12 Estates and the Problem of Resistance in Theory
Transcription
12 Estates and the Problem of Resistance in Theory
Winfried Schulze 12 Estates and the Problem of Resistance in Theory and Practice in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries Winfried Schulze From the modern perspective, Central and East-Central Europe at the end of the sixteenth and the beginning of the seventeenth century seem to present a reasonably clear and unequivocal political picture. 1 need describe it only briefly here since its essential features were determined by the victory of the princes. As the confessional territorial state developed, the princes' sphere of responsibility expanded. The princely state gained control over areas previously ruled autonomously by the nobility: it guaranteed the uniformity of religion; organised and regulated new forms of judicial proceedings; collected increasing tax revenues; appointed university professors and the like; conducted ecclesiasticat visitations; and guaranteed the existing social order. All this fits into a long-term pattern leading from the beginnings of the consolidation of dynasties and secular rule in the Tate Middle Ages to the trend towards bureaucratisation characteristic of the late eighteenth century. The years around 1600, which particularly interest us here, are of special significance in this context. After the various crises of the sixteenth century, the outlines of the early modern state emerged and were consolidated at that time, a process which became apparent first in the financial side of the state's activities, then in its military, economic and administrative functions. Gerhard Oestreich dates these developments specifically to the Tate sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. This picture, which has been so shaped by historical evolution that it now seems self-evident to us, can be contrasted with a 158 159 different view of our period and of the significance of the estates within it. If we adopt the perspective of the time itself and try to reconstruct the openness of its political alternatives, we see, from the point of view of the estates, a situation characterised by the princes' increasing and threatening interference in the existing system of privileges. Provincial nobilities saw themselves being ousted from traditional administrative positions and replaced by `landfremde Doktoren', foreign university-trained officials, who were regarded, not unjustifiably, as the princes' witling henchmen in weakening the rights of the noble estates. The implementation of Counter-Reformation measures was seen as breaking valid agreements anas an attack on the organic religious and political culture of the Landschaft. Regularly repeated tax demands were regarded as a new, `outrageous' burden, whose imposition deviated from the traditional practices of the princes' financial administration and attempted to place the estates in thrall instead. From the princes' point of view, by contrast, any estates' refusal to graut taxes looked like an attack on the ruler's slowly developing sovereignty. Modest attempts by the estates to achieve administrative autonomy were regarded as emanating from dangerous centres of resistance; similar disapproval was expressed of independence in religious policy. In short, princes and estates observed Bach other with suspicion; neither side could know that their confrontation was to be merely an episode in the development of the modern state. This was, then, a crucial turning-point in a situation where all the options were still open, and therefore hotly-contested, and which has since attracted the special interest of historians, as the present essays demonstrate. 'Ehe tension revealed itself not only on those occasions when nobility and princes, parliament and king, actually came into conflict, thus showing that the struggle had not yet been decided. It is evidenced also by a specific form of political theorising which has been described, using a word that is undoubtedly incorrect and was merely Born out of the polemics of the time, as `monarchomachic'. The monarchomachs, or tyrannicides, concentrated on the conditions and forms of estates' resistance to the princes. They were opposed by a broad stream of political literature which attempted to demonstrate the legitimacy and diffusion of princely authority, or of `sovereignty', to use the more modern word that has spread through Europe since Bodin. lt seems to me that our brief review of the situation is necessary in order to justify looking again at the system of estates and its Estates and the Problem of Resistance Winfried Schulze direct significance for this turning-point in central and east-central European history. As we know, modern interest in the history of the estates was to a largo extent aroused by the efforts of democratic historians in Europe who wanted to offer a counterweight to the fascist and anti-parliamentary movements whose influence grew markedly between the wars. As these ideas could not then fall on fruitful soil in Germany, the system of estates was not studied more closely there until after the Second World War, when the authoritarian state was no longer the main focus of interest. Undoubtedly, the research of the post-war period continued to absorb the initial `democratic' impulse. However, it soon lost its political thrust, and was diverted into a direction where the main concern was, increasingly, to emphasise those aspects of European absolutism which continued to be corporately organised and did not conform to the discipline imposed by central governments. The result of these efforts was a much more differentiated picture of European absolutism, and to that extent research on the estates has made a major contribution to the historiography of the early modern period in Europe. However, since the 1960s it has tended to lose sight of the political