excurse to the history of inertial force
Transcription
excurse to the history of inertial force
EXCURSE TO THE HISTORY OF INERTIAL FORCE I Igal Galili and Michael Tseitlin H P The Hebrew University of Jerusalem T S Jerusalem 2010 1 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force EXCURSE TO THE HISTORY OF INERTIAL FORCE Igal Galili and Michael Tseitlin The Hebrew University of Jerusalem e-mail: igal@vms.huji.ac.il Abstract The concept of inertial force is one of the most important and the most difficult in classical dynamics. It absorbed and increased the difficulties of both concepts of force and inertia, both complex and obscure. However, just because of that, making sense of inertial force may shed light on its both components. In fact, the notion of inertial force designates a whole cluster of meanings and touches on different subjects in science. This is seen in the history of physics brought here, that the term inertial force was used in several different meanings, which co-exist today and usually cause confusion of the novice learner. The account for the concept of inertia (inertial force) provides a good example showing that scientific knowledge is after all a learned ignorance (Nicholas of Cusa) but, at the same time, perhaps the only kind of powerful knowledge associated with understanding and ability to use and benefit. It is therefore clear that teaching the topic of inertial force is never easy, but in the hands of a trained teacher, the complexity and multiple meanings of "inertial force" can be a powerful tool for achieving mature genuine knowledge of classical mechanics as well as of the nature of scientific knowledge. In fact, without inertial force, and the directly associated with it issue of non-inertial observer, the classical mechanics cannot provide understanding of the most important aspect of movement – its relativity. This excurse follows the development of the concept "inertial force", its genetic consolidation in mechanics. * * * Keywords: inertia, inertial force, centrifugal force, inertial and non-inertial observers, equivalence of inertia and gravitation, operational definition of force * * * 2 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Introduction Commonly, we use inertia to address phenomenon of spontaneous continuation of certain state or activity after its cause, which originally supported this state or activity ceased to act. After Aristotle, scientists seek for causes of everything that happens. After the scientific revolution of the 17th century, even in general, non-scientific context, we often replace the word cause with the word "force": "the force of tradition", "the force of will", "the motive force". In fact, non-scientists use "the force of inertia" as often as scientists: Why do we continue to do things when there is no reason for them any more? Why things go on moving without any push? Why is it difficult to put a heavy body into motion? Many people answer to these questions: "because of inertia…" or because of "the force of inertia". However, only scientists try to put exact meaning into this concept, which gradually consolidated in the course of science history. We will follow this process in order to understand this scientific meaning of "the force of inertia". Inertia is what makes difficult to put a body into motion! Inertia is what preserves motion! What is inertia? 3 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Kepler's Inertia – the force of sluggishness Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) – a prominent German scientist – was among those few who performed the scientific revolution of the 17th century. He worked in astronomy, optics and mathematics and belongs to the founders of modern physics. He is especially famous for his formulation of three laws of planetary motion that he elicited from the rich data accumulated by his previous Johannes Kepler employer – Danish astronomer – Tycho Brahe. Being educated in the tradition of Aristotelian physics, Kepler shared much of the views from the Aristotelian views, in particular, on the nature motion. However, unlike Aristotle and being an original thinker, he did not divide the universe into two realms of different regularity – below and above the Moon (sublunary and supralunary physics). Kepler, a contemporary of Galileo, did not stop at a mere description of motion of celestial bodies, and did not take their motion as natural, but continued to think about its causes, as a natural philosopher should do. Kepler regarded the motion of celestial bodies as violent (not natural). In his mind, the Sun served as motor for the motion of the planets (Fig.). If so, within the Aristotelian framework of dynamics, besides the agent causing this motion there should be a special feature of bodies – inertia: 1 Drawing of Kepler shows his understanding of planet motion. The sun rotates and emanates "rays of power" (radial lines) which while turning around the center push the planet along its path – a clear Aristotelian account of motion. If the matter of celestial bodies were not embower with inertia, something similar to weight, no force would be needed for their movement from their place; the smallest motive force would suffice to impart to them an infinite velocity. Since, however, the periods of planetary revolutions take up definite times, some longer and others shorter, it is clear that matter must have inertia which accounts for this differences. This small passage shows Kepler arriving 1 De causis planetarum, in Keper. J., Opera Omnia, Vol. 6, p. 342. The quote from: Jammer, M. (1961). Concepts of Mass in Classical and Modern Physics. Harvard University Press, AmbridgeMass, p. 55. 4 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force at the far-reaching conclusion regarding the nature of the universe solely by breaking one of the basic presumptions of the Aristotelian physics: the division of the universe into two areas with different regularities. However, Kepler immediately encountered a problem: why the periods of planetary motions were different. Indeed, if one thinks about the cosmos as Greeks did, as an organism, one rotating body, all its components should share the same period of rotation. What makes the reality different? Kepler explained it by a special feature of the celestial matter – inertia that discriminates between the planets, in their ability to move under the action of the pushing force:2 If this were the case, would not the planets make their periodic returns at he same time as the sun? Yes, if only this were the case. But it has been said before this, that besides this motor force of the sun there is also a natural inertia in the planets themselves with respect to movement: hence by reason of their matter they are inclined to remain in their own place. So the motor power of the sun and the powerlessness of material inertia of the planet are at war with one another. Each has its share of velocity: the motor power moves the planet from its seat; the material inertia removes its own, i.e., the planetary, body somewhat from those bonds by which it was laid hold of by the sun. (emphasis added) Kepler mentioned that that virtue was "something similar to weight". It was quite in accord with Aristotelian view: weight of regular bodies causes resistance to their violent motion, and the heavier the body is, the greater is its "resistance to motion"3: v∝ F W (v- the speed of the body, F- the force of the mover, W – the weight of the body) Instead, for the celestial bodies, deprived of weight Kepler coined the new concept, determines their resistance to motion – inertia in order to explain the finite speeds of the planets: v∝ F I (v- the speed of the planet, F- the force of the Sun, I – inertia of the planet) Why not weight? Seemingly, this was because if planets had weight they would fall down in the pre-Newtonian physics… It was for this reason (planets do not fall) that Aristotle totally deprived them from weight (the element comprising celestial 2 3 Kepler, J. (1618/1954). Epitome of Copernican Astronomy. Book, IV. p. 899. See more about the Aristotelian dynamics in the excurse to the history of motion account in this collection. 5 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force bodies – ether – was weightless). Therefore, Kepler could feel the need for a new concept in order to explain resistance to motion regardless weight. Worth to see, that our everyday use of inertia is often different. One may say: "I keep moving by inertia", meaning, "I do not push any more, but keep moving". It is the spontaneous motion that one often ascribes to inertia. In contrast, Kepler's concept addressed the feature of matter which regulated its response to the exerted force of the mover – the sun pushing the planets. For Aristotle, this source of motion (the effective cause) of planets was the Primary mover, and for Kepler – vis motrix (life force), a sort of magnetic force (magnetic ropes or chains) acting between the Sun and the planets. Inertia represented the inability of matter (of the planets) to maintain motion, its inherent ‘laziness’, the intrinsic repugnance to motion and propensity to the state of rest. We read:4 …the motor power [potentia vectoria] of the sun and the powerlessness or material inertia of the planet [impotentia planetae] or its material inertia are at war with one another. Preventing unsupported motion of the planets, inertia of Kepler would return them to rest if the force (vis motrix) between the Sun and the planet ceased to act: inertia represented sluggishness of the body which is in proportion to its mater: 5 Inertia or opposition to motion is a characteristic of matter; it is stronger, the greater the quantity of matter in a given volume. One might think that by ascribing inertia to the planets, Kepler arrived to the meaning we usually associate with inertial mass in classical mechanics. This, however, was not the case. Isaac Newton fundamentally changed the concept of inertia. Bernard Cohen – the renowned expert in Newton's legacy – made a remarkable finding when he revealed Newton’s marginal remark in his private copy of the first edition of the Principia. Newton wrote6: I do not mean Kepler’s force of inertia by which bodies tend toward rest, but the force of remaining in the same state whether of resting or of moving. (emphasis added) However, before we get to Newton, it is worth to take a look what Galileo, the great contemporary of Kepler, had in mind in this regard. 