons with disabilities the right to do things that they are able to do, notwithstanding any functional limitations, despite perceptions that they cannot do these things. Thus, protection against disability discrimination has everything to do with countering stereotypical perceptions of ability based on an able-bodied frame of reference.” (Pothier p. 48) Pothier points out that the employers were preoccupied with having “normal” employees – also into the future. She thinks it is important to understand that people who are not “normal” are more vulnerable to being excluded. The judge in the Boisbrand case also made a point about disability discrimination being about “Uobstacles to the full participation in society rather than on the condition or state of the individual”. (Pothier p. 48) Pothier sees nothing inherently contradictory between taking a relation approach and a grounds approach. (Pothier p. 49) Constitutional Jurisprudence It was in the context of the Charter that judge L’Heureux-Dubé spoke out against the grounds approach. (Pothier p. 49) ETC Graz 124 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. RAAB, Heike (2007): Intersektionalität in den Disability Studies. Zur Interdependenz von Behinderung, Heteronormativität und Geschlecht, in: WALDSCHMIDT, Anna (Hg.): Disability Studies, Kultursoziologie und Soziologie der Behinderung: Erkundungen in einem neuen Forschungsfeld, Bielefeld. Interdependenz von Behinderung, Heteronormativität und Geschlecht werden erörtert. Intersektionalität wird als Analysemodell verwendet, um der tatsächlichen Bandbreite von Behinderung gerecht zu werden. Die Analysekategorien sind nicht hierarisch geordnet. (Raab S. 128) Behinderung wird erörtert als soziokulturelle Praxis, in Zusammenhang mit Macht und sozialer Ungleichheit. (Raab S. 29) Konstruktionen von Behinderung bringen durch Abgrenzungsprozesse Differenzen hervor. „Rasse“, Geschlecht etc. sind Differenzierungskategorien. (Raab S. 133) SCHIEK, Dagmar (2009): From European Union Non-discrimination Law Towards Multidimensional Equality Law for Europe, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE, Victoria, European Union Non-Discrimination Law, Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law. Routledge Cavendish, London, New York. EU Gleichbehandlungsrecht ist multidimensional. Erstens in seinen konzeptionellen Ansätzen hinsichtlich Form und Inhalt, hinsichtlich der Frage, ob Individuen oder Gruppen adressiert werden und hinsichtlich der Frage, ob es um Ergebnisgleichheit (Gleichstellung) oder um Gleichbehandlung geht. Weiters ist es hinsichtlich Unterscheidungskriterien mehrdimensional. „The notion of der verpönten multi-dimensionality thus encompasses the interrelation of different conceptions of equality law as well as the intersections between discrimination grounds.” (S 3) Das geltende EU Nicht-Diskriminierungsrecht ist aus Art 13 EUV (Amsterdam) abgeleitet. Die Auswirkungen dieser Bestimmung wurden von den Staats- und Regierungschefs bei der Beschlussfassung wohl kaum bedacht. So kam die Kommission sehr schnell mit den Richtlinienvorschlägen für die RL 2000/43/EG zur Gleichbehandlung aufgrund der ethnischen Zugehörigkeit, die über die Grenzen von Arbeitsrecht und Sozialpolitik hinausgeht, und für die RL 2000/78/EG, welche mehrere Gründe umfasst, den Anwendungsbereich jedoch auf die Arbeitswelt (iwS) beschränkt. Der Sozialschutz wurde in letzterer ausgeklammert, findet sich traditionell in der Geschlechtergleichstellungsgesetzgebung. Bis dahin (2000) war der Rechtsschutz zur Gleichbehandlung auf Geschlecht und Nationalität beschränkt. RL 2002/73/EG und 2004/113/EG entwickelten die Gesetzgebung zur Geschlechtergleichstellung weiter. Letztere, die auch den Zugang zu Gütern und Dienstleistungen schützt geht allerdings nicht ETC Graz 125 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. so weit wie die RL 2000/43/EG und klammert die Bildung (aus nicht ersichtlichen Gründen) vom Gleichbehandlungsgebot aus. Die Genderdebatte unterstreicht die Spannung zwischen dem Gedanken der formalen und der materiellen Gleichheit. Der asymmetrische Charakter von Diskriminierungen in der gesellschaftlichen Realität und die Schwierigkeiten in der individuellen Rechtsdurchsetzung führten zur Forderung nach wirksamen Rechtsmitteln einerseits und begleitender institutioneller Unterstützung andererseits. Der EuGH hat diese Forderungen mit entsprechender Rechtsprechung unterstützt (Beispiele S. 4). In Art 3 EUV wurde eine Gender-Mainstreaming Klausel eingefügt. Durch die Diskussion im Vereinigten Königreich, dass trotz „Rassengleichheitsgesetzen“ institutioneller Rassismus persistent ist, entstand die Überlegung, durch positive Maßnahmen als Verpflichtung für Institutionen statt mittels individueller Rechtsdurchsetzung diese Defizite zu beseitigen. Diese Entwicklung wird als 4. Generation des Gleichbehandlungsrechts bezeichnet, allerdings fanden diese Überlegungen noch keinen Eingang in das europäische Gleichbehandlungsrecht (besser: Gleichstellungsrecht). All diese Entwicklungen und unterschiedlichen konzeptionellen Ansätze führten zu einem sehr fragmentierten Gleichbehandlungsrecht auf europäischer Ebene. Die konzeptionellen Ansätze sind zum Teil sogar widersprüchlich. Die RL, zusammen mit der Rechtsprechung des EuGH beinhalten substantielle Gleichheitsaspekte und gehen über formale Gleichbehandlungserfordernisse hinaus. Ein Beispiel dafür ist die Rechtsprechung und schließlich Normierung, dass die Diskriminierung von Schwangeren eine sexuelle Diskriminierung darstellt. Aufgrund der sozialen Realität sind asymmetrische Zugänge zu Gleichheit erforderlich. Außerdem sind die wechselseitigen Verbindungen der Diskriminierungsmotive zu beachten. Durch die Zersplitterung der Rechtsmaterie und durch die unterschiedlichen Schutzniveaus und Schutzbereiche ist dies allerdings erschwert. Dies führt zu einer essentialistischen Auslegung (Betonung durch den single-ground Ansatz) (S 6). Es ist an den Mitgliedsstaaten, einen „body of equality law“ zu entwickeln. Das EU Gleichbehandlungsrecht muss im Kontext der europäischen Integration gesehen werden. Diese hat sich von einem marktorientierten Projekt zu einem breiten Politikkonzept entwickelt, das im Vertrag von Lissabon gipfelte. Dabei steht die EU noch immer im Wettbewerb mit ihren Mitgliedsstaaten, was sich in der Sozialpolitik besonders ausdrückt, weil hier die Kompetenzen besonders zersplittert sind. Zu Beginn meinte man, durch einen gemeinsamen Markt harmonisiere sich die Wirtschaftspolitik, führe zu höherem Wohlstand und bringe damit ohne weitere Intervention sozialen Zusammenhalt hervor. Diese Meinung wurde wohl mit dem Vertrag von Maastricht aufgegeben, die EU blieb aber vorerst in erster ETC Graz 126 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Linie Wirtschaftsgemeinschaft. Nicht-Diskriminierung und Gleichstellung hatten jedenfalls einen hohen Stellenwert, sind sie doch auch Grundlagen für einen offenen und freien Markt. Dazu gehört auch die Mobilität von Arbeitskraft. Was also Marktintegration war, entwickelte sich zu einer Basis für individuelle Ansprüche auf Gleichbehandlung und Anerkennung von Qualifikationen. Die EU Bürgerschaft wurde mit dem Vertrag von Maastricht eingeführt (gleichzeitig mit der Währungsunion). Die Rechtsprechung des EuGH zum freien Personenverkehr hat zusätzlich auch den Zugang zum Wohlfahrtsstaat für Drittstaatsangehörige bzw. deren Angehörige geklärt. Citizenship und Nicht-Diskriminierung sind eng miteinander verbunden. Das zeigt sich nicht nur in Art 12 (Citizenship) und 13 (Gleichbehandlung) EUV. Die Bestimmungen begründen Gleichbehandlung von BürgerInnen unterschiedlicher Nationalitäten. EU Citizenship ist ein Beispiel „multipler Identität“ (S 8) und erfordert Diversity Management und Förderung von Integration. Nicht-Diskriminierungsrecht ist also eine Notwendigkeit für ein „cosmopolitan citizenship“. Gleichbehandlungsrecht geht weiter als Citizenship. Haben Drittstaatsangehörige einen Gleichbehandlungsrecht legalen geschützt. Aufenthaltsstatus, Weiters kann sind auch auch die RL sie durch das 2000/43/EG trotz Einschränkung dahin gehend interpretiert werden, dass auch im Immigrationsverfahren Gleichbehandlung geboten ist. Der Vertrag von Maastricht führte mit Art 6 EUV eine Referenz zu Menschenrechten ein. Für den Bereich der Gender-Gleichstellung war es schon früher der EuGH, der menschenrechtliche Gesichtspunkte vertrat. Die Rechtsprechung des EuGH ist eine wesentliche Quelle Menschenrechte, für die Entwicklung Citizenship-Law und eines gemeinsamen Grundrechtskatalogs. Nicht-Diskriminierung spielen in der Rechtsentwicklung der EU eine wechselwirkende Rolle. Zwischen Menschenrechten und Gleichbehandlungsrecht existieren aber auch Friktionen, zB in der Abwägung von Geschlechterungleichheit und Religionsfreiheit, wie am „hijab-enigma“ gezeigt wird (S 9). Das EU Gleichbehandlungsrecht ist auch weiter entwickelt als das Diskriminierungsverbot in der EMRK. Das kann zu Schwierigkeiten, insbesondere bei der Beurteilung von intersektionellen Fällen, führen. So ist zB zu erwarten, dass der EuGH Kopftuchverbote anders beurteilt als der EGMR. Das Gleichbehandlungsrecht als Diskriminierungsverbot entwickelt sich zum Gleichstellungsrecht unter Berücksichtigung von New Governance Ansätzen. Bislang konzentriert sich das EU-Gleichbehandlungsrecht auf das Diskriminierungsverbot samt Rechtsdurchsetzungsmöglichkeiten. Die Politik entwickelt sich jedoch in Richtung Gleichstellung. Das Verhältnis dieser beiden Entwicklungen ist noch ungeklärt (S 10). Die ETC Graz 127 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Debatte ist kontroversiell. Gleichheit bezeichne den gewünschten Zustand, welcher durch Gleichstellung