issues involved altogether. One of my intentions in looking again at the significance of resistance by the estates in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries is to assess and digest the empirical work that has been done in the last few years. Beyond this, however, we also have to ask what direction future research on the estates should take. Our picture certainly contains gaps, and several specific questions are still awaiting detailed work. But practice has long taught us that asking major new questions is always the best way to stimulate empirical studies. Although detailed historical research has shown that the estates of the early modern period were not the predecessors of modern democratic parliaments, at least not in a direct way, the whole issue and the questions it raised concerning the significance of autonomous elements within absolutism have proved to be astonishingly persistent. My point of departure in this essay is the consolidation of power in the still fluid circumstances of the Tate sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. However, my analysis will pay more attention to the total constellation of political interests than has so far been usual. 1 shall be looking at the various interests of princes, estates and subject populations and at what factors intluenced those interests. The question of resistance in theory and practice will be seen against this background. What I hope to show is, above all, that research on the estates must not work with an abstract model of resistance such as is still commonly used in the literature of constitutional law. At the level of both estates and associations of subjects, resistance must be regarded as one possibility of action that was inherent in the political system of the time. Resistance in the early modern period was, to some extent, the complement of the state's as yet incompletely formed system of authority. Its enormous significance for our purposes is that in the second half of the sixteenth century this traditional instrument for the regulation of power collided with the princes' absolutist claims to take sole responsibility for leadership. The issue of resistance can thus be used as an effective test-case to establish the actual extent of the consolidation of state authority. Given the proviso that the theory and practice of resistance were an indispensable component of the process by which the modern state emerged, then we may see resistance in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as part of that universal struggle between freedom and order which underlies all its specific historical manifestations. At the beginning of the twentieth century, these questions were still evaluated quite differently. In 1916 and 1918 German historians were declaring that the problem of resistance now possessed only historical significance. In 1916 Kurt Wolzendorff wondered why it was 'that the question of the people's right to resist, posed by the tyrannicides of the sixteenth century, retained its place in political science for three hundred years, only to disappear from it then suddenly and completely'. He did not doubt that the establishment of the rule of law on a constitutional basis had `put paid' to the doctrine of the right to resist. The legal historian Hans Fehr believed that the right to resist was logically untenable in juridical terms', and that it had become `institutionally superfluous': 'The right to resist passed away with the corporative state itself'. I do not think that the inappropriateness of this sort of eschatological thinking in legal matters needs to be demonstrated. Today we lack these certainties about the perfection of history, especially in our own era. The experience of the Nazi dictatorship and European fascism has shown us that the question of freedom and order remains in essence an unsolved one. 'The history of European absolutism contains so much of our own destiny that there is good reason for us to go back to it again and again, and think about it afresh.' Reinhard Wittram's insight of 1948 provided a motto for 160 161 162 Estates and the Problem of Resistance recent work on absolutism and the estates. It is a motto that we can still adopt today. Indeed, given the complacency and the seemingly quite apolitical nature of much individual research, it sometimes seems appropriate to recall such comments. We shall now look at the framework of political power within which the resistance of the estates of Central Europe must be placed. A four-part scheme is most appropriate to the Holy Roman Empire, taking into account the interests of the nobles, the subject populations, the princes and the emperor. Here I should like to draw upon conclusions which I have already reached about each of these interest groups in the context of my comparative research on peasant resistance, and which, it seems to me, are also indispensable to the problem that interests us here. Firstly, the landowning nobility, given the growth of a money economy and the upward demographic trend of the entire sixteenth century, had a fundamental interest in making the fullest possible use of peasants' obligations to render them taxes and services. In each case, the given agrarian structure determined the particular form of increased burden that was preferred. In political terms, this economic priority meant that the estates initially aimed to protect their own landed domains visä-vis the ruler as far as possible, or to limit princely intervention in that area to what could be circumvented. In terms of financial policy, their orientation could only mean as complete a rejection as possible of all attempts by the central administration to appropriate their subjects' income. The landowning nobility's peasant subjects, in turn, had a strong interest in securing as far as possible their individual and collective titles to the land, as