4 Kepler, Op. cit. Ibid. 6 Cohen, B. (1971). Introduction to Newton’s ‘Principia’. University Press, Cambridge, pp. XVI, 28. 5 6 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Galileo's Inertia – indifference Although the name Galileo is regularly related to "the law of inertia", his views on inertia were different from ours too. He never used the term inertia and never formulated the law of inertia.7 However, he addressed inertial motion, as we call it now, and therefore it is important to see his framework of thought to be compared with others'. Galileo Galiley Galileo's view on inertia was not consistent and not too well articulated. Preceding Newton in studying mechanics, he had no all-forces picture of the world to account for motion and did not formulate his lawlike statements succinctly. Instead, he voluminously and repeatedly expressed his views in non-formal dialogues, letters, assays, etc. In his famous Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, Galileo made Sagredo (the intelligent layman, initially neutral, representing an educated person of common sense), not Salviati (who represented his own views), expressing a seemingly regular view:8 I see in a movable body is the natural inclination and tendency it has to an opposite motion. . . . I said internal resistance, because I believe that this is what you meant, and not external resistances, which are many and accidental. (emphasis added) However, Salviati readily confirmed and refined, still making no statement: I wonder whether there is not in the movable body, besides a natural tendency in the opposite direction, another intrinsic and natural property which makes it resist motion (emphasis added). Here, Galileo showed here his thoughts similar to Kepler's comprehending of inertia: the inherent resistance to motion. But in another place, in his letter on sunspots, Galileo showed another view:9 I seem to have observed that physical bodies have physical inclinations to some motion (as heavy bodies downwards), which motion is exercised by them through an intrinsic property and without need of a particular external mover, whenever they are not impeded by some obstacle. And to some other motion they have a repugnance (as the same heavy bodies to 7 Drake, S. (1964). Galileo and the Law of Inertia, American Journal of Physics, 32, 601-608. Galiley, G. (1632/1953). Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, p. 213. 9 . Galiley, G. (1613/1957). Letters on Sunspots. In Drake, S. Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo. Doubleday, New York, pp. 113-114. 8 7 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force motion upward), and therefore they never move in that manner unless thrown violently by an external mover. Finally, to some movements they [bodies] are indifferent, as are these same heavy bodies to horizontal motion, to which they have neither inclination (since it is not toward the center of the Earth) nor repugnance (since it does not carry them away from that center). And therefore, all external impediments removed, a heavy body on a spherical surface concentric with the earth will be indifferent to rest or to movements toward any part of the horizon. And it will maintain itself in that slate in which it has once been placed; that is, if placed in a state of rest, it will conserve that; and if placed in movement toward the west (for example), it will maintain itself in that movement. Thus a ship, for instance, having once received some impetus through the tranquil sea, would move continually around our globe without ever stopping; and placed at rest it would perpetually remain at rest, if in the first case all extrinsic impediments could be removed, and in the second case no external cause of motion were added. In this piece, Galileo started with quite medieval views on natural and violent motion in falling bodies (Sagredo),10 but he also introduced the new idea. In between the two Aristotelian motions natural (downwards) and violent (upwards), Galileo found the third type: neutral, in between, the one keeping at the same distance from the center of the Earth, therefore, on the circular orbit around the center, on the surface of the Earth. This motion, as inferred by Galieo, left the body indifferent. This motion was indeed the close predecessor of the inertial motion, motion, the one without change and without support. This idea nicely accomplished Aristotelian and medieval account of motion. The point to keep in mind is, however, that such an inertial motion, as stated by Galileo, was circular, although the phrasing used by him confused generations of historians. Indeed, Galileo spoke about horizontal motion, leaving much space to further questions:11 On a perfectly horizontal surface a ball would remain indifferent and questioning between motion and rest, so that any the least force would be sufficient to move it, just as any little resistance, even that of the surrounding air, would be capable of holding it still. From this we may take the following conclusion as an indubitable axiom: 'That heavy bodies, all external and accidental impediments being removed, can be moved in the horizontal plane by any minimal force. 10 Galileo, using Sagredo, represents the medieval explanation of the motion of a body tossed upward in Galiley, G. (1636/1914). Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences. Dover, New York, p. 165. 11 Drabkin, I. & Drake, S. (1960). Galileo on Motion and on Mechanics. University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wis., p. 171. 8 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force In light of the two mentioned views, the one close to Keplerian (resistance to motion) and the one of his original (indifference to motion), it seems that Galileo, eventually, combined the two. Stilman Drake wrote:12 Galileo must have been teaching it in his private classes, for one of his pupils, Renedetto Castelli, who had left Padua some time before, wrote to Galileo in 1607 mentioning "your doctrine that although to start motion a mover is necessary, yet to continue it the absence of opposition is sufficient." This view shows that Galileo approached rather close to Newtonian understanding of motion, but still remained premature. Leaving aside the circular inertial motion, one of the cornerstones of the old physics refuted by Descartes13, a contemporary reader would refine the "resistance to motion", by replacing with "resistance to the change of motion", not to the motion itself. Such resistance combines both manifestations of inertia – resistance to begin motion as well as resistance to reduce it, or in other words, preservation of motion. And so we come to Newton. Newton: inertial force and inertia of mass Newton, Sir Isaac (1642-1727), was a remarkable mathematician, physicist, and natural philosopher, one of the most brilliant scientists of all times. A Fellow of Trinity College at the University of Cambridge, he produced one of the most famous scientific books: the Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, known as the Principia, that was published in 1687. Isaac Newton In his Principia, Newton introduced a new picture of the world in which material bodies interacted only by means of forces. Newton abolished the difference between natural and violent motions and the forces became the allinclusive framework of mechanics – the theory of motion. 12 13 Drake, S. (1964). Galileo and the Law of Inertia, American Journal of Physics, 32, 601-608. More about Descartes' laws of motion in Module 1 (Understanding Classical Mechanics: A Dialogue with Cartesian Theory of Motion). 9 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Newton defined the concept of inertial force in the very beginning of the book, where in a special chapter he defined the basic concepts of his theory. In his third definition, he wrote14: Inherent force of matter [vis insita] is the power of resisting by which every body, so far as it is able perseveres in its state, either of resting or of moving uniformly straight forward. and immediately explained: This [vis insita] force is always proportional to the body and does not differ in any way from the inertia of the mass except in the manner in which it is conceived. Because of the inertia of matter, every body is only with difficulty put out of its state either of resting or of moving. Consequently, inherent force may also be called by the very significant name of force of inertia [vis inertia]. Moreover, a body exerts this force only during a change of its state, caused by another force, impressed upon it; and this exercise of force is, depending on the viewpoint, both resistance and impetus: resistance in so far as the body, in order to maintain its state, strives against the impressed force, and the impetus in so far as the same body, yielding only with difficulty to the force of a resisting obstacle, endeavors to change the state of that obstacle. Resistance is commonly attributed to resting bodies, and impetus to moving bodies; but motion and rest, in the popular sense of the terms, are distinguished from each other only by point of view, and bodies commonly regarded as being at rest, are not always truly at rest. The force of inertia [vis insita] introduced by Newton was related to the first law of motion. Too often this law is considered as a special case of the second law. It was natural in the translation made in the past and changed only in the recent past.15 Within the recent interpretation, it appeared that the second law could be understood as a refinement of the first. In this perspective, the first law should be rather stated as following:16 Every body perseveres in its state of being at rest or of moving uniformly straight forward, except in so far it is compelled to change its state by forces impressed. (emphasis added) 14 Newton, I. (1687/1999). Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, p. 404. 15 Galili, I. & Tseitlin, M. (2003). ‘Newton's first law: text, translations, interpretations, and physics education’. Science and Education, 12 (1), 45-73. 16 Newton, I. (1687/1999). Op. cit. p. 416. 10 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Careful reading of this text reveals that it talks about the intention to preserve the state of motion (or rest) when the external force is applied and not when the net force is nullified. Traditionally, however, physics teachers keep with the simplified version of the first Newton's law, in which this law becomes a trivial case of absent forces, whereas the second law describes object behavior under the impressed force claiming that the inertial mass inversely determines the acceleration of the body under the influence of the force exerted. In his approach to description of the reality, Newton always tried to address real situations, that is the situation of active forces. This attitude was in contrast to Galileo who tried to establish the laws of nature in their ideal form, corresponding to the ideal situations (such as in the absence of friction). Therefore, the popular presentation of the first law in physics classes goes with the tradition of Galileo rather than of Newton. The highly important for the physics was the revolutionary treatment of Newton stating, in contrast to his all predecessors, the full equivalence of the states of rest and motion. In particular, the change was striking from the Aristotelian claim that a body is at state only when it rests, while being in motion it undergoes through a process of changing state.17 In any case, vis insita described the intention of the body to preserve its state. Indicatively, in the critique of Newton by Mach at the end of the 19th century, the force of inertia was already removed from Newtonian mechanics18. Let us clarify now the relationship between the mass, the quantity of matter and inertia. We start with Newtonian Definition I:19 DEFINITION I. Quantity of matter is the measure of matter that arises from its density and volume jointly. following by explanation:20 I mean this quantity whenever I use the term body or mass in the following pages. 17 Descartes was very close to Newton's understanding but did not reach it. See the module of Cartesian laws of motion in this selection. 18 Mach, E. (1893/1960). The science of mechanics/A critical and historical account of its development. Chicago. The Open Court, London, p. 241. 19 Newton, I. (1687/1999). Op. cit. p.403. 20 Ibid, p.404. 11 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force The above contains one of the most important and controversial ideas in the theory of motion. When Newton wrote his Principia, it was the time to clarify the fundamentals in the physical account of motion. Material bodies are characterized by a variety of properties (form, weight, color etc.). Mass is not equivalent to matter, but presents its property, the property of all material bodies. There is a reason why we say "the mass of the body" and don't say "the matter of the body". Mass is the quantified physical characteristic of the matter. Thus, we can say "big mass" and not "big matter". Furthermore, mass presumes certain uniformity. We may say, that in a crowd, "in a mass", people loose individuality and behave appropriately. We use mass to emphasize the absence of differences, aiming only quantity. Newton stated that mass was the quantity of the matter. On the first glance, it looks obvious: the bigger mass – the bigger quantity of matter. However, let us think how we know about the quantity of matter. In fact, matter is not given to us directly, as an observable property. We estimate the quantity of matter only through the properties of material bodies comprised of various kinds of materials (wood, metal, etc.). What is fundamental characteristic of any material? It cannot be the number of atoms – atoms are different – and neither their volume. We might assume that the quantity of matter of two identical bodies is two times more than such quantity in one of them. However, how could we compare the amounts of matter in different bodies? If we cannot, then the quantity of matter cannot be the primary physical notion that determines the mass. Seemingly, therefore, the quantity of matter should be secondary notion and should be expressed in terms of inertia, as measured in practice. In fact, the quality universal for all bodies is inertia. It is inertia that identifies the mass of the matter. Gravitation is another such universal property of all material bodies, and thus the gravitation describes the quantity of matter too. It is because Newton believed that matter was more fundamental than inertia, he defined mass as a quantity of matter and in the following treatment ascribed to the mass the feature of inertia. Euler in his Mechanics (see the following) understood that the quantity of matter was a confusing notion, lacking operational definition independent of inertia. Indeed, inertia is simply and directly measured through the force required to accelerate the 12 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force body. Consequently, mass as a "quantity of matter" was abandoned in the rigor theoretical physics. Only inertial mass remained as a central concept that appears in the second Newton's law, in the definition of momentum – the quantity of motion, and in the law of the universal gravitation. Students often feel that the quantity of the matter is a clear notion. Therefore, in introductory education, initial instruction, one may preserve Newtonian definition of mass. However, later, in the course of study, one should be guided to discover that it is more justified physically (operationally) to think of mass in terms of measure of inertia, and only inferentially as the quantity of the matter proportional to inertia, regardless any specific features of particular bodies. Furthermore, the understanding of mass as inertial mass is ready for further upgrading within the theory of relativity being closer to the fundamental relation mass-energy. In fact, we may talk about the inertial mass of a photon (the particle of light), but cannot talk about its quantity of matter, since its rest-mass is strictly zero. So, inertia is the primary property of matter and the law of inertia presents the fundamental ontological claim. If for Descartes bodies were conceived by their impermeable boundary (geometry), then, for us boundaries are secondary after inertia of the body. The fact that masses of bodies were measured by their weights, as mentioned by Newton in his explanation to definition I, illustrates that the quantity of matter is secondary to the gravitational mass. Newton wrote: … It is this quantity that I mean hereafter everywhere under the name of body or mass. And the same is known by the weight of each body; for it is proportional to the weight, as I have found by experiments on pendulums, very accurately made, which shall be shown hereafter. Newton showed the proportionality of weight to the inertial mass and considered this discovery very important. The proportionality to the quantity of matter was only an inference. In the definition of inertia (Definition III), Newton related the internal force (vis insita) to the magnitude of body, that is, its mass as already defined in Definition I:21 DEFINITION III. The vis insita, or innate force of matter, is a power of resisting, by which every body, as much as in it lies, endeavours to 21 Newton, I. (1687/1952). Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (Definitions, p, 5). Great Books of the Western World. Encyclopedia Britannica, Chicago. 13 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force persevere in its present state, whether it be of rest, or of moving uniformly forward in a right line. This force is ever proportional to the body whose force it is; and differs nothing from the inactivity of the mass, but in our manner of conceiving it. A body, from the inactivity of matter, is not without difficulty put out of its state of rest or motion. Upon which account, this vis insita, may, by a most significant name, be called inertia [vis inertia], or force of inactivity. But a body exerts this force only, when another force, impressed upon it, endeavours to change its condition. (emphasis added) In the explanation to the following Definition IV, defining the external (impressed) force, Newton again mentioned inertial force as that which preserved the state of uniform motion or rest of a body:22 DEFINITION IV. An impressed force is an action exerted upon a body, in order to change its state, either of rest, or of moving uniformly forward in a right line. This force consists in the action only; and remains no longer in the body when the action is over. For a body maintains every new state it acquires, by its vis inertia only. That far about Newton's view on inertial force in general context. Euler: inertia is not a force Leonhard Euler (1707–1783) was a Swiss mathematician who greatly contributed to a wide range of topics in mathematics and physics. As a young researcher, he comprised his treatise – Mechanics, which was practically the first textbook on the classical mechanics that influenced the subsequent development of mathematics, physics and philosophy. In it, he Leonhard Euler continued to use the term "inertial force" but already in the preface he wrote:23 … a state of conservation is an essential property of all bodies, and all bodies, in as much as they are such, have the strength or facility to remain permanently in their state, which is called nothing other than the force of inertia. Indeed, calling the inertial effect a force for the source of this conservation is less than suitable, since it is not a force of the same kind as the other forces thus properly discussed, such as the force of gravity, nor can it be compared with