und Diskriminierungsverbot herzustellen wäre (S 10). Zusätzlich zum Diskriminierungsverbot enthält der Vertrag von Amsterdam auch eine Verpflichtung zum Gender-Mainstreaming, der im Vertrag von Lissabon durch Art 3 (2) zu einer allgemeinen Verpflichtung zum Gleichbehandlungsmainstreaming erweitert wurde. Der Vertrag über die Arbeitsweise der EU nennt in Art 5a alle in Art 13 EUV genannten Gründe als Mainstreamingmaterie. Mainstreaming zielt auf Änderungen in den Politikinhalten in Form von Reorganisation, Verbesserung und Evaluation von Prozessen ab, um eine Gleichstellungsperspektive in allen Politikfeldern auf allen Ebenen in allen Phasen einzubeziehen. Mainstreaming ist demnach ein Instrument zur strukturellen Gleichstellung (new governance structures, S. 11). Mainstreaming beinhaltet partizipative Prozesse und soll im strukturellen Bereich eine größere und nachhaltigere Wirkung entfalten als traditionelles „hard law“. Die Open Method of Coordination (OMC) soll die Notwendigkeit von EU Gesetzgebung in sozialpolitischen Feldern umgehen. Mit diesem Instrument sollen die Mitgliedsstaaten überzeugt werden, Gleichstellungsziele durch freiwillige Maßnahmen und durch Lieferung und Austausch von Good Practice zu erreichen. Trotz der Erwartungen, die in die New Governance Structures gesetzt werden ist die individuelle Rechtsdurchsetzung für die von Intersektionalitäten betroffenen Menschen wichtig. Die Ausgewogenheit zwischen New Governance Instrumenten und durchsetzbaren Rechten ist noch zu finden. Die Herausforderungen für ein mehrdimensionales Gleichstellungsrecht sind vielfältig. Je mehr „Gründe“ das Anti-Diskriminierungsrecht umfasst, desto wahrscheinlicher wird es mit Mehrdimensionalität der Realität umgehen können. Das wird umso bedeutender in Situationen, in denen unterschiedliche Ausschließungsmechanismen wirken. Unterdrückung zu lokalisieren ist nicht notwendigerweise eine rechtliche Frage, Sozial- und Politikwissenschaft haben hier wesentliche Beiträge geleistet. Gleichstellung ist auch im Sinne von Interdisziplinarität mehrdimensional. Welche Formen von Mehrfachdiskriminierung sind zu unterscheiden? Mehrfachdiskriminierung oder Multidimensionale Gleichheit (Anm. als Synonym verwendet, S. 13) sind als Überbegriffe zu verstehen. Weiters werden additive und intersektionale Diskriminierung unterschieden. Additive Diskriminierung bezeichnet Diskriminierungen, bei denen mehrere separate Gründe (nebeneinander) wirken. Intersektionelle Diskriminierung ist eine unsichtbare Interaktion von Diskriminierungsgründen, die als solche betroffene Personen benachteiligt. Additive Diskriminierung ist weniger schwer zu fassen als intersektionelle, weil „alle“ Mitglieder von zB ethnischen Minderheiten dieselben Erfahrungen machten und „alle“ Frauen ebenfalls, während bei intersektioneller Diskriminierung eben ETC Graz 128 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. „nur“ Frauen mit einer ethnischen Minderheitenzugehörigkeit betroffen sind. Allerdings ist wiederum zu bezweifeln, ob es eine reine Form additiver Diskriminierung überhaupt gibt. (S 13) SCHIEK, Dagmar (2011): Organizing EU Equality Law around the Nodes of ‚Race‘, Gender and Disability, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, LAWSON, Anna: European Union NonDiscrimination Law and Intersectionality – Investigating the Triangle of Racial, Gender and Disability Discrimination, Ashgate. In diesem Artikel spricht sich Schiek für eine Ausweitung der Diskriminierungsgründe aus. Es würden mehr Fälle durch das Nicht-Diskriminierungsrecht abgedeckt werden, mehr Betroffene würden Gerechtigkeit erfahren und das öffentliche Bewusstsein würde steigen. Ein negativer Effekt ist die Hierarchie; das Feld könnte sich dadurch aufweichen. Um die positiven Effekte zu erreichen und die negativen zu vermeiden, strukturiert Schiek Diskriminierungsgründe um die drei „Knoten“: „Rasse“, Geschlecht und Behinderung. Im ersten Abschnitt Diskriminierungsgründen zeigt in Schiek den das unterschiedliche verschiedenen Ausmaß internationalen an verpönten Konventionen und Dokumenten auf. (Schiek S. 11-14) Sie befasst sich mit der Hierarchisierung der Diskriminierungsgründe und deren mangelnder Begründung bzw. wenig überzeugenden Rationalität. Die Gleichbehandlung aller Gründe (auch ausgeweitet) ist nicht unbedingt notwendig. Allerdings birgt die unterschiedliche Behandlung unterschiedlicher Gründe die Gefahr einer Hierarchisierung. Durch die Anordnung von Diskriminierungsgründen als Knoten kann eine Hierarchisierung vermieden werden. Jeder Knoten hat ein Zentrum (Geschlecht, „Rasse“ oder Behinderung) und eine Peripherie. Je nachdem können sich andere Gründe näher oder weiter entfernt vom Zentrum befinden. Durch das Überlappen können die Positionen anderer Gründe auch in Hinblick auf zwei oder sogar drei der Knoten bestimmt werden. (Schiek S. 19) Schiek begründet die Auswahl der drei Knoten sowohl über formale als auch über konzeptionelle Argumente. Formale Argumente sind die drei Nicht- Diskriminierungskonventionen der UN (CERD, CEDAW und CRPD). Konzeptionell ist der Zweck des Anti-Diskriminierungsrechtes. (Schiek S. 20 ff.) Gender hat die längste Tradition im EU Recht (Schiek S. 23): Verbunden mit diesem Knoten sollten sein: Diskriminierungen wegen Nicht-Erfüllens der mit der jeweiligen Gender-Rolle verbundenen Erwartung, sexuelle Orientierung, Schwangerschaft, sowie das nichtgendergerechte Erscheinungsbild einer Frau/eines Mannes. ETC Graz 129 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. „Rasse“ wird nach CERD definiert als: Hautfarbe, Sprache, Abstammung, nationale oder ethnische Herkunft. Schiek fügt dieser Liste Religion hinzu. (Schiek S. 25) Behinderung: In diese ohnehin schon weite Definition inkludiert Schiek noch Alter (Schiek S. 26), und eventuell auch Schwangerschaft als besonderen Zustand. Durch die Anordnung der Gründe in und um die Knoten herum, können Intersektionen besser fassbar werden. (Schiek S. 26-7) SHESTACK, Jerome J (1998): The Philosophic Foundations of Human Rights, Human Rights Quarterly 20, 201-234, vgl.: http://www.jstor.org/stable/762764 This article includes a quick tour of the historical development of human rights and the theories that accompanied this development. He cites religion; natural law (the autonomous individual); positivism; Marxism; the sociological approach and utilitarianism. He has quite positive things to say about religion as a source of human rights – citing the idea that we are all made in the image of God as a strong foundation for rights claims. (Shestack, p. 206) Under the natural law heading he discusses Locke and others and mentions a couple of the big problems with this theory: “Critics pointed out that most of the norm setting of natural rights theories contain a priori elements deduced by the norm setter. In short, the principal problem with natural law is that the rights considered to be natural can differ from theorist to theorist, depending upon their conceptions of nature”. (Shestack p. 208) The big criticism of positivism: “Under this view, rules of international law are not law but merely rules of positive morality set or imposed by opinion. Furthermore, by emphasizing the role of the nation state as the source of law, the positivist approach produces the view that the individual has no status in international law.” (Shestack p. 210) The problem with Marxism: “On an international level, Marxist theory proved incompatible with a functioning universal system of human rights. The prior claims of a Communist society do not recognize overruling by international norms.” (Shestack p. 211) On the sociological approach, Shestack gives a fleeting overview, primarily discussing Pound. He concludes: “The sociological school does not answer the logical question of how a normative conclusion about rights can be derived empirically from factual premises such as ETC Graz 130 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. having interests. A descriptive science in the social human rights field is helpful, ‘but is not enough’ to satisfy the need of goal identification. The sociological approach thus provides a useful method, but a method in need of a philosophy.” (Shestack p. 212, footnote omitted) In regard to utilitarianism, he briefly rehearses the theory of classical utilitarianism, using Bentham, and then outlines the standard criticism that utilitarianism does not take individuals or rights seriously and can lead to abuses of majoritarianism. (Shestack p. 214) Shestack now turns to modern (post World War II) theories of rights. He concludes that the dominant approach is a qualified natural rights theory. He sees Kant as the underlying theoretical driving force. (Shestack pp. 215-216) He then observes how this theoretical commitment to individual autonomy plays out in modern theories: “In variant forms, modern human rights core theories seem to be settling for concepts of natural necessity. By necessity one means prescribing a minimum definition of what it means to be human in any morally tolerable form of society. Put another way, some modes of treatment of human beings are so fundamental to the existence of anything that one would be willing to call a society that it makes better sense to treat an acceptance of them as constitutive of man or woman as a social being, rather than as an artificial convention.” (Shestack p. 216) This section closes with the question of how one moves from the foundation value of respect for autonomous individuals to a fully fleshed out system of rights. Rights based on Justice The section has a considerable discussion of Rawls, beginning with basics of the “veil of ignorance”. (Shestack p. 218 ff) “The answers given by those in the original