well as their right to inherit, and to use or sell the products of their land under favourable conditions, since that was the only way in which individual agrarian producers could prove their worth and peasants could have a share in the agricultural boom. Politically, this grass-roots interest meant that subjects increasingly appealed to the prince's authority to settle disputes, which signified a progressive weakening of the nobles' autonomy. Thirdly, the governments of the territorial states, in their turn, had a strong interest in an economically healthy population that could pay its taxes. This was the only way in which their authority could be stabilised at home and extencled abroad. A monopoly of civil power, a legal system that applied to everyone, and a standing army formed the basis for the state's ability to defend itself against Winfried Schulze 163 aristocratic frondeurs and rebellious peasants, as well as against external attack. Finally, the constellation of powers and interests outlined so far remains, of course, incomplete as far as most of Central Europe is concerned, where it would have to include the emperor as guarantor of internal and external order. The emperor was able to assert himself as a controlling authority mainly against the smaller territorial powers. Given that the duality of emperor and Empire served unmistakably to strengthen the position of the princes between the mid-sixteenth and mid-seventeenth centuries, this factor must be taken into account in assessing the total situation. Further, the relationship between the emperor and the estates of the Reich in many cases provided the background for the behaviour of princes and estates in the separate territories. Certain fundamental kinds of conflict almost inevitably derived from this constellation of forces. Moreover, it seems to me worth stressing that the peasant revolts and estates' disputes to which it gave rise—in other words, this epoch's massive disruptive potential—were a product not only of dynastic and national rivalry or of religious struggles, but also of basic social tensions and shifts in status. In my view, this Interpretation is more broadly based and productive than the often polemical contention found, for example, in the work of J.H. Elliott, that social conflicts were less relevant than conflicts about the control and exercise of power. Abstract recourse to political power struggles as explanatory factors seems to me to be as unproductive as constant references to the exclusive significance of social forces. More important, in my view, is to identify the interests which underlay such power struggles, or to analyse the catalytic function of religious factors in socio-political conflicts. I hope that the brief breakdown of interests given above takes us one step further towards this goal. If I am right, then the often overlapping, but divergent interests of peasants, nobles and princes were the characteristic feature of the early modern period in Europe. In terms of domestic politics, we can distinguish at first glance two distinct lines of conflict, namely estates' disputes on the one hand and peasants' revolts on the other. But from time to time these two levels of conflict wwwere sso closely entwined that their connection becomes obvious. This phenomenon is very clearly visible in the French power struggles of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, where royal authority had to assert itself against peasant resistance as much as against aristocratic regionalism. In the Habsburg territories, which mainly concern us here, Estates and the Problem of Resistance Winfried Schulze conflicts between princes and estates, rulers and subjects, mingled to such an extent that they cannot be clearly separated. Both lines of conflict can easily be derived from the power structures outlined above. They are part of a large and coherent historical process. At issue in the peasants' revolts were the extent of taxation and the various forms of seigneurial obligation; while the estates' disputes, in essence, were about the ruler's right to raise taxes and quasi-parliamentary safeguards against abuse of this right. More pointedly, one could say that, while the peasants' revolts were about the Surplus which could be skimmed off peasant production, the estates' disputes concentrated on the fundamental right to exploit peasant production. Of course, I am aware that the struggles of the estates can also be described in the terminology of the major political conflicts of the time, but it seems important to establish that they were not abstract disputes about sovereignty. On the contrary, the main issue was access to Chose resources which were the prerequisite for the position of power which, superficially, always appeared to be the aim of the struggle. largely unchallenged, in response to the demands of practical politics and without any particular process of constitutional reflection. The catch-phrase `Quoll omnes tangit' was certainly known in Central Europe. However, once it had beeil established in principle that the diets would participate to some degree in .domestic political decision-making, that phrase was more commonly used by the imperial cities in order to justify their meetings. The crucial breakthrough to theorising about the position of the estates vis-ä-vis the princes was manifestly prompted by the religious question. This issue confronted the estates concerned with the problem of tyranny, known from medieval political theory. In other words, we must assume that the question of religious resistance aggravated a problem that was much older and fed upon feudal law as well as upon the literature about the relationship between emperor and pope. But it was not until the sixteenth century, when the state's activities had expanded and the confessional issue exerted a specific pressure, that theories of