these; into which error many are accustomed to fall, especially those involved in metaphysics, from the ambiguity of their deceptive discussions. (emphasis added) 22 23 Ibid, p. 6. Euler, L. (1736/2008). Mechanics or the science of motion analytically demonstrated. Vol. 1, Preface, p. 3. Online: http://www.17centurymaths.com/contents/mechanica1.html 14 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Euler's definition of inertial force defines it as a faculty of a body:24 The force of inertia [vis inertiae] in all bodies is that in faculty of the body to maintain its state of rest or of continuing in its present state of [uniform] motion in a straight line. This definition coincides with the modern definition in physics textbooks today. One may also pay attention to the fact that in his treatise Euler, unlike Newton, stated first the law of inertia,25 and only after that, inertia was defined. Since Euler wrote his Mechanics as a textbook (not as an original theoretical essay), he explained things more than Newton did. In Proposition 17, Euler tried to demonstrate the important feature, which was stated by Newton as obvious:26 The force of inertia of any body is proportional to the quantity of matter, upon which it depends. Euler argued for this as following27: That [the force of inertia] therefore is to be estimated from the strength or the force applied to the body, with the aid of which it is to be disturbed from its state. Truly different bodies equally [disturbed] in their state are disturbed by forces, which are as the quantities of material contained in these. Therefore, the forces of inertia of these are [also] proportional to these forces. In other words, we know by the second Newton's law (in the form F=ma) that if two bodies, of masses m1 and m2, are accelerated to the same extent (a1=a2), then the masses ("the quantities of matter") are in the same ratio as the forces are: F1 m1 = F2 m2 In this fact, Euler saw the evidence for the forces of inertia of the bodies also to be in the same ratio as the ratio of their quantities of matter: different forces of inertia caused by the same changes of motion. 24 Euler, L. (1736/2008). Op cit. Vol. 1, Ch. 1, Definition 9, page 18. Euler, L. (1736/2008). Op cit. Vol. 1, Ch. 1, Scholium 1, page 17. 26 Euler, L. (1736/2008) op cit. Vol.1, Ch. 2, p. 59. http://www.17centurymaths.com/contents/euler/mechvol1/ch.2.pdf 27 Ibid. 25 15 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force We have demonstrated this result by using the second law of motion in the form F=ma. This was not, however, the form suggested by Newton. As noted by Jammer,28 the considered treatment of Euler was of particular importance, since starting from it the famous formula F=ma ("force equals mass multiplied by acceleration"), used by all of us today, eventually replaced the original Newtonian claim, which was apparently different and be represented in modern symbols as: Δ(mv) ∝ F One may write the correspondent equation, instead of the proportionality as: Δ( mv ) = FΔt The new form of the Newton's law – F=ma – serves us as an accurate definition of mass, as widely used in most of the modern textbooks of classical physics: m= F a In his later treatise, Euler returned to the criticism of the notion "inertial force" and wrote:29 SCHOLIUM 95. Calling this property inertia indicates that character of bodies, whereby being at rest means that they will continue to be at rest, therefore as if they oppose not being in that state of motion themselves; but since bodies set up in motion themselves equally oppose all to be changed, either on account of the speed or direction, this name is not a bad choice taken to account for the conservation of the state of rest or of motion. Also now and then it is called the force of inertia, because the force is a little resistant to the change of the state; but if the force is defined by some cause, which is changing the state of the body, here it is not in the least acceptable with this meaning; certainly the reason for this strongly disagrees with that by which henceforth we show a force to be acting. Whereby, lest any confusion should arise, we omit the name force and this property of the body and we will call it by the simpler name of inertia. We read that Euler saw the force to be of active origin that exerted on the body causing it to change its state, while inertia was due to the innate inert matter (conserving the state). Therefore, he inferred that the term "force of inertia" was contradictive and should be replaced by inertia to signify a property. 28 29 Jammer, M. (1961). Op cit. p.88 Euler, L. (1765/2009). Theory of the motion of solid or rigid bodies. [Theoria Motus Corporum Solidorum Seu Rigidorum], Vol. 1, Ch. 2, Concerning the Elements of Internal Motion, p. 60. http://www.17centurymaths.com/contents/mechanica3.html 16 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force D'Alembert: inertial force as a fictitious force in Newton's second law Another perspective on the inertial force was introduced by the great French scientist and philosopher Jean le Rond d'Alembert (1717-1783) who apparently was the first to introduce a very different approach to this concept.30 D'Alembert started with the adoption of the idea that force of inertia is a property of bodies Jean d'Alembert by which they preserve their state of rest or uniform motion. However, unlike Euler, for whom this force was fundamental, d'Alembert considered this approach ("a property") obscure and wanted to define all forces in the same way: by their result – the change of motion. For this purpose, he considered that Newton's second law, in the form suggested by Euler: F = ma, was the best framework to account for forces. In fact, one may see this law as a definition of force – "effective (or moving) force".31 Furthermore, within his rationalist intention to construct mechanics on universal principles, d'Alembert (under the influence of Archimedes treatment of lever) sought to reduce the physics of motion to the static principle of equilibrium.32 And so was done. Simple manipulation with the second law yields: F - ma = 0 ⇒ I ≡ - ma ⇒ F+I=0 Here a new force I was defined – the force of inertia. Was it the old force of inertia? Yes, it was. But if the old force was defined qualitatively and thus obscurely ("tendency"), the new one was given a precise mathematical formula. To support this idea, one may think about force I, as the "resistance to the change of motion", which nullifies the effect of an impressed external force. Together, the external agent and internal resistance 30 D'Alembert, J. (1758). Traité de dynamique. David Libraire, Paris. Later this idea, to define force by means of Newton's second law, was adopted by other physicists, supporters of positivist philosophy, such as Mach, Hertz and others. 32 We see here how strongly embedded in people the conceptual inequality between the state of rest and the state of motion. The preference of Statics, the state of rest, over Dynamics, is purely Aristotelian. 31 17 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force create a sort of balance, equilibrium. We have arrived to the d'Alembert principle:33 Any system of forces is in equilibrium if we add to the impressed forces the forces of inertia. Lagrange mentioned that d'Alembert reduced theory of motion to Statics.34 This, however, was only an illusion. Dynamics was imbedded within the expression for the force I (in the concealed acceleration a). Many physicists (e.g. Mach) saw the meaning of this manipulation and said that d'Alembert did not say anything new: no new physics can be obtained by transferring the term from one side of equation to another. Indeed, the essential difference between the forces, inertial I and external F, was that the latter was always interactive (in correspondence with Newton's third law) and the former was not. Therefore, for the physicists adopted Newton's paradigm of mechanics (absolute and unique space-time, central interactive forces) d'Alembert force of inertia was a mere hoax, and so it got an inferior status and even the name – fictitious force. Much later, in the 20th century, it was understood in what sense dynamics may indeed be reduced to statics: this change implies the change of the observer (reference frame). This, however, required a whole new picture of the world, not reached by physicists in the 18th and 19th centuries. The first step to this picture was, however, made already in the 17th century by Christian Huygens. New vision: Newton versus Huygens The influence of Newton on the adopted by scientists framework of physics thought was enormous. However there was another brilliant mind – Christian Huygens (1629-1695), a prominent Dutch physicist who worked almost in parallel to Newton and produced alternative ideas regarding the most fundamental issues of physics, both in mechanics and optics. Christian Huygens In the latter they confronted the ideas of particle (light rays) paradigm of Newton by the wave theory of light as elastic distortions in the ether medium. In our excurse to the history of inertia, we touch on another fundamental idea – the centrifugal force, which was differently interpreted by Newton and Huygens. 33 This is the modern formulation of the principle, as can be seen in Lanczos, C. (1949/1970). Variational principles of mechanics. Toronto: University of Toronto, p. 90. 34 Lagrange, J. L. (1783). Mechanique Analitique. Desaint, Paris. Translated into Russian (1938) by Gochman, V.S., GOSNTI, Moscow, p.176. Translated into English (1997). Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 191, Springer, New York. 18 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Introduced by Huygens in 1673 in his treatise De vi centrifuga (Concerning the centrifugal force), the centrifugal force was associated with circular motion. We will present both approaches one after the other, starting with Newton, which followed Huygens after several years (Newton's Principia was published in 1687). In considering circular motion, Newton first of all emphasized the centripetal force – the force applied on a body and causing it to follow circular path (the ball on the picture), instead of the inertial straight uniform motion. The centrifugal force – the radial force outward the center of rotation – was also addressed by Newton, but as the force that the Fcp Fcf circling body exerted on the constraint, the other body that caused this motion to the revolving body (on the rope or the person on the picture). In fact, in this subject, Newton To throw a ball (hammer throwing) the person first rotates it around herself. followed the steps of Descartes who analyzed circular motion before him. Describing the circular motion of Rene Descartes a stone in a sling, Descartes explicitly explained that because of the tendency of a stone to proceed in the tangential direction, AG (Fig.), the centrifugal effect is experienced by the sling: a radial tension which stretched the sling outwards, along EAD, manifesting "endeavor" (conatus, in Latin) to motion. This effect is a direct consequence of the body's tendency to move along Fcf the straight tangential path ACG. Newton adopted this view and, considering the body moving inside a solid circular frame along the sides of inscribed polygon, he wrote35: Fcp And if a body, moved with a given velocity along the sides of the polygon, is reflected from the circle at the several angular points, the force, with which at every reflection it strikes the circle at each 35 Newton, I. (1687/1999). Op. cit., Book I, Section 2, Scholium, pp. 452-453. 19 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force reflection, will be as its velocity: and therefore the sum of the forces, in a given time, will be as that velocity and the number of reflections jointly; … This is the centrifugal force, with which the body urges the circle; and the opposite force, with which the circle continually repels the body towards the center, is equal to this centrifugal force. (emphasis added) This definition of the centrifugal force matches the framework of Newton's paradigm of force: they are central and interactive, that is one always can point to a pair of force obeying the Newton's third law. Much later, Hertz,36 elaborated on this meaning of the centrifugal force: 37 We swing a stone attached to a string in a circle; we thereby consciously exert a force on the stone; this force constantly deviates the stone from a straight path, and if we alter this force, the mass of the stone or the length of the string, we discover that indeed the motion of the stone occurs at all times in agreement with Newton's second law. Now, the third law demands a force opposing that which is exerted by our hand on the stone. If we ask for this force, we obtain the answer familiar to everybody, that the stone reacts on the hand by virtue of the centrifugal force, and that this centrifugal force is indeed equal and opposite to the force exerted by us on the stone. … In summary, in Newton's mechanics, which became classical mechanics, centrifugal force was a regular interactive force, the reaction to the centripetal force. Huygens: The centrifugal force – the force for the rotating observer Huygens view was highly original. In 1659, before Newton introduced his laws of motion and theory of gravitation, Huygens' original mind produced the concept of centrifugal force38 and determined its variables. Today we express this force in modern symbolic way, by using the formula: F= mv 2 r Huygens could only describe the dependence of what he considered to be centrifugal force on different parameters: weight, velocity and radius of rotation, often through comparison between two bodies in a similar situation. 36 Heinrich Rudolf Hertz (1857 – 1894) was a prominent German physicist. In his "Principles of Mechanics Presented in a New Form" (1899) Hertz tried to create a new version of mechanics, reconsidering the concept of force. 37 Hertz, H., Mechanics /Collected Works, Vol. III, p. 6 38 Huygens, Ch. (1659/1703). On centrifugal force. From De vi Centrifuga, in Oeuvres Complètes, Vol. XVI, pp. 255-301, Translated by M.S. Mahoney. Online: http://www.princeton.edu/~hos/mike/texts/huygens/centriforce/huyforce.htm 20 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force However, one should not forget that Huygens never wrote this formula. Moreover, before Newton people thought only in terms of weight, which was not distinguished neither from inertial mass nor from the gravitational force, both inventions of Newton. Also the concept of force itself was ambiguous and not well defined concept, waiting for Newton's touch. And despite all these, Huygens was the first who tried to describe physical situation from the point of view of the observer in a rotating system. For that he used a thought experiment suggesting:39 Let us imagine some very large wheel, such that it easily carries along with it a man standing on it near the circumference but so attached that he cannot be thrown off; let him hold in his hand a string with a lead shot attached to the other end of the string. He made a statement regarding the tension in a string caused by the rotation and promised to clarify this dynamic situation: 40 The string will therefore be stretched by the force of revolution in the same way and with the same strength, whether it is so held or the same string is extended to the center at A and attached there. But the reason why it is stretched may now be more clearly perceived. To facilitate understanding of Huygens' writing we should first present the modern account for this case. distinguish T O b In our view, we between the Fcf description of situation made by -ma observer A, outside the wheel m (Fig.) and that by observer B, on B the mg mg* A wheel, whom considered Huygens. Observer A, the only one considered later by Newton, observes the tension of the rope T Body m suspended on the rope is located on the rotating disc. The situation is similar to the one described by Huygens. 39 40 and the gravitational force mg acting on the mass m and fully describes the rotation by means of Ibid. p. 1 Ibid. 21 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force the second Newton's law. As it is defined by modern physics, A presents inertial observer, the only kind of observer for whom Newton's laws hold. Observer B, considered by Huygens, does not see mass m at rotation (he rotates with the disc) and states that the ball is at rest, hence – equilibrium of forces acting on it. Tension T and the gravitational force mg are not sufficient to describe this state. He needs additional force –ma to reach equilibrium. It is this additional force (Fcf), not existing for Newton, but required by Huygens, that is termed today inertial force (Fin = -ma). Observer B, is defined as a non-inertial observer (the one employing inertial forces), and the rotating wheel presents a non-inertial frame of reference. Within this perspective we may understand the meaning of D'Alembert step of converting dynamic problem to a static one, as mentioned by Lagrange. It was the transformation of the description from one (inertial observer) to another (non-inertial one). Such a transition is accompanied by appearance of inertial force: Fin = - ma. Huygens: The inertial force is similar to the force of gravity Lacking Newton's theory of gravitation and Newton's laws of motion restricted Huygens very much in his treatment of rotation. Nevertheless, he made an ingenious guess trying to show that the gravity force is similar to the centrifugal force. Were he know the formulas we know: Fcf = m v2 r and Fg=mg he would immediately see that both forces are proportional to the mass of the object and in this sense they are essentially similar (they coincide in form if one uses notations aR= v2/R and ag=g). This implies that observer B on the disc might be misled regarding the gravitational force. This is because he does not distinguish between the gravitational force and weight – for him the heaviness of the suspended body at rest is mg*. Although observer A can clearly identify the gravitational weight (mg), he must depart from the identity between weight (measured by how heavy is the body to support) and the gravitation: for him they are different. This indeed could be the point to split between the concepts: gravitation and weight, but Huygens, although was very close to this inference, did not do it explicitly. 22 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Totally lacking the knowledge of laws of motion, but familiar with the works of Galileo and Descartes, Huygens drew on their conceptions. Unlike Newton, he defined gravity using Descartes' notion of conatus:41 Heaviness is a tendency to fall [Gravitas est conatus descendendi]. And then, he considered the rotating body fastened by a rope. Here, as was mentioned, Descartes specified the radial tension in the rope – conatus. The intention of Huygens was to show that there is no difference between this conatus and the tension due to the gravity. How could he do it? Huygens showed that if one frees the stone from the rope and the stone recedes along the strait line (in according with Descartes' second law of motion), then, the distances from the center of the wheel increase in a sequence that was exactly established by Galileo for the free fall of an object. This testifies, Huygens thought, for the identity of the nature of the rotational conatus (the centrifugal force) and the gravity. Here is the quote from Huygens' De vi Centrifuga:42 Let BG be a wheel that rotates parallel to the horizon about center A. A small ball attached to the circumference, when it arrives at point B, has a tendency to proceed along the straight line BH, which is tangent to the wheel at B. Now, if it were here separated from the wheel and flew off, it would stay on the straight path BH and would not leave unless it were pulled downward by the force of gravity or its course were impeded by collision with another body. At first glance it indeed seems difficult to grasp why the string AB is stretched so much when the ball tries to move along the straight line BH, which is perpendicular to AB. But everything will be made clear in the following way. Let us imagine some very large wheel, such that it easily carries along with it a man standing on it near the circumference but so attached that he cannot be thrown off; let him hold in his hand a string with a lead shot attached to the other end of the string. The string will therefore be stretched by the force of revolution in the same way and with the same strength, whether it is so held or the same string is extended to the center at A and attached there. But the reason why it is stretched may now be more clearly perceived. 