position may then be taken as a blueprint, or as a pattern for the establishment of laws that are worthy of the universal assent of citizens everywhere.” (Shestack p. 218) And what will they chose? The two principles of justice, both aimed at “fairness”. The first is related specifically to liberty and the second to distributive justice: 1) "each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all." (Rawls, cited in Shestack p. 219, footnotes omitted) 2) "Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.” (Rawls, cited in Shestack p. 219, footnotes omitted) ETC Graz 131 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Shestack then outlines some problems for Rawls’ theory in the real world. In regard to the first principle, clashes can occur between liberty and “efficient measures to ensure public health and safety”: “To solve this conflict, Rawls suggests a Principle of Reconciliation under which basic liberties may be restricted only when methods of reasoning acceptable to all make it clear that unrestricted liberties will lead to consequences generally agreed to be harmful for all. This Principle of Reconciliation is that of the common interest. A basic liberty may be limited only in cases where there would be an advantage to the total system of basic liberty.” (Shestack p. 220) Shestack thinks that the problems with the second principle are more serious. A): Rawls is committed to equality of opportunity, but, in accounting for different starting points (educational levels etc), there may be tension between egalitarian and utilitarian approaches (such as controversy surrounding some affirmative action programmes). And B): and Shestack thinks more seriously, Rawls’ principle of a more equal distribution of economic benefits, raises questions of how much action should be taken here as it seems clear that this cannot be secured by mere negative restraints on government. (Shestack p. 221) And this is a problem domestically for individuals as well as internationally for disadvantaged nation-states. (Shestack p. 222) If it is accepted that some countries are disadvantaged due to the behaviour of other countries (colonialism etc), this provides a different and possibly stronger ground for redistribution of resources than if more developed countries think it is merely a utilitarian good or matter of self-interest (so worth helping disadvantaged countries in order to develop markets etc). (Shestack p. 222) Shestack mentions that Rawls’ theory may have been intended for domestic not international law, but that it still applies internationally. (Shestack p. 223) Rights based on reaction to injustice Here Shestack briefly discusses the theory of Cahn, who was in favour of identifying injustice from particular examples rather than justice as an abstract, theoretical concept. (Shestack pp. 224 – 225) Rights based on Dignity This is often a religious project; however Shestack cites McDougal, Lasswell and Chen as providing a secular expression of this idea. (Shestack p. 225). They provide a list of eight values that they believe flow from respect for human dignity and then an enormous list of demands that satisfy these values. Shestack criticizes this: ETC Graz 132 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “Their list of demands is huge; no hierarchical order exists; both trivial and serious claims are intertwined; and it has a utopian aspect that belies reality.” (Shestack p. 226) Rights based on equality of respect and concern Ronald Dworkin tries to reconcile natural rights and utilitarian theories. Under a broad utilitarian principle Dworkin thinks that states are permitted to do a lot to advance social welfare, however he thinks that some rights need to be protected, not because of their content but because these are the rights that would be limited if only utilitarian concerns are considered. (Shestack p. 227) Theory based on cultural relativism (versus universalism) Shestack is critical of the philosophical claims of cultural relativism. He points out that there were some traces in Greek philosophy, but that it was really Herder’s ideas that gave the theory strength in the 18th/ 19th century. “Johan Gottfried von Herder, dissenting from Enlightenment philosophy, claimed that all nations had a unique way of being; only regional and contingent principles existed. Condemning universal values, he introduced the concept of Volksgeist, the spirit of the people. Von Herder's view influenced German romanticism and French counterrevolutionary writers who glorified the aggregate of local customs and prejudices under an umbrella called ‘culture.’” (Shestack p. 229) Cultural relativism was also adopted post World War II as a way to counter the previously dominant colonial/imperialistic approach to non-Western cultures. (Shestack p. 229) Shestack thinks it cannot be sustained, however, and cites Finnis’ empirical research as proof that there are universal values, identifiable across all cultures as a matter of fact. (Shestack p. 231) More convincing is the evidence that “cultural relativism” is used by tyrants as a shield in order to behave terribly. (Shestack pp. 231-232) He then argues that some cultures are just bad and that suffering and abuse are simply not culturally authentic values. (Shestack p. 232) Also, cultural relativism often seems to view cultures as static, denying the fact that cultures change over time and in response to different circumstances. And modern technology has probably made change both, more likely and faster. (Shestack p. 232) Finally, history has overtaken this argument as human rights are now accepted internationally as universal. (Shestack p. 233) ETC Graz 133 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. SOILAND, Tove (2008): Die Verhältnisse gingen und die Kategorien kamen. Intersectionality oder vom Unbehagen an der amerikanischen Theorie, Querelles-Net, Rezensionszeitschrift für Frauen- und Geschlechterforschung 26, vgl.: http://www.querelles-net.de/index.php/qn/article/view/694/702. Im Intersectionality - Konzept vereinen sich zwei Strömungen: Eine, deren Erkenntnisinteresse Kategorien grundsätzlich kritisiert und eine, die versucht, die Komplexität sozialer Ungleichheitslagen adäquat zu erfassen. (Soiland p. 2) Im deutschsprachigen Raum ist vor allem letzteres bedeutend. Hier wird nach intersektionalen Betroffenheiten von Ungleichheitslagen gefragt. (Soiland p. 3) Untersuchungsobjekt sind hier Effekte von Segregation und die anschließende Frage, wie aufgrund dieser Segregation die Gruppen gedacht werden können. SOLANKE; Iyiola (2009): Stigma: A Limiting Principle Allowing MultipleConsciousness in Anti-Discrimination Law?, in: SCHIEK, Dagmar, CHEGE; Victoria, European Union Non-Discrimination Law, Comparative Perspectives on Multidimensional Equality Law. Routledge Cavendish, London, New York, 115-136. Solanke leitet den Aufsatz mit dem Fall Bahl vs. Law Society ein, wo der verhandlungsführende Richter feststellte, dass rassistische Diskriminierung und Gender Diskriminierung nicht als gemeinsamer Diskriminierungsgrund (combined single ground) geklagt werden können. Beide Motive seien separat zu behandeln. Daraus ist zu schließen, dass, wenn eine Schwarze Frau nicht Opfer einer Diskriminierung aufgrund der „Rasse“ und des Geschlechts sein kann, das Gesetz nicht mit komplexen Diskriminierungsfällen umgehen kann. Es bedarf daher einer Veränderung des Single-Ground Modells zu einem Bewusstsein multipler Identitäten (multiple-consciousness). Dazu sei es notwendig, argumentiert Solanke, über das Intersektionalitätskonzept hinauszugehen, weil es durch die Verwendung von „Diskriminierungsgründen“ auf die Logik der Unveränderbarkeit von Merkmalen (Immutability-concept) zurückgreift. Solanke stellt als Alternative die Idee des Stigmas vor. Immutability schafft begrenzte Kategorien, während Stigma ein Spektrum an Charakteristika ermöglicht, von denen unveränderliche Merkmale nur ein Aspekt sind (p. 117). Solanke argumentiert gegen das beschränkende Prinzip der Unveränderbarkeit, merkt jedoch an, dass Anti- Diskriminierungsrecht Beschränkungen in den Anwendungsbereichen benötige (ohne dieses Argument jedoch weiter auszuführen) (p. 118). Offensichtlich verwendet Solanke US-amerikanisches Recht als Referenz. Die Prüflogik folgt der Struktur zu fragen, ob Evidenz für eine Geschichte bezweckter (purposeful) Diskriminierung der benachteiligten „Gruppe“ gegeben sei, die „Gruppe“ nicht die Macht ETC Graz 134 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. besitzt, Abhilfe zu schaffen und in einer Art betroffen ist, dass das Ausmaß an Unfairness das Erfordernis gleichen Schutzes verletzt. Solanke geht von einem engen Intersektionalitätskonzept aus, nämlich der Intersektionalität zwischen „Gruppenmerkmalen“. „Intersectionality remains grounded in the logic of immutability.