resistance were explicitly formulated. Of course, this was only part of a general and remarkable movement towards theorisation which characterised the sixteenth century in Europe as a whole: our question about theory and practice makes no sense until then. The main factor in making the question of resistance more radical and more acute was that the impulse behind Reformation thinking opened up the possibility of resistance to a much wider social group. So far, it had been restricted to the nobility; now resistance could be expressed at a communal and sometimes even at an individual level. The problem of tyrannis exercitu only arose when the emperor and his imperial estates, or the prince and his territorial estates, belonged to different faiths. Until that time this variant of the medieval concept of tyranny had been an exception in Europe; now it became the norm where the exercise of power was at issue. What is the particular significance of this phase of reflection about confessional resistance? If we summarise what Zwingli, Luther and Calvin had to say on the subject, it appears that it was the idea of a lower authority' which became added at this stage to the Jong intellectual tradition concerning potential agents of resistance. In 1958, Gerhard Oestreich, expanding upon Beza's tenet that the authority of the king derived from the authority of the people, proposed that the concepts of the sovereignty of the prince and of the people should be supplemented by that of the sovereignty of the magistrates. This, he suggested, would better `capture the reality of 164 Turning now to the question of the right to resist in theory and practice, we will not be examining earlier historical developments. Our subject is not the protracted process by which the princes established their position during the later Middle Ages, confirming noble privileges merely from case to case in various treaties or Herrschaftsverträge, a term which actually covers a multiplicity of different kinds of agreement. What is important here is that initially, on each occasion, the rights and duties of prince and nobles were laid down without reference to general principles which would allow us to speak meaningfully of resistance. This term, it seems to me, becomes useful only as that phase in the relationship between prince and estates was reached when the extension of the state's activity at home and abroad gave the prince a specific kind of authority—that is, when princes claimed responsibility for all political questions pertaining to their territories. Historically, I would date this phase in Central Europe to about the second half of the fifteenth century, when the decline of partible inheritance within dynasties, growing tax demands, the enhanced peacekeeping role of the prince as arbiter of the Landfrieden, and the establishment of the territorium clausum as a legal and administrative unit made the princely court the natural focus of domestic politics. Rulers achieved such a position of real predominance 165 167 Estates and the Problem of Resistance Winfried Schulze the times and their aspirations'. Some years later J.H. Elliott pointed to the significance of the various communities, corporations and Landschaften which articulated the idea of political solidarity in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Using the `magistrate theory' to examine the impact which those bodies had on political theories is in line with these Europe-wide `idealised notions', emphasised by Elliott, of how political communities emerge. The first significant expression of the idea that I can find is in Zwingli's Predigt vom Hirten of 26 June 1524. In this sermon, he refers to Spartan ephors, Roman tribunes and the chief wardens of urban German guilds as examples of authorities who can exercise some control over the ruler. Thence he draws the almost revolutionary conclusion that preachers can fulfil the same function for their congregations. More detailed investigation of the rote of such magistratus inferiores has, over the last twenty years, considerably modified our picture of the history of the theory of resistance in the sixteenth century. Above all, the view that St Bartholomew's Night in 1572 marked the decisive breakthrough to a qualitatively new theory of resistance has had to be revised. Instead, interest has focused on the Magdeburg Confession (Magdeburger Bekenntnis) of 1550, the first systematic explication of the lower magistrates' right to resist. lt arose out of the exigencies of the political situation faced by the city, which opposed the Interim of Augsburg. Recent research has shown this document to be an interesting meeting-point between German and Anglo-French doctrines of resistance. The notion it develops of resistance by lower authorities is of special interest not only because it broadens the basis of the old theory of corporate resistance, but also because it puts forward a division of political authorities that extends downwards as far as the commune. The progressive lowering of political and social credentials from the level of Protestant princes of the Empire right down to the lower status occupied by the magistratus inferiores of the Magdeburg Confession and other texts is, undoubtedly, a remarkable process. lt remains to be seen whether this lowering of the credentials for resistance was not also used as an argument against resistance by the estates. Looking at the question which has probably been most fully researched, that of the justification offered for armed resistance to the emperor after the imperial diet of 1530, we can distinguish two lines of argument. First there is the theory, used by theologians, of resistance being justified on the basis that all authorities, including the lower ones, have a specific task. On this view, all authorities are appointed by God; they all have the task of protecting their subjects. Quentin