41 42 Ibid. Ibid. 23 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Take equal arcs BE, EF very small in comparison to the whole circumference, say hundredth parts or even smaller. Therefore, the man I spoke of [as] attached to the wheel traverses these arcs in equal times, but the lead would traverse, if it were set free, straight lines BC, CD equal to the said arcs, the endpoints of which [lines] would not, however, exactly fall on the straight lines drawn from center A through points E, F, but would lie off these lines a slight bit toward B. Now it is clear that, when the man arrives at E, the lead will be at C if it was set free at point B, and when he arrives at F it will be at D. Whence we say correctly that this tendency is in the lead. But now if points C, D were on the straight lines AE, AF extended, it would be certain that the lead tended to recede from the man along the line drawn from the center through his position; and indeed such that in the first part of the time it would move away from him by the distance EC, and in the second part of the time it would be distant by the space FD. But these distances EC, FD, etc. increase as the series of the squares from unity, 1, 4, 9, 16, etc. Now they agree with this series ever more exactly as the particles BE, EF are taken to be smaller, and hence at the very outset they may be considered as if they differed nothing. Thus this tendency will clearly be similar to that which is felt when the ball is held suspended on a string, since then too it tends to recede along the line of the string with a similarly accelerated motion, i.e. such that in a first certain period of time it will traverse 1 interval, in two parts of time 4 intervals, in three 9, etc. Huygens' work on the centrifugal force is one of the most remarkable in mechanics of the 17th century. He preceded Newton's treatment of mechanics which though was more mature, did not considered non-inertial observers. In fact, he did not consider observers at all. His view of one static universe, to be described in the absolute space and time, implied one true observer – God. Therefore, also praised, even by Newton, Huygens' work was not be truly evaluated by anybody, including Huygens himself. Apparently, the time was not ripe for that. The idea of different observers entered the physics theory only by the beginning of the 20th century. Albert Einstein was the first who put inertial observers in the center of physics theory and it happened only in 1905. He did the same with the non-inertial observers in 1916. Huygens' non-inertial observer rotating with the wheel was actually able to declare the principle of equivalence of the general theory of relativity: 43 There is no experiment observers can perform to distinguish whether an acceleration arises because of a gravitational force or because their reference frame is accelerating 43 Giancoli, D. C. (1988). Physics for Scientists and Engineers. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, p. 155. 24 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force One may alternatively claim that this indistinguishability manifests the universal for all matter equality (or proportionality) between inertial and gravitational masses. Reality of inertial forces Huygens opened the door to the new physics, but nobody entered that door at his time, neither Newton, nor anybody else, including Huygens himself. Seemingly, there was a need first to go and construct physics without observer (or, more exactly of the unique observer) as Newton did. Even later, in the 18th century, as was shown above, after d'Alembert in 1758 by simple manipulation with Newtonian equation obtained the term of inertial force FI = -ma, even then and thereafter until the 20th century, this force was considered only as a casus: fictitious forces, those one can manage without. In the 19th century, physicists explained several phenomena depended on the rotation of the Earth, as observed by us, on the surface of the rotating globe – noninertial reference system. Such descriptions essentially involved inertial forces: centrifugal and Coriolis force (the latter presents inertial force on the object Centrifugal regulator of a steam machine: its simplest description is by the rotating observer and requires inertial force – centrifugal force moving in the non-inertial frame of reference, such as rotating Earth). The situation flipped, such phenomena as Foucault pendulum, cyclonic motion of the air in atmosphere and the difference in heights of banks of the rivers running along the longitude line are Cyclonic motion of the atmosphere: its description by the observer on the Earth requires inertial force – Coriolis force inconceivable without inertial forces, and physicists and engineers widely use them. This is how Sommerfeld wrote in his famous course of physics:44 44 Sommerfeld, A. (1952). Mechanics. Lectures on theoretical physics. Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press. 25 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Incidentally, the operation of railroads furnishes a very vivid example of the fact that the "fictitious" centrifugal force has a very real existence. On the curve, the rail bed is banked in such a way that the outer rail is higher than the inner. The difference in height is always such that for some mean velocity of the train the resultant of gravity and centrifugal force is perpendicular to the rail bed. This procedure eliminates not only the danger of overturning about the outer rail, but also a harmful unequal loading of the rails. Summary Our excursus to the history of "the force of inertia" revealed a complex and impressive conceptual story. In the ideas on inertia of Kepler, Newton, Euler, d'Alembert, Newton and Huygens we observed different conceptions. Summarizing these ideas could be helpful to understand the idea of inertia – one of the central in modern physics: Kepler introduced inertia and considered it as a passive resistance to motion (sluggishness). Descartes excluded the idea introduced by Kepler. He wrote: 45 I do not recognize any inertia or natural sluggishness in bodies… His rationale was that there is nothing but a conservation of [quantity of] motion and so only this principle governs the changes of motion of bodies. Newton conceived inertia as an active internal force with which the body preserves its state of uniform motion or rest and resists to their change. He also distinguished between weight (gravitational force) and inertial mass. Euler refused to consider inertia as a force and claimed it to be a faculty of the body by which it maintains its state of motion or rest. He also introduced the new form of the second Newton's law (currently used in introductory physics courses) F=ma, in which inertia entered as inertial mass m. Huygens introduced the inertial (centrifugal) force and revealed its reality while considering rotating (non-inertial) observer. He obtained the functional dependence of the centrifugal force: Fc.f. = 45 mv 2 r Descartes, R. (1976), Letter to Mersen. In Oeuvres de Descartes, C. Adams and P. Tannery (eds.), Paris: J. Vrin, Vol. 2, p. 466. 26 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force and demonstrated the essential similarity between the nature of the centrifugal force and gravity. The centrifugal force was the first inertial force introduced into physics. D'Alembert obtained the general form of inertial force, FI = -ma, but this step was considered as a trick by which any dynamic problem is reduced to static one. Only in the modern physics this same manipulation became a legitimate description of reality by the non-inertial observer moving with the accelerating frame of reference. Einstein, framed the modern physics by the possibility of multiple observers, which legitimized the inertial forces (in the form of d'Alembert) as real forces (as was the centrifugal force for Huygens), that is, defined operationally, by their effect described by the non- inertial observer. The personal history of inertia Johan Kepler Christian Huygens Isaac Newton Jean d'Alembert Albert Einstein * * * 27 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Historical and philosophical background including nature of science The nature of scientific knowledge is such that it develops gradually in the continuous process of inquiry. So, at each moment, it presents a cumulative product of human effort to make an objective sense of Nature, natural phenomena and reveal the principles of world organization. In the course of history, several scientific revolutions occurred when the tension between the unexplained by the old theory phenomena and the new theory, which did it and did it better, caused a conceptual change, creation of a new picture of the world that replaced the old one. A close look at the new theory may reveal that it always carries significant traces of the previous ideas, concepts, and features. This thought once surprised Heisenberg, when he heard it from Einstein. The idea that the new theory is inevitably linked to its predecessors could be illustrated by the history of inertia. In any case, the knowledge of conceptual roots in science occupies the history and philosophy of science and promotes a genuine understanding of contemporary concepts on behalf of students and teachers. Impetus – a conceptual predecessor of inertia A close look may reveal that inertia concept possesses traces of the central concept of earlier physics – the impetus. The latter was central in the medieval physics of motion.46 In the course of the scientific revolution of the 17th century, impetus was criticized and refuted due to the efforts of Galileo and Descartes. However, the idea of a sort of "charge of motion" possessed by the moving body and causing bodies to move seems reasonable to the common sense of people who associate motion with certain faculty ("fuel of motion"). As such, it often presents a barrier to the novice learner begins of physics. In complete similarity to impetus, classical mechanics considers inertia to be the faculty of preserving by a body its state of uniform motion or rest. Hence, inertia replaced impetus in its role to support motion in classical physics after 17th century. Two faces of inertia Basing on the everyday experience, one may ask herself why is it difficult to move things? And also, why do things, we set in motion, preserve movement for a while, after we stop pushing them? Is there anything in the moving body, thought medieval scholars, that prevents it from stopping, getting at rest which seemed to be a natural 46 See the correspondent module on the history of the theory of motion in this collection. 