“ (p. 120) Stattdessen schlägt sie eine Gruppeneinteilung nach Stigmata als abgrenzendem Kriterium vor. Dies bedeutet zunächst lediglich, dass die konservativen Aspekte des Antidiskriminierungsrechts beibehalten werden. Solanke erwartet von der Anwendung des Stigmakonzepts offenbar ein Aufbrechen des Immutabilitykonzeptes. Es bleibt offen, ob damit ein anti-kategorialer Ansatz verfolgt wird oder ob sie damit lediglich eine Alternative als ungleichheitsgenerierendes Prinzip zur Bildung von Kategorisierungen vorschlägt. Stigma ist sicher als symbolische Repräsentation (vgl. Harding 1986) ein viel versprechendes Konzept. Es greift aber theoretisch zu kurz, weil es die strukturelle und individuelle Ebene kaum berücksichtigt. Solanke bezeichnet die von Stigma betroffenen Menschen wiederum als soziale Gruppen. Dies ist offenbar der gängigen Rechtspraxis geschuldet. Allerdings löst die Änderung des beschränkenden Prinzips nicht andere grundlegende Probleme des Single-ground approach. Warum sollte ein Gericht sich überschneidende Stigmata eher anerkennen als sich überschneidende unveränderliche Motive? Stigma löst freilich das Problem der „Enge“ der anerkannten Diskriminierungsgründe und wird den sozialen Realitäten besser gerecht. Bis zu einem gewissen Grad kann es das Problem der adäquaten Vergleichsperson dadurch lösen, dass das Stigma als solches den Kausalitätsbeweis darstellt, eine Vergleichsperson also nicht notwendig wird. Sie ist implizit vorhanden, indem durch das Stigma bereits die Unterschiedlichkeit und die Benachteiligung (durch negative Konnotation) belegt sind. Offen bleibt jedoch die wichtige Frage, ob durch die Betrachtung als soziale Gruppen (und nicht als Individuen) das Problem der konkreten, individuellen Betroffenheit adäquat behandelt werden kann. Insbesondere die Frage, wie dies zu geschehen habe, wäre zu klären. Welche Stigmata und deren Verbindung sind anzuerkennen? Sind nur diejenigen anzuerkennen, die eine soziale Gruppe schaffen oder auch andere, die ausschließlich individuell wirken? Ein spezifisches Problem der Intersektionalität ist ja, dass die Überschneidung von Kategorisierungen in einem konkreten Anlassfall und für eine individuell betroffene Person eine Individualisierung schafft, die durch Gruppenzugehörigkeit nicht adäquat gelöst werden kann. Solanke definiert Stigma als negativ konnotierte Zuschreibungen zu sozialen Kategorien wie Geschlecht, Hautfarbe usw. Stigma bezeichnet die Interaktion von Attribuierung und Stereotyp. Stigmata können auf unveränderbare oder temporäre Merkmale bezogen sein. Sie können rassistisch, physisch, verhaltensbezogen, ererbt, angeboren usw. sein. Sie beziehen sich auf einen kulturell-geographischen Kontext oder globale Gültigkeit haben. ETC Graz 135 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Stigmatisiert zu sein, bedeutet, von der Norm (Anm. wohl der mehrheitsgesellschaftlich definierten) ausgeschlossen zu sein. Stigmata wirken sozial-strukturierend und kontrollierend (Funktion), sind also machtbasiert. Entmenschlichung der betroffenen Person(en) ist der Wirkungsmechanismus des Stigmas. Die Verbindung mit Diskriminierung wird hergestellt, indem Stigma ie „Begründung“ liefert, Menschen unterschiedlich zu werten (als ungleich) (p. 121). Die rechtliche Analyse soll daher davon ausgehen, welche sozialen, politischen und wirtschaftlichen Konsequenzen mit einem (bestimmten) Stigma verbunden sind (p. 122). Die Analyse sollte dann folgende Fragen klären: - Worauf zielt das vorliegende Stigma ab? - Ist die betroffene, durch das Stigma abgegrenzte, beschränkte Gruppe „discrete, insular and powerless“? - Führen die Stigmata zu sozialen, politischen oder wirtschaftlichen Benachteiligungen? - Gibt es Hinweise, dass die Stigmata zur beklagten Behandlung beigetragen haben? Solanke demonstriert das Modell anhand eines britischen Falles. Die Eltern zweier Schwarzer Schüler klagen die Schulleitung auf rassistische Diskriminierung. Nach einer Rauferei zwischen zwei weißen und zwei Schwarzen Schülern werden letztere von der Schule verwiesen und in Folge ausgeschlossen. Das Gericht konnte in der Entscheidung keine rassistische Motivation seitens der Schulleitung erkennen. Solankes These ist jedoch, dass bei Berücksichtigung des Stigmas, das über junge, schwarze Männer vorherrscht, die Entscheidung hätte anders ausfallen müssen. Die Argumentation ist plausibel. Für die Praxis bleibt jedoch eine Reihe von Schwierigkeiten bestehen. Welches Stigma kann angeführt werden? Das „intersektionale“ Stigma im beschriebenen Fall ist durchaus geeignet, aber gilt das auch für andere, viel individualisiertere Kombinationen? Wie ginge eine betroffene Person damit um, wenn es kein argumentierbares Stigma gibt? Was, wenn das Gericht die Argumentation nicht anerkennt, welche „Ziele“ ein Stigma verfolgt? Ist dann bereits das Erfordernis der Plausibilität nicht erfüllt? Der Nachweis der sozialen, wirtschaftlichen und gar politischen Benachteiligung ist generell nicht einfach zu erbringen, bei vielen Kombinationen mangels statistischer Daten unmöglich. Diese Fragen sind keine Fundamentaleinwände gegen das Konzept, es bringt sicherlich eine Weiterentwicklung auf dem Weg zu einer realitätsnäheren Rechtspraxis, allerdings kann es für sich die rechtspraktischen Probleme nicht lösen. ETC Graz 136 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. SOLANKE, Iyiola (2009): Putting Race and Gender Together: A New Approach to Intersectionality, The modern law review, 72(5), 723-749, vgl: http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1468-2230.2009.00765.x/full Solanke advocates three steps to improve the European response to intersectional discrimination: 1) Clarify the qualitative difference of intersectional discrimination claims 2) Replace the conceptual framework of immutable, underlying grounds with something “...more aligned to social realities, such as stigma.” (Solanke p. 726) 3) Develop a method so that courts can incorporate social context into judicial decisionmaking. (Solanke, abstract p. 723) She follows an approach of Bob Watt to develop her own account of ‘social framework analysis’ (Solanke p. 726) Introduction Solanke sees no inherent reason for discrimination law to be organised in terms of categories. (Solanke p. 723) USA and Britain has an exhaustive list of categories, but Canada and the EU (in terms of the European Convention on Human Rights at least) do not. (Solanke p. 723) She gives a brief, historical outline of the way that discrimination was fought bit-by-bit, so that some groups such as black women were excluded. (Solanke pp. 723-724) “The single-issue focus did have an important advantage – it facilitated the creation of specific remedies which would to some extent be tailored to each bias. D In order for law to provide an effective remedy for persons who suffered detriment due to a particular characteristic, that characteristic had to be isolated and magnified, bracketed from all other aspects of identity.” (Solanke p. 724) However, the rigidity of these grounds has caused problems and this is clearly seen in intersectional cases. (Solanke p. 725) “The two European Union (EU) Directives based on Article 13 EC now mention multiple discrimination. Directive 2000/43 on equal treatment in relation to ‘race’ and ethnicity, and Directive 2000/78 establishing equal treatment in relation to religion or belief, disability, age and sexual orientation in employment and occupation state in their preambles that the Community, in implementing the principle of equal treatment, should ‘aim to eliminate inequalities, and to promote equality between man and women, especially since women are often the victims of multiple discrimination.’” (Solanke p. 725) Solanke’s approach is to compare and contrast first the two kinds of multiple discrimination (additive and intersectional) and then to compare and contrast how these varieties of ETC Graz 137 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. discrimination have been treated in the UK and the USA with comments about the EU as well. (Solanke p. 726) Additive and Intersectional Discrimination Solanke gives a quick, historical outline of the development of the recognition of multiple discrimination in the EU. Of particular interest is that she notes that it was in response to a resurgence of nationalism in Austria that the Commission submitted an Action Plan Against Racism and two Community Directives: Directive 2000/43 and directive 2000/78. Both called for multiple discrimination to be recognized, but without defining what it was. (Solanke p. 727) Additive discrimination is sex- or ‘race’-‘plus’. (Solanke p. 728) Nwoke v Government Legal Service shows that this can be successfully pleaded under UK law. A Nigerian woman applied for a post in the Government Legal Service and was given a very low ranking after the interview. All white applicants, even those less well-qualified, were graded higher. So this was ‘race’ discrimination. In addition, even the white women were unlikely to be offered a job and those that were got lower pay. This was sex discrimination. Another case of additive discrimination is Ali v North East Centre for Diversity and Racial Equality – a Pakistani Muslim woman harassed due to her sex and ‘race’. (Solanke p. 728) Solanke notes that tribunals in the UK have been sympathetic to intersectional claims but that Bahl shows that when these claims go to a higher court (Bahl was a court of Appeal case) that they are likely to be overturned. This is apparently the opposite of the situation in the USA where lower courts reject intersectional claims but then higher courts overturn these rulings. (Solanke pp. 729- 730) The cases where British tribunals have shown sympathy to intersectional claims are Lewis v Tabard Gardens – a black woman was treated very harshly after she criticized a colleague (Solanke pp. 729-730); and Mackie v G & N Car Sales – where an Indian woman was summarily dismissed when others would not have been. (Solanke p. 730) US cases where higher courts overruled unfavourable findings of lower courts: Jefferies v Harris City Commission – Federal Court overruled District Court to say that “Ublack women could be discriminated against even in the absence of discrimination against black men or white women.” (Solanke p. 730) And Degraffenreid v General Motors – Federal Court reversed District Court and said that “absent a clear Congressional statement of intent not to protect black women as a group distinct from women and blacks, it would not condone a result which leaves black women without a viable Title VII