Skinner has called this interpretation of the possibility of resistance by lower authorities, even against higher authorities, the `constitutionar theory of resistance, because in essence it did no more than reformulate the possibility of vassals offering resistance to the highest feudal lord, already contained in the imperial constitution, and apply it to religious conflict. The other line of argument relating to resistance was developed by Saxon lawyers and derived from the general right of self-defence. That right became operative when an authority acted unjustly and thus forfeited its official standing. Skinner calls this argument the theory of resistance under private law. However, we could also speak of a natural-law theory because, to quote Melanchthon, it is based on the idea that `vim vi repellere natura concedit'. lt is obvious that the practical applications of these two theories of resistance would be totally different, a point soon perceived by contemporaries, as the Torgau discussions of October 1530 Show. Martin Bucer, who in general approved of resisting the emperor, pointed to the incalculable consequences of the natural-law theory of resistance, emphasising the gravity of a failure to distinguish between the authority of private individuals and that of the bearers of public office. It is not surprising, therefore, that Bucer mainly developed the `constitutionar variant of the right of resistance, which thus found its way, presumably via Calvin and Beza, into French Protestantism, where it formed the core of all varieties of Huguenot theories of resistance. We should observe in passing that we owe our knowledge of Bucer's significance for the development of Calvinist thinking on resistance primarily to the work of Hans Baron, who saw in him the bridge between the ius divinum of the age of Reformation and Counter-Reformation, and the ius naturale of modern times. Above all, Bucer developed the fundamental idea of merutn imperium as the criterion of authority: so long as it possessed merum imperium, even the 'geringste und schwecheste oberkait', the lowest and weakest authority, had the right to rule, to pass laws and to punish offenders. The Magdeburg Confession of 1550, which we have already mentioned, articulated this basic rule in its Statements on lower authority: 166 Wenn die hohe Obrigkeit sich understehet, mit gewalt und unrecht zu verfolgen, nicht so vast die Personen ihrer Untertanen 168 Estates and the Problem of Resistance als in ihnen das Göttliche und natürliche Recht, rechte lehre und Gottesdienst aufzuheben und auszureuten, so ist die unter Obrigkeit schuldig, aus kraft Göttlichs befehls wider solch der Obern fürnehmen sich sampt den ihren, wie sie kon, auffzuhalten. In the present context, we cannot pursue the question, interesting though it is, of how the Magdeburg Confession found its way into the English and French world and was further developed there. Instead, we shall turn our attention to the significance of this specific theory for the resistance of the estates in Central Europe. lt seems that the local estates of the various territories of the Empire had much more difficulty in accepting this theory than did the Protestant princes and cities vis-a-vis the emperor. This means that estates' resistance within the territories remained much more strongly orientated towards the traditional model of upholding privileges. Even in the Habsburg territories, where conflict between princes and estates was most acute, the Legitimation of resistance by the estates initially remained fully within the framework of inherited models of consensus. `Vertreuliches Miteinanderhandeln', confidential negotiation, between prince and diet was considered the ideal of political life, disturbed only by the prince's jealous and, of course, foreign advisers. Loyalty to the ancestral dynasty was presented as historically tried and tute, and absolutely unswerving; the traditional rights of the territories were regarded as the guideline for all political action. If I am correct, and apart from a few exceptions to be mentioned below, corporative resistance in the Holy Roman Empire largely stayed within a traditional framework of rule: the theoretical concepts being developed elsewhere at the time were not accepted there. lt seems rather that, at the end of the sixteenth and the beginning of the seventeenth century, the theory of `constitutional' resistance was further invoked only at two particular points in the Empire's system of estates. First, it cropped up in the discussions of the imperial estates, held after the 1594 Reichstag, about the validity of the resolutions passed by that body's Catholic majority. As I have discussed this episode several times over the past few years, 1 shall refer to it only briefly here; but it is worth mentioning because the discussions took place at a conspicuously high level, which serves to confute the preconception that the development of European political thought in the sixteenth century, as at other times, largely took Winfried Schulze 169 place outside Germany. In fact, this discussion, sparked off by legal measures implemented against those Protestant states which refused to pay imperial taxes approved by the Catholic majority, provides evidence of an interesting new usage of the axiom Quod omnes tangit. In addition, the Protestant estates used the magistratus inferiores argument, justifying their refusal to pay these taxes by saying that in such dangerous times they had to look after their own subjects instead of spending money on defending the far distant border with Turkey. For the rest, there can be no doubt that the group of Protestant princes who looked to the Palatinate based their right to resist the emperor and the Catholic party of which he was the leader on the same constitutional arguments that had been developed in the first half of the