28 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force state since Aristotle? Aristotle did not answer these questions. He did not ascribe to bodies any inherent resistance: if the body was pushed, it moved in proportion to the push. Kepler's view was the same. He only expanded this view to planets and for them introduced inertia as the ability to resist the push from the sun. The medieval scholars asked about that something which kept things in motion but continued to see the resistance of bodies to start motion because of their weight. Although these two phenomena might look different, Newton united them in the same cause – inertia, the force resisting any change of motion. To unite several phenomena under the same cause was one of his philosophical principles – rules of reasoning in natural philosophy – that he followed. This step matched the physical relativity of motion as stated by Galileo and known to Newton. Suppose we observe body accelerating from the rest (v1=0 at t1=0) to the velocity of 1m/sec (v2=1 at t2=1). The same body would be seen to the observer moving with the velocity V=1m/sec in the same direction as another change: from v'1=-1 (at t1=0) to v'2=0 (at t2=1). Galileo stated that there were no differences between the two pictures; the first observer saw the body accelerating from the rest to motion and the other – decelerating from motion to rest! So, Newton inferred: as long as we go with physics, there should be one faculty of bodies which do both: resist to "motion" (one observer) and causes motion preservation (another observer). This universal faculty was inertia. This progress made by Newton regarding inertia might remind recognizing by the ancient astronomers that "evening star" and "morning star" were actually the same object, planet Venus, that being close to the sun may appear to us at sunset or sunrise. Evolution of the role of observer Historically, the laws of motion were established first by Newton and they are valid for describing reality only by inertial observers. The work of Huygens exploring the view of the rotating observer was confusing. This confusion was removed only after clarifying the status of inertial forces. It became clear that these forces are particular for the non-inertial observers and allow them to apply the same framework of laws of motion. Expansion of the area of validity, the ability to serve any observer, represents the nature of science, which seeks the most inclusive framework of universal and objective account for natural phenomena – no discrimination among the observers. 29 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force One may identify three important periods in the perception of the role of observer: I. The physics of Aristotle. In it, the universe, cosmos, was considered to be spherical, finite, static and geocentric in appearing to the observer who by contemplation can reveal its nature and law-kind regularity. II. The classical physics of 17-19 centuries changed this picture, but, in a sense, not too much. Newton stated the space to be absolute and immobile reservoir of the world moving in absolute time – in a sense, quite in accord with the Aristotelian view. The change in understanding the universe as infinite and Galileo's relativity made all inertial observers equal in practicing physics, but all of them observed the same unique picture (force description of the reality). Other viewers were illegitimate in physics. III. The modern physics (from the 20th century) cause the fundamental change. Following the vision of Einstein, any observer became legitimate for physical description. Non-inertial observers used for that inertial forces. Physics reached the universal picture of the world by means of objective laws, which could be formulated regardless the observer. Furthermore, the introduction by Einstein the principle of equivalence, which states identity of the force of inertia to the gravitational force for the non-inertial observer, allowed the new understanding of weight of the body and caused by either gravitation or inertia.47 Making all observers equally legitimate in physics was establishing a philosophical principle of the fundamental importance. Expanding the concept of force The history of inertial force touches on the meaning of the concept of force in general. It was Newton who created an all inclusive paradigm of classical mechanics with the concept of force in its center: the universe was considered as an empty space with point masses interacting in pairs by means of central forces. Being central implied the force exerted by one particle on the other on the line connecting between them. However, his definition of impressed force was more inclusive:48 An impressed force is an action exerted upon a body, in order to change its state, either of rest, or of moving uniformly forward in a right line 47 See more about the weight concept in the special module of the history of this concept in this collection. 48 Newton, I. (1687/1952). Op.cit., Definitions, Definition 4, p. 6 30 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force This definition does not restrict force to be central or interactive (as the gravitational force) but to exclude any other factor causing the change of state of rest or motion. Perhaps it is not fair to expect from Newton this subtlety at the time when all known interactions (gravitational, static electricity and natural magnets (loadstones)) worked at straight line between the agent and subject. Only the discovered by Oersted in 1820 force of electric current on magnetic needle, and the magnetic force on a charge introduced by Maxwell in 1861 were not central. They, however, still matched the Newtonian requirement of forces: they caused the change of state of motion. The new requirement of operational concept definition for physical quantities was recognized later, by the positivistic philosophy of science starting from Mach49, Kirchhoff and Hertz, at the end of the 19th century. This was an epistemological revolution in physical concepts. Following it, Einstein applied operational definition to simultaneity in the theory of special relativity, which caused the new scientific revolution in 1905. The requirement for operational definition for any physical quantity was the basis of the special philosophical trend – operationalism.50 Later it was moderated by modern philosophers of science,51 by demonstrating the necessity of both nominal (theoretical) and operational definitions to define concepts in physics. In any case, ever since, the importance of the operational definitions was widely recognized in physics. After this introduction, the problematic of inertial force becomes clear: one need to provide an operational definition of force. In the classical physics, the force is often determined as a manifestation of interaction between objects. The inertial force is not interactive and failed to be the force in this perspective (one cannot point to the pair of objects interacting by means of this force: action-reaction air). However, if one introduces an operation definition of force (as a cause of elastic deformation of a spring of the force-meter) inertial forces become legitimate (causing the change of state of motion), a subject to measurement by an observer (the non-inertial observer). This development, the recognition of the inertial forces as real, presents an impressive illustration of the epistemological change introduced by the modern physics 49 e.g. operational definition of mass in Mach (1893/1970). Op. cit. Bridgman, P. (1927/1952) The Nature of Some of Physical Concepts. New York: Philosophical Library. 51 e.g., Margenau, H. (1950) The Nature of Physical Reality. New York: McGraw-Hill, pp. 220-244. 