remedy.” (Solanke pp. 730-731) Also, Lam v University of Hawaii – The Federal Court rejected the District Court’s ‘mathematical’ approach of searching for distinct, separate evidence of racism and sexism. “The Federal Court rejected the reduction of the claim to distinct components as an attempt ETC Graz 138 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. to ‘bisect a person’s identity’ which would distort or ignore the particular nature of the migrant woman’s experiences.” (Solanke p. 731) Solanke notes that in Lam and Degraffenreid the US Federal Courts recognized that it was necessary to recognize intersectional discrimination, otherwise these women would have no remedy at all. But the UK courts have not discussed this. In fact, they seem to be under some false impressions such as when, in Bahl, Gibson J remarked that it was very rare to find a woman guilty of sex discrimination against another woman. “Underlying Justice Gibson’s remark is the erroneous assumption that the experiences of black women are analogous to those of white women.” (Solanke p. 731) The qualitative difference of ‘race’/gender intersectional discrimination Solanke uses empirical studies to make her point about the qualitative difference of intersectional discrimination. She outlines some of the stereotypes and prejudices that attach specifically to black women and the effects these have on their lives. (Solanke pp. 731-734) A qualitatively different approach Solanke now moves on to the second and third of her proposals for improving the treatment of intersectionality in British courts. Beyond immutability: stigma as a threshold concept Solanke suggests “stigma” as an alternative to the exhaustive list of grounds approach. (Solanke p. 736) This is, “stigma” is meant to provide guidance for an open-ended or nonexhaustive list of grounds such as that found in Article 15 of the Canadian charter of Rights. Solanke asks the question what currently guides the creation of ‘grounds’ in law. (Solanke p. 737) She argues that immutability has been a key concept here (so features where there is permanence and an absence of choice) (Solanke p. 737) However, the introduction of religion and sexual orientation show that immutability is not strictly adhered to now. But, nevertheless, traces of it remain. (Solanke p. 737) Solanke does not think immutability is a good principle for non-discrimination law. However, she does think that some kind of principle is needed to identify “socially salient” injustices and this is what “stigma” may do. (Solanke p. 738) Solanke recognizes that the breadth of the concept of “stigma” could work as both an advantage and disadvantage. To make it more manageable, Solanke proposes “Uthat discrimination law focus on those stigma(s) which are both difficult to escape and make a significant difference to individual access to and acquisition of resources in key areas, such as health, housing, education, training and employment. These are attributes which, even though not necessarily immutable, ‘tarnish’ the whole identity of an individual, so that other ETC Graz 139 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. ‘characteristics’ ‘are subordinated to or negated by this trait, which is immediately felt to be more central to the “actual” identity of the individual.” (Solanke p. 738, footnote omitted) The advantages of using “stigma”: “Ufirst, stigma legitimates the use of law beyond the permanent/produced dichotomy: it includes immutable characteristics but it not limited to them. Secondly, it is flexible enough to facilitate both additive and intersectional discrimination: discrimination can travel alone, but also in aggregate and interacting forms. However thirdly and perhaps most importantly, stigma widens the spotlight of discrimination law to situate the individual in society. Stigmas are by definition contextual: they are socially determined and maintained, and to focus on them is to prioritise social meanings.” (Solanke p. 739) ‘But for’ revisited Watt suggested a subjective nuance for ‘but for,’ but Solanke favours a social one. (Solanke p. 739) Discrimination under the Sex Discrimination Act 1975 Solanke cites James v Eastleigh Borough Council – the case where pensioners were able to get a discount for the local pool, but as the pension age for men is older than for women, Mr James brought a discrimination case. The case went all the way to the House of Lords where his claim was upheld – ‘but for’ his sex, Mr James would have received the same treatment as his wife. (Solanke p. 740) Solanke notes that Lord Ackner’s symmetrical approach excluded consideration of motive – the only two relevant questions were: 1) Had there been unfavourable treatment? 2) Did the complainant belong to a group protected by the act? (Solanke p. 740) Only Lord Griffith and Lord Lowry disagreed with this test with Griffith favouring a substantive approach that would consider both motive and context. (Solanke p. 740) Watt drew on Griffith and Lowry’s ideas to propose that motive be formally included in the assessment of discrimination: “In other words, did the respondent impose that unfavourable treatment because of the complainant’s membership of a group defined on the basis of a forbidden ground? DThe focus therefore moved from ‘but for’ to ‘but why’?” (Solanke p. 741) Solanke cites Shamoon v Chief Constable of the Royal Ulster Constabulary as evidence of the use of a ‘but why’ approach when Lord Nicholls encouraged tribunals to investigate why the claimant had been treated as she was and whether this reason was a prohibited ground. (Solanke p. 741) Network Rail Infrastructure Ltd v Griffiths-Henry – “Plainly there cannot be a finding of sex or ‘race’ discrimination every time an employer carries out a selection process unfairly to the detriment of somebody who is black or female.” (Solanke p. 741 – footnote omitted) ETC Graz 140 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. In order to incorporate social context (which Solanke thinks has not been sufficiently done), Solanke suggests that courts ask ‘but how?’ instead of ‘but why?’ (Solanke p. 741) “It encourages an observation of society in order to excavate deeply embedded stigmas and stereotypes which underlie discrimination. It does not ignore individual actions but throws a spotlight upon the context of actions to identify a relationship between a social stigma(s) and individual decision-making.” (Solanke p. 742) The social framework analysis Social framework analysis is used in the US. “Social framework analysis refers to the use of general social science research to ‘construct a frame of reference or set of background context for deciding factual issues crucial to the resolution of a specific case.’” (Solanke p. 742) In discrimination cases it is used to establish the role of discriminatory stereotypes. In employment discrimination it offers “Uinsight into the operation of stereotyping and bias in decision-making, social framework experts can help fact finders to assess other evidence more accurately.” (Solanke p. 742) Solanke outlines the use of the social framework analysis in a case of sex discrimination. There, a psychologist explained to the court that stereotyping may have influenced the partners at Price Waterhouse to reject the sole female candidate for a partnership. The female candidate was advised by a colleague to wear more make-up and behave in a more feminine way to help her chances. The evidence of the psychologist established that there was a general risk of discrimination as the management decision may have been influenced by stereotypes. (Solanke pp. 742-743) Beck v The Boeing Company; Dukes v Wal-Mart – both cases used experts to show how stereotyping may have informed company employment practices. (Solanke p. 743) Applying ‘but how?’ Experts are sometimes used in UK cases, but Solanke thinks there is no reason why the UK could not adopt the full US “social framework analysis” approach. This would work for intersectional discrimination. (Solanke p. 744) Bahl – what would have happened if a “social framework analysis” had been used? The Employment Tribunal would first have “Uasked whether there had been unfavourable treatment, and secondly by what means or to what extent stigma informed the unfavourable treatment complained of. In order to answer this second question, it would be necessary to consider whether any stigma attached to the group of which the defendant claimed membership, followed by the use of the social framework analysis to elucidate the nature and consequences of the stigma and finally an evaluation of the extent to which this stigma did or did not influence the decision complained of.” (Solanke p. 745) ETC Graz 141 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Solanke notes that Dr Bahl was a member of a stigmatized group. Also that charts, reports, personnel policies etc could have been brought as evidence of the culture of the law society. This culture could then have been placed in the context of stereotypes about black women and Solanke thinks that all this would have let the claim of intersectional discrimination be treated seriously even though the outcome might have been the same. (Solanke p. 746) Solanke also thinks that social science research could re-set the balance in regard to the burden of proof. Article 8(1) of the EU Race directive is now in the Race Relations Act through a new S. 54A. The burden is shifted if on regard to all the evidence (from both claimant and respondent) there is a prima facie case of racial discrimination. (Solanke p. 747) British courts now often take the explanation of the defendant into account at this initial stage. Solanke thinks that these explanations