century. Thus, for example, participants in the Rothenburg assembly of the Protestant Union, which met before the important imperial diet of 1613, were fully agreed that, should this Reichstag fail, the Union `raust be ready for the worst', and should look to some kind of alliance with other, foreign powers, just as our opponents have done'. The magistratus inferiores argument received further support when the Protestant estates at that diet, again rejecting the majority resolution, referred to the institutions always cited as historical examples of the ephor theory, that is, the Roman tribunes and similar institutions in Sparta and Athens, as well as to Persia, Poland and the Estates General. The other area where we can discern the unequivocal effects of a developed theory of magistrates is the Habsburg hereditary lands during the Counter-Reformation. Since the 1560s and 1570s, the Protestant estates there had managed successfully to safeguard their position. Indeed, because the princes relied on them to grant money for the Turkish war, the estates were able to consolidate themselves politically and culturally. They ran their own schools and churches, were involved in everything pertaining to warfare, and maintained permanent, politically aware and efficient administrations. All this meant that the Austrian hereditary lands were truly dualistic corporative states, although naturally there were differences between individual territories. Of some importance, finally, is the fact that during the sixteenth century, a Sense of political community among the estates of the various lands had already begun to develop. This has led no less an authority than Hans Sturmberger to suggest that in Austria the system of estates represented 'the other variant of state development' beside the rule of the princes, a judgement echoed by some of the other contributors to this volume. 171 Estates and the Problem of Resistance Winfried Schulze For our purposes the crucial point is that the largely Protestant estates in the Habsburg lands were able to reject the conditions of the religious Peace of Augsburg and impose the Protestant faith in their own domains. This clear deviation from the general confessional regulations laid down for the Empire provoked the Catholic House of Habsburg to try to regain its lost position at the beginning of the Counter-Reformation. Its attempt posed the central question of who held the real power. Was the sovereign now only a `painted' or `paper' prince, as the Habsburg ruler of Styria feared? Were the estates the real masters of the country? Or did plenum imperium, or absolutum Imperium, as in other lands, accrue to the prince? In essence, the Austrian estates developed two positions to cope with the threat posed by the Counter-Reformation. The first was to adopt an attitude that could be called 'passive resistance', `whereby obedience comes to the same thing as the power of obstruction', as Sturmberger has established for Upper Austria in the stante of Achaz von Hohenfeld in 1589. I myself have found an instance of the same thing in Styria in 1582: an estates' report of that year on the religious question says that the estates should prepare for the most dire emergency with a responsible defence 'contra vim et iniuriam"wider besorgende gewalt', since they are holders of public office who are bound by oath to respect and defend privileges. Thus we have another instance of the magistrate theory being applied. Neither position, however, involved offering active, armed resistance to the prince. Nothing going beyond that defensive posture can be found in the Erblande until after 1608 when, under the leadership of Georg Erasmus von Tschernembl and protected by the Lieben treaty of 25 June that year, the Protestant estates of Upper Austria organised resistance to Archduke Matthias. This phase of the quarret witnessed the most comprehensive definition of corporate resistance in Europe. In his speeches during negotiations with the Hungarian and Moravian estates, Tschernembl developed his idea of a truly corporative state which elected its own ruler, whose subjects enjoyed freedom of religion, and which was `almost a free res publica' as Archduke Matthias feared at the time. If we also take into account Tschernembl's `Consultationes', written a decade later, in which he specifies the conditions under which a prince can be deposed and also considers how to win over the peasants, there can be little doubt that what we have here is an alternative model of early modern statehood, developed on the basis of noble autonomy and Calvinist reflections on resistance. Its translation into reality, however, miscarried. Of course it is possible to argue that the Battle of the White Mountain could have had a different outcome, and with that the verdict of history on the policies of the Habsburg estates could have been different. This objection is certainly valid and, remembering the fluidity of the situation mentioned at the outset, we should be wary of discounting from the start the possibility that the estates could have been successful. Nonetheless, that possibility should not prevent us from thinking about the problematic character of corporate resistance in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. We need to ask why such a discrepancy arose between the theory and the practice of resistance by the estates. In my opinion, that discrepancy cannot simply be brushed aside by being blamed on the contingencies of historical development. 