should be set within a wider social context. (Solanke p. 747) Conclusion “Intersectionality highlights that anti-discrimination laws have posited discrimination as a zero-sum game: if one form, then not the other. However, discrimination is not zerosum at all: it is often not just one of the other ground but can be many acting together in addition or intersecting. Victims of bias should not have to approach discrimination law as consumer, and make choices where none actually exist.” (Solanke p. 748) WALBY, Sylvia (2007): Complexity Theory, Systems Theory, and Multiple Intersecting Social Inequalities, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 37, 449-470 The article aims to use complexity theory to revise the concept of system in social theory. (Walby p. 449) “Not only is the intersection of gender with class important, but also those with ethnicities, nation, religion and other complex inequalities. While there is a wealth of empirical material on these intersections in sociology and other social sciences, their theorization remains difficult and contested. Their theorization as intersecting systems is challenged by the critique of the old systems theory, but the major alternative theorization within postmodern paradigm has a tendency to fragmentation and to micro or cultural reductionism especially in the use of the concept of identity.” (Walby p. 450) ETC Graz 142 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Intersectionality Walby describes intersectionality as “...a relatively new term to describe an old question in theorization of the relationship between different forms of social inequality.” (Walby p. 450) Walby argues for the importance of dealing with intersectionality as such, and not just double or triple disadvantage (the additive approach), as the disadvantages may at least in part constitute each other. Again, she emphasises that this is not a new idea, but that the Crenshaw work reshaped and revitalised the issue. (Walby p. 451) Walby identifies five different approaches to intersectionality, divided into two types: those that reject the concept of social system and those that use it. (Walby p. 451) She notes that intersectionality theories usually begin by pointing out the inadequacy of over generalisation in terms of class, ‘race’ etc, which is a good and straightforward point, but she is cautious about its links to “...a more general turn in social theory toward the particular and a critique of the so-called meta-narratives...” as this is more controversial. (Walby p. 451) The other main approach that intersectionality challenges is the reduction of multiple inequalities to one, overarching inequality. For example, to see everything in Marxist terms, would be to explain all inequality as reducible to class or capitalism explanations. In response to these theorists that first tried to include gender and class as articulating systems – this attracted criticism for its use of the concept of system. (Walby p. 451) A third approach is micro-reduction which grew out of rejecting “... the conceptualization of social relations in terms of systems.” (Walby p. 451) Intersectionality often focuses on neglected intersections, and does this by case studies, ethnographic and narrative methods on enquiry. But this interest in being ever more specific and particular is not without its own problems: “This has tended to become a strategy of seeking out ever finer units for analysis, in pursuit of a pure intersecting category. But, there are no pure groups; there are always more forms of difference; there will still always be some differences within the group being researched. There is also a tendency to cultural reductionism; and the use of rather static identity categories, even though it was a critique of the restrictive use of the concept of ‘identity’ that was the starting point for Crenshaw’s analysis. Furthermore, with such a micro approach it is hard to address larger questions, such as those involving a global horizon.” (Walby p. 452 – footnotes omitted) The fourth approach is the rejection of categories altogether: “Analytic categories were seen as not only never adequate representations of the lived world, but as indeed potentially pernicious in their potential for false sedimentation of these categories in practice. Hence a focus on difference was preferred to that on identity.” (Walby p. 452) Walby’s observation about deconstruction seems worth noting: ETC Graz 143 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. “However, such radical deconstruction and destabilization of categories makes substantive analysis, which requires distinctions between categories, rather hard.” (Walby p. 452- footnotes omitted) The fifth approach is the segregationary reductionist approach: “Rather than rejecting categories, instead the analytic strategy is to build up a better analysis of each of the sets of social inequalities as part of the process of analysing their intersection. Each set of social relations as identical or parallel, is considered to have a different ontological base.” (Walby p. 452 – footnotes omitted) “This approach segregates the bases of each of the categories: class is grounded in the economy; gender is a discourse about sexual and biological differences; ethnicity relates to discourses about exclusion and inclusion. The implication appears to be a relatively simple base-superstructure understanding of each set of social relations.” (Walby p. 453) Walby notes that this approach makes theorization in terms of intersectionality difficult: “Since each category has a separate ontological base, how can they, in theory, mutually constitute each other?” (Walby p. 453) Nevertheless, Walby sees the fifth approach as a step in the right direction, but advocates two improvements: “First, it is necessary to theorize more fully the ontological depth of each set of social relations. Rather than there being merely a single base to each of these sets of social relations, there is a much deeper ontology, including the full range of domains: economy, polity, violence nexus, and civil society. Within each domain (economy, polity, violence, civil society), there are multiple sets of social relations (e.g. gender, class, ethnicity). D. Second, it is necessary to theorize more fully the relationship between systems of social relations and how they affect each other together with the dynamics of social change.” (Walby p. 454 – footnotes omitted) Walby outlines why she believes that this approach has been seen as too theoretically problematic to adopt. ETC Graz 144 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. WINKER, Gabriele, DEGELE, Nina (2009): Intersektionalität. Zur Analyse sozialer Ungleichheiten, Transcript Verlag. Einleitungskapitel: Was ist Intersektionalität? (Degele und Winker p. 11) Die historischen Wurzeln der Intersektionalität bilden Erfahrungen schwarzer Frauen, insbesondere schwarzer Feministinnen. Als Konsequenz forderte die Verwobenheit zwischen verschiedenen Formen der Ungleichheit eine erweiterte Analyse von „Rasse“, Klasse und Geschlecht. (Degele und Winker p. 12) Crenshaw bringt 1989 dafür den Begriff der Intersektionalität auf und verwendet das Bild der Verkehrskreuzungen. Soiland kritisiert daran, dass sich der Vergleich mit Kreuzungen zu sehr auf die Zusammensetzung von Gruppen konzentriert, statt auf gesellschaftliche Verhältnisse. Daher sprechen sich manche für den Begriff der Interdependenz statt Intersektionalität aus (Dietze et al.): Der Begriff soll wechselseitige statt monodirektionale Abhängigkeiten beschreiben. Hier geht es nicht um wechselseitige Interaktion zwischen Kategorien, sondern darum, dass soziale Kategorien in sich selbst interdependent sind. Die Autorinnen sprechen sich allerdings gegen diesen Begriff aus, weil er das Problem auch nicht klarer mache. Es bleibt also die Frage offen, was als interdependent zu denken ist. (Degele und Winker p. 13) So sieht auch Davis die Aktualität gerade darin, dass das Konzept vage und unklar ist und sich darin viele verschiedene Richtungen tummeln, deren einzige Gemeinsamkeit “Geschlecht als zentrale Kategorie” ist. Es gibt zwei verschiedene Schwerpunkte: Während es in den USA um das Empowerment für diskriminierte Frauen geht, diskutiert man in Europa die Dezentrierung und Dekonstruktion von Geschlecht. In den USA gibt es nach wie vor die Kategorien von „race“, class und gender (triple oppression, vgl. Yuval oder Mehrfachunterdrückung vgl. Lutz), in Europa hingegen entstehen heftige Diskussionen über die Verwendung dieser Kategorien. Die Autorinnen verstehen Intersektionalität als Wechselwirkungen zwischen Ungleichheitskategorien. (Degele und Winker p. 14) Die Autorinnen bemühen sich um eine Definition, die empirisch geeignet ist. Sie möchten illustrieren, „wie die Verwobenheit von Ungleichheitskategorien auf verschiedenen Ebenen theoretisch zu fassen und im empirischen Forschungsprozess zu analysieren ist.” (Degele und Winker p. 15) Intersektionalität ist die an soziale Praxen ansetzende Wechselwirkung ungleichheitsgenerierender sozialer Strukturen (Herrschaftsverhältnisse), symbolischer Repräsentationen und Identitätskonstruktionen. Welche Kategorien wie verbinden? (Degele und Winker p. 15) ETC Graz 145 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. „Race, “ class und gender kommen aus dem US-amerikanischen Kontext und können nicht so einfach auf europäische Verhältnisse übertragen werden. Verloo und Weber etwa plädieren für vier Kategorien, mit Sexualität als vierte Kategorie. Lutz und Wennig schlagen 13 Linien der Differenz vor. Die Auswahl der Kategorien hängt immer vom untersuchten Gegenstand und der Untersuchungsebene ab. (Degele und Winker p. 16) Im Status Quo gibt es verschiedene Ungleichheitskategorein, sie sind kontextspezifisch verschieden wirksam und sie müssen über reduktionistische Ungleichheitsbeschreibungen hinauskommen. (Degele und Winker p. 18) Welche Ebenen wie verbinden? (Degele und Winker p. 18) Hier besteht bislang noch weniger Einigkeit als bei den Kategorien. Die Autorinnen schlagen daher einen Mehrebenenansatz vor (Degele und Winker p. 18): Dieser berücksichtigt sowohl gesellschaftliche Sozialstrukturen (auf der Makro- und Mesoebene), sowie Prozesse der Identitätsbildung (Mikroebene), als auch kulturelle Symbole. Auf den Ebenen von Sozialstrukturen wird Geschlecht als Strukturkategorie begriffen, das heißt als Ursache sozialer Ungleichheit, die sich nicht auf andere Ursachen reduzieren lässt. Ein Beispiel dafür ist die gesellschaftliche Ungleichheit von Männern und Frauen am Arbeitsmarkt und in der Familie, also die einfache Vergesellschaftung (Männer) und die doppelte Vergesellschaftung (Frauen nach Becker-Schmidt). (Degele und Winker p. 19) Den Prozess der Identitätsbildung erklären die Autorinnen nach dem Ansatz von West und Fenstermaker: AkteurInnen bringen ungleichheitsrelevante Kategorien in Interaktionen hervor (doing gender beschreibt den Prozess des Entstehens). Geschlecht ist (eine von mehreren) Kategorien, über die sich Personen selbst definieren. (Degele und Winker p. 20) Identität bezeichnet das Verhältnis zu sich selbst. Geschlecht ist ein Ergebnis sozialen Handelns, eine Leistung, die in Interaktionen immer wieder neu erbracht wird. Symbolische Repräsentationen sind Verbindung zwischen untersuchten Phänomenen und Prozessen mit Normen und Ideologien (Degele und Winker p. 20), wie beispielsweise Bilder, Ideen, Gedanken und Alltagswissen. Butler etwa legt dar, wie gender als kulturelle Form der Erfahrung dem Faktum sex zugrunde liegt. (Degele und Winker p. 21) Knapp oder McCall versuchen, Intersektionalität auf der strukturellen Ebene zu behandeln: Ihre Herangehensweise ist eine gesellschaftstheoretische. (Degele und Winker p. 22) Ansätze des doing difference beschäftigen sich hingegen nur mit Interaktionen, um Erfahrungen von Menschen und die damit verbundenen Identitätskonstruktionen zu beschreiben. ETC Graz 146 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Butler hingegen betrachtet die Ebene der symbolischen Repräsentationen und spricht sich für eine offene Kategorienliste aus. (Degele und Winker p. 23) Bourdieu und Giddens bemühen sich, zumindest zwei Ebenen miteinander zu verbinden. (Degele und Winker p. 23) Die Ebenen sind genau wie die Kategorien je nach Untersuchungsebene verschieden relevant. McDowell plädiert für Vergleich von Einzelfällen, wie auch von sozialen Gruppen, um über Fallstudien hinauszukommen. (Degele und Winker p. 24) Dazu sollen quantitative Analysen mit einbezogen werden. Zusammenfassung: Methode der Mehrebenenanalyse In ihrer Einleitung arbeiten die beiden Autorinnen die Diskussion auf, die zum Thema Intersektionalität und intersektionale Diskriminierung in den Anfängen der 1970er Jahren aufkam. Sie beschreiben, wie das Konzept der Intersektionalität zunächst rund um schwarze Frauen entstand, ehe es auch auf andere Ungleichheitskategorien ausgeweitet wurde. Die Diskussion, welche Differenzkategorien mit einbezogen werden sollen, hält allerdings immer noch an. Dabei bevorzugen ForscherInnen in den USA immer noch die Trias „race“, class und gender, während die europäische Forschung die Auswahl der Kategorien noch heftig diskutiert. Darüber hinaus ist noch die Frage offen, wie die Unterscheidung der ausgewählten Kategorien zu denken ist. Welche Untersuchungsebenen sollen gewählt werden? Die Autorinnen sprechen sich für drei Untersuchungsebenen aus (Degele und Winker p. 25): 1. Strukturebene: Strukturelle Herrschaftsverhältnisse Hier definieren die Autorinnen vier Kategorien: • Klasse: Vermögen, Bildung, Netzwerke ( Klassismen) • Geschlecht: biologisches Geschlecht, Geschlechtsidentität, Sex. Orientierung ( Heteronormativismen) • „Rasse“: Hautfarbe, Nationalität, Ethnie, Religion, Weltanschauung ( Rassismen) • Körper: Gesundheit/Schönheit, Alter, Behinderung ( Bodyismen) Diese vier Kategorien tragen in einem kapitalistischen System zur möglichst kostengünstigen Vermarktung der Ware Arbeitskraft bei (Degele und Winker p. 51). Über sie entstehen aber auch für die Individuen je nach Zugehörigkeit unterschiedliche Einkommensniveaus. 2. Repräsentationsebene: Symbolische Repräsentationen Normen, Werte und Stereotypen stützen die oben dargestellten Herrschaftsverhältnisse und tragen zu Identitätskonstruktionen bei. Im Neoliberalismus wird die Eigenverantwortung eines jeden Individuums betont (bei Körper und Klasse), nicht hinterfragt bleiben dagegen „Rasse“ und Geschlecht. ETC Graz 147 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. 3. Identitätsebene/Interaktionsebene Doing difference - Ansatz: Geschlecht entsteht gleichzeitig mit Ethnizität und Klasse. Relevante Kategorien auf dieser Ebene sind prinzipiell offen. Hier gibt es keine Einschränkungen. Verbunden sind diese drei Ebenen durch kapitalistische Akkumulation und durch soziale Praxen des Einzelnen. Subjekte entwerfen sich selbst durch Identitätskonstruktionen über soziale Praxen (Handeln und Sprechen), verstärken oder vermindern den Einfluss bestimmter symbolischer Repräsentationen und stützen gesellschaftliche Strukturen oder stellen sie in Frage. Diese drei Ebenen bilden aber auch den Rahmen für soziale Praxen. Methodologie: Praxeologischer Intersektionalitätsansatz (Degele und Winker p. 63) Verbindung der drei Ebenen durch einen an Bourdieu angelehnten praxeologischen Ansatz (das auf Körper und Wissen basierte Tun von Menschen, inklusive Sprechen). Die Analyse beginnt im Alltag der Menschen: Welche Probleme, Themen, Fragen bestimmen ihr alltägliches Tun? Welche Differenzkategorien nutzen Individuen, um sich selbst und ihren Alltag darzustellen? (Praktiken der Unterscheidung nach Wacquant, zitiert in Degele und Winker p. 64) Darauf aufbauend werden Strukturen und Repräsentationen analysiert, die diese Praxen fortschreiben und aus ihnen resultieren. Acht methodische Schritte der intersektionalen Analyse (Degele und Winker p. 79) Block I: Auswertung einzelner Interviews: 1. Identitätskonstruktionen beschreiben: Menschen beschreiben sich selbst mit Hilfe von Differenzierungskategorien. Diese können explizit oder implizit sein. Vor allem Privilegierte benennen keine Privilegien (z.B. weiße Männer in Führungspositionen). Möglichst alle Differenzierungskategorien sollen herausgeschrieben werden. 2. Symbolische Repräsentationen identifizieren: Werte, Normen, Ideologien explizit machen, die eine Person erwähnt. Stereotype, Erklärungen etc. notieren. 3. Bezüge zu Sozialstrukturen finden: Strukturelle Zusammenhänge (Gesetze etc.) herausarbeiten, auf die die interviewten Personen verweisen. Diese dann den vier Kategorien Klasse, Geschlecht, „Rasse“ und Körper zuordnen. 4. Wechselwirkungen zentraler Kategorien auf drei Ebenen benennen: Wichtigste Differenzierungskategorien für die jeweilige Person herausarbeiten, dann auf drei Ebenen beziehen. Block II: Analyse aller Interviews einer Untersuchung: 5. Identitätskonstruktionen vergleichen und clustern: Vergleich aller durchgeführten Interviews. ETC Graz 148 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. 6. Strukturdaten ergänzen und Herrschaftsverhältnisse analysieren: Auf der Strukturebene sollen zusätzliche Datenquellen mit einbezogen werden. Strukturelle Herrschaftsverhältnisse analysieren. 7. Analyse von benannten Repräsentationen vertiefen: Zusätzliche Datenquellen mit einbeziehen. 8. Wechselwirkungen in der Gesamtschau herausarbeiten: Verallgemeinerungen jenseits des einzelnen Falls herausarbeiten. Beispielhaft wird die intersektionale Mehrebenanalyse dann in der Auswertung durchgeführter Interviews mit nicht erwerbstätigen Frauen dargestellt. (Degele und Winker S. 99) WINKER, Gabriele, DEGELE, Nina (2011): Intersectionality as Multi-level Analysis: Dealing with social inequality, European Journal of Women’s Studies 18, 51-66 This article is basically an English language summary of their book. The style is rather dense. They identify a lack of attention being given to methodology in intersectional literature. They follow Leslie McCall and also Sylvia Walby in identifying three versions of complexity currently discussed in intersectionality: anticategorical, intracategorical and intercategorical. Each of these has a different focus. Winker and Degele want to adopt “...a multi-level intersectional approach that encompasses differentiation and inequality on the levels of representation, identity and structure.” (Winker and Degele p. 53) Further: “We suggest a multi-level approach in line with the epistemological reflections of Sandra Harding (1986) when she discusses the symbolic, structural and individual aspects of social genders. Accordingly, we understand intersectionality as a system of interactions between inequality-creating social structures (i.e. of power relations), symbolic representations and identity constructions that are context-specific, topicorientated and inextricably linked to social praxis. The multi-level approach we suggest will be able to analyse the interactions of categories of difference on both a single level and throughout all three levels.” (Winker and Degele p. 54) They identify three structural levels: • Identity constructions • Symbolic representations • Social structures ETC Graz 149 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. Praxeological intersectionality “The three structural levels we are concentrating on are linked through the social practices of individuals. Through social practices like social action and