170 Any answer to this question must draw upon more than one argument. First we should mention the evidente from all over Europe that a certain store of political experience had accumulated in the course of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, best summed up in the Latin tag: Praesumptio setnper militat pro magistratu. It indicates a high esteem for the leadership of the authorities, whose function in creating order and guaranteeing security is especially appreciated. This Sentiment was matched by a critical attitude to popular movements, which were described as disordered and dangerous, and whose members were seen as incapable of participating in politics. Even a thinker like Althusius does not doubt that the political leadership of a community is best left in the hands of one man. In Emden, he himself acted accordingly, curtailing the power of the patriciate and setting himself up as `dictator of Emden', as Michael Behnen has recently put it. Against this background, any serious attempt to set up corporative or republican organisations was bound to carry special weight. We must also mention the special position into which the Turkish danger put the Habsburg hereditary lands. Although this factor could be used as a compelling argument in negotiations with the princes, it was also an argument for not pushing the estates' claims vis-ä-vis the prince too far. The European position of the House of Habsburg, its ties with rich Spain and the Papacy, ensured its ability successfully to defend the Austrian lands and the Empire. To that extent the diets' annual resolutions concerning border security 172 Estates and the Problem of Resistance ultimately turned out to be an argument against the estates. Moreover, we must also remember that power struggles in corporate societies always included that sector of society which, although excluded from the direct exercise of power, to a large degree determined the political decisions that were made. It is therefore especially interesting to look at the many references to the significance of the subject population in disputes between prince and estates, and to examine to what extent a conflict superficially taking place between prince and diet was also intluenced by the unprivileged Untertanen. The fact that in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries the Habsburg territories were in a state of `perpetual social upheaval', to quote Karl Eder, cannot have been without significance for the Protestant nobility. That the peasants might rise at any time was used as a many-sided argument. Diet and prince accused each other of provoking disturbances among the common people by their respective policies on religion. At the 1582 Reichstag, the ruler of Inner Austria, Archduke Charles, was not as confident of his peasants' attitude towards the Turks as of the nobility's. lt is extraordinarily difficult to determine the position of the nobles vis-ä-vis their subjects because, although they were brought together by a common religion, they were divided by social antagonisms. On the other hand, the nobility made common cause with the peasants against the princely policy of re-Catholicisation when its right to exercise patronage, and thus to appoint clergy or to accept `runaway' subjects of Catholic lords into Protestant churches, was at stake. On the other hand, the extent of conflict between the nobles and their subjects was frequently revealed in refusals to render compulsory services and labour, in local unrest and lawsuits. In all these disagreements, the peasantry increasingly appealed to the prince's authority to settle disputes. Thus the Robotpatent that put an end to the uprising of 1598 was achieved only because the emperor put strong pressure on noble interests, whose chief representative, incidentally, was Tschernembl. In Georg Erasmus von Tschernembl the Problem we are addressing here was concentrated in one person. On the one hand, he clearly subscribed to monarchomachic ideas; on the other, he was a vehement defender of the rights of the nobility and, ultimately, an advocate of the use of force against the subject population. In his view, the disobedience of peasants towards their lords threatened the foundations of the polity. His writings contain no references to a Winfried Schulze 173 possible coalition between the nobility and its subjects for the purpose of achieving noble religious aims, apart from his advice, given at the eleventh hour, that Bohemian peasants should be released from their serfdom in order to make them more favourably disposed towards the estates, and to forestall the emperor's adoption of the same tactic. This demonstrates very clearly the limits of the nobility's capacity for action. In a society predicated upon social inequality, which had already been recognised as such and made the subject of reform measures, power struggles between the privileged estates could only in exceptional circumstances break down social barriers. The nobility's basic need for internal peace and social stability could be effectively guaranteed only by the prince, representing an authority that transcended the interests of the various strata of society. Awareness of the prince's irreplaceable function affected all conflicts between estates and rulers, and it explains why the solutions proposed by the estates could be realised only under special conditions. Those cases in which the estates were finally successful illustrate, in their often precarious development, the difficulty of bypassing the authority of the prince. In 1578 the imperial tourt feared that the estates would rebel against a change in the religious concessions made by Maximilian II. Even at this early stage, Dr Georg Eder, member of the Aulic Council, suggested in his report that the estates of Upper and Lower Austria gave absolutely no cause for concern. He wrote that they consisted of 'gutherzige verständige Leuth', and that in these territories there was a very different opinion from that in France and the Netherlands, 'da hier viel seien, die der Obrigkeit nach dem Schwert und Regiment greiffen'. Undoubtedly more reasons could be listed for the restraint shown by the estates in their dispute with that princely authority which in the end destroyed the nobility's