speech, individuals delineate themselves in social contexts, construct identities, process symbolic representations, support social structures or challenge them. Conversely, the three aforementioned levels construct a framework for social practice. Thus, social practices are intrinsically linked to each other through categories of difference and those three levels. For this reason it is social practices that serve as the methodological starting point of our intersectional multi-level analysis.” (Winker and Degele p. 56) Note that Winker and Degele here are following Bourdieu’s “Theory of Practice”. Intersectional analysis in eight steps pp. 58 - 62 Step 1: Describing identity constructions Step 2: Indentifying symbolic representations Step 3: Finding references to social structures Step 4: Denominating interrelations of central categories on three levels Step 5: Comparing and clustering of subject constructions Step 6: Supplementing structural data and analysing power relations Step 7: Deepening the analysis of denominated representations Step 8: Elaborating interrelations in the overall demonstration ETC Graz 150 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. CASES Bahl v The Law Society, also known as The Law Society v Bahl [2003] I.R.L.R. 640; (2003) 147 S.J.L.B. 994 The sexism and racism claims were not the original point but came in response to allegations of bullying made against Dr Bahl. She was viewed as a very, very unsympathetic figure. This may have had an impact on the outcome. The tribunal mentions at the outset that some of her claims are ridiculous and so seems to agree with her ex-colleagues that she is a difficult trouble-maker. Of course a question might be whether this very negative perception of Dr Bahl was a result of racial and gender stereotypes etc. The recitation of the facts does not really explain why she was so disliked. For example, is it not possible to argue that, yes, she was authoritarian and rude, but many white male CEOs act like this and are seen as real, decisive leaders? The account of the facts leading up to the allegation of sex and ‘race’ discrimination is very depressing reading. It is the record of a lot of personal squabbling at work that got very nasty indeed. Dr Bahl had a long history of antagonizing people at work (she is described as a bully) and the reactions to this built and built. Eventually everyone turned on her and it became really unpleasant and personal – it is at this stage that the allegations of ‘race’ and sex discrimination emerge. Arguably there is at least the appearance of a bitter element of revenge in the behaviour of the law society members when the momentum swung the way of attacking Dr Bahl. Direct discrimination: undisputed principles - paras 80 -90 Grounds of appeal – including specifically that it is an error in law to deal with discrimination intersectionally rather than ground by ground – paras 154 on 158. Plainly it is possible for a tribunal to infer that there may be discrimination both on grounds of ‘race’ and sex after considering the evidence in respect of each. But if the evidence does not satisfy the tribunal that there is discrimination on grounds of ‘race’ or on grounds of sex, considered independently, then it is not open to a tribunal to find either claim satisfied on the basis that there is nonetheless discrimination on grounds of ‘race’ and sex when both are taken together. That would fail to give effect to the fact that the burden of proof is on the applicant. Nor can the tribunal properly conclude, if it is uncertain about whether it is ‘race’ or sex, that it will find both. One disturbing aspect of this is that the failure to disentangle the grounds of ‘race’ and sex is linked to a failure of reasoning, or, more specifically, of clarity of reasoning. Tribunal also did not identify a hypothetical comparator (I think it would need to have two – one for each ground). ETC Graz 151 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. There is a lot of discussion about the antagonism and hostility and the importance of proving that this had a discriminatory basis or character. Also, the situation is complicated as Dr Bahl was hired partly to provide diversity to the law society and partly to reform the law society, yet it may be that they did not want to change in fact. Her approach and reforms were, perhaps, a step too far for the culture of the law society and what were originally viewed as Dr Bahl’s strengths became problems for the law society. Perhaps this points to a difficult aspect of discrimination: the way in which Dr Bahl performed her job, the very things that her colleagues were unhappy with, could have had cultural and/or gendered aspects. The use of the hypothetical comparator here shows that the white, middle-class male is indeed the norm. This conceptual situation seems to be almost this: that it is discrimination if this person (who is not a white, middle-class male) was acting like a white, middle-class male, and yet not treated as well as a white, middle-class male. Immediately there is a problem even with this, however: as it has often been noted that behaviour that would, for example, be considered assertive in a white, middle-class male, might be considered rude or aggressive when performed by a woman or someone of a different ‘race’ or class. Anti-discrimination legislation still seems to work on the myths that 1) we all interact with each other behind a Rawlsian veil of ignorance and 2) that there is a neutral, human space that is genderless, ‘race’less etc. O’Reilly v BBC In the tribunal case of O’Reilly v BBC, the BBC tried a line of defence that stated that it had discriminated against O’Reilly on the combined basis of her age and sex and that this was not prohibited under English law (relying on Bahl). The tribunal rejected this. However, it should be noted that the tribunal was also sympathetic to the intersectional argument in Bahl and yet the Court of Appeal dismissed this. How can this be reconciled? One suggestion from the O’Reilly judgement itself, is that the Bahl decision should not be understood as rejecting intersectional discrimination as such as that it pointed out that, in that case, there was insufficient evidence to ground a claim of either sex or ‘race’ discrimination, even considering that neither sex nor ‘race’ discrimination would need to be the sole cause of the bad treatment, but only a significant cause. O’Reilly v BBC was only a tribunal decision at first instance. It is not binding. It has been published, however, and subject to considerable attention, both of which are unusual, so the signals are that this may indeed be a good indication of the current state of English law on this point. ETC Graz 152 Literature Review Apostolovski, V./Philipp, S./Smith, S./Starl, K. To sum it up on para 245: “...the prescribed reason need not be the sole reason, or even the principal reason, why a person suffers detrimental treatment. Part of the reason that a woman over 40 is precluded from applying for a job, in the above example, is that fact that she is a woman. Another part of the reason is that she is over 40. Both of them are significant elements of the reason that she suffers the detriment. In such circumstances, we consider it is clear that the woman is subject to both sex and age discrimination.” Note that O’Reilly actually only succeeded on the age discrimination claim, though, and not the sex discrimination claim. The issue we might ask is this: given that her treatment did seem to be on the basis of being an older woman, why do the courts chose one characteristic and not the other? They can see that discrimination exists, but the current UK law does not allow them the concept of intersectional discrimination as such to describe it accurately. The choice in terms of which characteristic or both, seems rather arbitrary and again, comes down to the question of the choice of comparator. And para 246: “The way that this can be fitted with the comparative exercise set out in the legislation is that a woman over 40 can compare her treatment to a man over 40; by which exercise the sex discrimination element of her treatment is established. Similarly, the woman over 40 can compare her treatment to another person under 40, thereby establishing the age discrimination element.” This confirms that two separate comparators are required. The woman over 40 is not compared to a man under 40 but to a man over 40 for sex discrimination and to a man or woman under 40 for the age discrimination requirement. And para 248 on why Bahl failed: “The error was not as to the possibility of there being combined discrimination, which was not expressly considered in the case; but of analysis of the evidence which requires a conclusion that age and/or sex were significant factors in the decision that was made before liability can be established. It is not sufficient to conclude that the evidence does not support a finding of either sex or age discrimination, but that it must be one or the other, or both.” So this is still anti-intersectional, but the thinking of practitioners (and this includes those sitting on the tribunal) seems to be that this would hardly ever have an impact in a real case. That is, because the grounds need only be a significant cause of the disadvantage and not the sole or primary cause, many cases of combined discrimination may be able to meet this requirement. There seems to be a statement of faith that intersectional discrimination can be dealt with well-enough as if it were additive or single-ground discrimination. When the tribunal here talks of “combined” discrimination, then, one should probably read “additive” discrimination. ETC Graz 153