autonomy and subjected its political functions to far-reaching controls, compensating it with greater social privileges. Ultimately, however, we cannot disregard the important function fulfilled by the princes themselves, a function made possible by the historical situation of the sixteenth century. Our insights depend on the retrospective view granted to historians; they were not available to Chose participating in the power struggles at the end of the sixteenth and beginning of the seventeenth century. From this we can conclude that estates' resistance, in theory and practice, must be regarded as an alternative possibility of 174 Estates and the Problem of Resistance Winfried Schulze state-building, even if, for the time being, the main path of historical development passed it by. McNeill, J., `The Democratic Element in Calvin's Thought', Church History, xviii (1949) 153-71. Oestreich, Gerhard, 'Die Idee des religiösen Bundes und die Lehre vom Staatsvertrag', in his Geist und Gestalt des frühmodernen Staates (Berlin, 1969) 157-78. Salmon, J.H.M., 'An Alternative Theory of Popular Resistance: Buchanan, Rossaeus and Locke', in: Diritto e potere Hella storia europea. Quarto Congresso haernazioftale in onore di Bruno Paradisi (Florence, 1982) 824-49. Scheible, Heinz, Das Widerstandsrecht als Problem der deutschen Protestanten, 1523-1546 (Gütersloh, 1969). Schoenberger, C.G., `The "Confession" of Magdeburg and the Lutheran Doctrine of Resistance' (Diss., Columbia University, 1972). Schulze, Winfried, Landesdefension und Staatsbildung. Studien zum Kriegswesen des innerösterreichischen Territorialstaates (1564-1619) (Vienna/Cologne, 1973). Idem, 'Eine deutsche Übersetzung von Bezas De jure magistratuum in subditos', Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte, lxx (1979) 302-7. Idem, Bäuerlicher Widerstand und feudale Herrschaft in der frühen Neuzeit (Stuttgart, 1980). Idem, 'Bäuerlicher Widerstand und die "Rechte der Menschheit"', in Grund- und Freiheitsrechte im Wandel von Gesellschaft und Geschichte, ed. G. Birtsch (Göttingen, 1981) 41-56. Althusius-Bibliographie, compiled by H.U. Scupin and U. Scheuner (2 vols., Berlin, 1973), an important bibliography for sixteenth-century political theory as a whole. Skinner, Quentin, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Vol. 11: The Age of Reformation (Cambridge, 1978). Stricker, G., `Das politische Denken der Monarchomachen' (Diss., Heidelberg, 1967). Strohl, 1-1., Te Droit ä la i-sistance d'apres les conceptions protestantes', Revue d'llistoire et de Philosophie Religieuses, x (1930) 126-44. Sturmberger, Hans, Georg Erasmus Tschernembl. Religion, Libertät und Widerstand. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Gegenreformation und des Landes ob der Enns (Cologne, 1953). Vahle, 1-1., `Calvinismus und Demokratie im Spiegel der Forschung', Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte, lxvi (1975) 182-212. Wolf, E., `Das Problem des Widerstandsrechts bei Calvin', in: Widerstandsrecht, ed. Arthur Kaufmann and L.E. Backmann (Darmstadt, 1972) 152-69. Wolgast, Eike, `Die Religionsfrage als Problem des Widerstandsrechts im 16. Jahrhundert', S itzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-hist. Klasse, 1980, 9. Abhandlung. Idem, Die Wittenberger Theologie und die Politik der evangelischen Stände. Studien zu Luthers Gutachten in politischen Fragen (Gütersloh, 1977). Wolzendorff, Kurt, Staatsrecht und Naturrecht in der Lehre vom Widerstandsrecht des Volkes gegen rechtswidrige Ausübung der Staatsgewalt. Zugleich ein Beitrag zur Entwicklungsgeschichte des modernen Staatsgedankens (1916, reprinted Aalen, 1961). Bibliography Baron, Hans, `Calvinist Republicanism and its historical Roots', Church History, viii (1939) 30 42. Idem, 'Religion and Politics in the German Imperial Cities during the Reformation', English Historical Review, Ih (1937) 405-27, 614-33. Benert, R.R., 'Inferior Magistrates in Sixteenth Century Political and Legal Thought' (Diss. University of Minnesota, 1967). Idem, Tutheran Resistance Theory and the Imperial Constitution', in Il pensiero politico (1973) 17-36. Jürgen Dennert ed., Beza, Brutus, Hotman. Calvinistische Monarchomachen (Cologne/Opladen, 1968). Elliott, J.H., 'Revolution and Continuity in Early Modern Europe', Past and Present, xlii (1969) 35-56. Franklin, J.H., Constitutionalism and Resistance in the Sixteenth Century (New York, 1969). Gierke, Otto von, Johannes Althusius und die Entwicklung der naturrechtlichen Staatstheorien (5th edn., Aalen, 1958). Gilmore, Myron P., Argument front Roman Law in Political Thought, 1200-1600 (Cambridge, 1941). Hildebrandt, E., `The Magdeburg Bekenntnis on a Possible Link between German and English Resistance Theory in the Sixteenth Century', Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte, lxxi (1980) 227-53. Hoyer, S., `Bemerkungen zu Luthers Auffassung über das Widerstandsrecht der Stände gegen den Kaiser (1539)', in Martin LutherLeben, Werk, Wirkung, ed. Günter Vogler (1983) 255-68. Huschke, Rolf Bernhard, Melanchthons Lehre vom Ordo politicus. Ein Beitrag zum Verhältnis von Glauben und politischem Handeln bei Melanchthon (Gütersloh, 1968). Widerstandsrecht, ed. Arthur Kaufmann and L.E. Backmann (Darmstadt, 1972). Kern, Fritz, Gottesgnadentum und Widerstandsrecht im früheren Mittelalter (3rd edn., Darmstadt, 1962). Kingdon, Robert M., `Calvinism and Democracy: Some Political Implications of Debates on French Reformed Church Government, 1562-72', American Historical Review, lxix (1963/64) 393-401. Idem, 'The First Expression of Theodore Beza's Political Ideas', Archiv für Reformationsgeschichte, xlvi (1955) 88-100. Kreutzer, Jakob, Zwinglis Lehre von der Obrigkeit (Stuttgart, 1909; reprinted Amsterdam, 1965). Lüthje, `Melanchthons Anschauung über das Recht des Widerstands gegen die Staatsgewalt', Zeitschrift für Kirchengeschichte, NF x (1928) 512-42. 175