50 31 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force On the nature of the scientific knowledge The history of inertia illustrates the dialectical nature of the scientific knowledge. Following this history one observes that evolution of understanding of inertia started from qualitative descriptions and eventually arrived to the accounts by formal principles. The qualitative and formal (mathematical and quantitative) accounts for inertia developed synergistically and are deeply interwoven. Indeed, as long as the first ideas of inertia by Kepler and Galileo were solely qualitative the concept of inertia could not have practical applications. Newton started with the same approach in his first law, but then he introduced a quantifiable concept of inertial mass, m, and the second law, which resulted in flourishing of various applications, mathematical accounts of physical systems. Importantly, Huygens' innovative application of dynamics to the observer on a rotating wheel and obtaining by him functional dependence of the centrifugal force, the first inertial force known, did not cause further progress at that time. The fact of proportionality of inertial to the gravitational mass was also known to Newton (see above the quote from Principia). However, he failed to explain it and could only express his surprise of such coincidence. Inertia remained an enigma: Huygens failed trying to use his centrifugal force in explaining gravitation as a residual force, and D'Alembert's inertial force was considered only as a trick, good for problem solving. The philosophers of physics abandoned fictitious inertial forces. It all changed soon after the elucidating interpretation of the same reality provided by Albert Einstein in his theory of general relativity, in 1916. Non-inertial reference frames made inertial forces legitimate in physics. One may imply that neither practical use of physical construct nor its interpretation exclude or surpass each other in importance. They coexist in dialectical complementarity in science. The later presents the major feature of the scientific method. Paraphrasing Einstein, one may say that conceptual understanding without mathematics is empty but mathematical formalism without conceptual interpretation is blind. Furthermore, the history of inertial concept testifies for the special diachronic discourse maintained in physics regarding certain fundamental concepts. If after the first part of this excurse we could summarize the history of the inertial force and represent it in a line of inventions of physicists followed each other in a chronological 32 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force line (see above); now, considering the conceptual genesis of the inertial force, we may represent the same process as a diachronic dialogue of the great minds. In a sense, this representation ignores the time the certain scholars were active and represent the nature of the scientific knowledge in a different manner as demonstrated in the following picture. It is in this sense the scientific knowledge is cumulative. It is a fictitious force of reaction Tendency similar to gravity It is a push of medium It is a feature of a material body Indifference to motion Gravity and inertia are indistinct It is laziness of material bodies It is impetus… It is an illusion of force, just an implication of motion conservation It is an internal force On the nature of scientific concepts The concept of inertial force may shed light on the nature of scientific concepts. The fact that inertial force "exists" only for non-inertial observers suggests clarification of concepts "existence" – an ontological aspect of physics knowledge. We often use to consider interactive forces as if really existed. In what sense do they exist? A discussion on this topic may lead to recognition of force (a physics concept) to be an artifact, a mental tool to describe certain objective reality. If it appears that people can imagine alternative descriptions, forces may disappear (there is no forces in classical sense in quantum theory!), similarly to the disappearance of inertial forces for the inertial observers. Thus, in the general theory of relativity, there is no 33 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force gravitational force, but a curved space-time which causes the effect ("attraction" of material objects) that we describe in classical mechanics by means of the gravitational force. Reference to the status of inertial force, therefore, may lead one to the discovery of the true status of scientific concepts which we operate with so freely, normally without any second thought. Distinguishing between the physical description and the real world may eventually arrive to the appreciation of the difference between physics, as human knowledge, and the real world that the humankind makes its best to describe by means of physical theories and physical concepts. * * * Target group, curricular relevance and didactical benefit As was shown, the topic of inertia and the forces of inertia are not new in physics. Making legitimate non-inertial observers was the progress in the modern physics already at the beginning of the 20th century. Therefore, considering inertial forces in physics class could introduce students into the ontology and epistemology of the modern physics. However, the system of education is slow in following this development. The gap between science and curriculum with regard to the inertial forces is already about 100 years, despite of no formal complexity related to this topic. Inertia and inertial forces are usually not included in regular and even the advanced placement secondary school curriculum.52 The exposed here historical excurse may support teachers, curriculum designers, science museums, and policy makers in education in changing this policy and including inertial forces into the science curriculum. Another goal for this project is to illustrate worthiness of using the history of science in regular teaching physics. Researchers of science education observed that teachers refrained from using historical materials:53 … even materials produced for teachers, for example, those produced in the UK … are not used. Attempts to produce restructured courses that put history at the center of the enterprise … have enjoyed only marginal success, as have those that have sought to introduce a more rigorous and current view of the philosophy of science … 52 53 The situation in the secondary education in Israel, the UK, and the USA. Monk, M., & Osborne, J. (1997). Placing the History and Philosophy of Science on theCurriculum: a model for the development of pedagogy. Science Education, 81(4),405-424. 34 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Science educators and scientists involved in teaching also explained their negative attitude to using HPS-based materials.54 They usually reason by two factors: (a) teachers believe that historical materials, by presenting old theories, conceptions and scientific methods that were surpassed in the course of physics development, put astray the learners, confuse them by contents not relevant for studying physics today; (b) teachers often state total lacking of time for including additional materials into the instruction already overloaded by the abundance of materials required by the curriculum. Our examination, however, suggests that there could be another reason behind these two: the programs of teacher training (as well as the regular programs of training practitioners in science) normally do not include any exposure to the philosophy of science and neither to the history of science.55 Clearly, lacking the appropriate background, people cannot evaluate the beneficial potential of such type of materials, at least in parallel to the different reasons to avoid using the history and philosophy of science. For this very reason, our historical excurse was developed. It addresses, first of all, the teachers of physics – prospective and already practicing – showing that historical materials are worth, relevant and beneficial. We invested a special effort to expose the gradual consolidation of the present understanding of inertial forces through several steps made by brilliant minds of the past who developed the concept of inertial force. In educational perspective, this material may serve as a teaching unit and a resource, original and not available in this form in other places. What makes using historical materials essential? Among other reasons,56 we may mention the specific rationale with regard to the inertial forces and non-inertial observers. It is commonplace to admit that teaching science in order to be effective 54 Galili, I. & Hazan, A. (2001a). Experts' views on using history and philosophy of science in the practice of physics instruction. Science & Education, 10 (4), pp. 345-367. 55 The situation in Israel. 56 This issue in general terms was elaborated in the paper Galili, I. (2010), Promotion of Cultural Content Knowledge through the use of the History and Philosophy of Science, submitted to Science & Education. 35 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force should address the naïve knowledge of the learners in the considered topic. This presents a central tenet of educational constructivism.57 The topic of inertial forces and non-inertial observers obtains its special importance because in the regular life environment of the modern society, a person frequently finds oneself in considerably accelerating systems, accumulating rich experience as a non-inertial observer, and observing such environments in the media (films, news, and documentary). In many real-life situations, it is simply impossible to ignore such sense experience (sense-data): in accelerated vehicles, while jumping and falling, observing astronauts in space stations and many others. Moreover, we all use to ignore the experience as inertial observers for its routine nature. Personal sense experience of students as non-inertial observers cast their naive knowledge organized in explanatory patterns (schemes of knowledge58). They structure our common sense as deeply entrenched believes. In class teaching, these naïve and often wrong schemes (known under the name alternative or mis-conceptions) often collide with the "teacher's truth" presented for learning. This collision significantly impedes the result of learning which often presumes a radical conceptual change (Fig.)59. This is especially true regarding inertial forces, due to the rich experience in non-inertial frames of reference. Even good students widely use in practice inertial forces despite of the apparent contradiction with the curriculum and the instruction they received.60 Schemes of naïve knowledge Generated explanations of reality based on the schemes The principles of classical mechanics – "Teacher's knowledge" of mechanics Students' conceptual change in the course of learning can be represented as an exchange of contents between the core ideas and periphery knowledge (shown by arrows) 57 Duit, R. & Treagust, D. F. (1998). Learning in science - from behaviorism towards social constructivism and beyond. In B. Fraser & K.G. Tobin (Eds.), International handbook of science education (pp. 3–25). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer. 58 e.g. Galili, I. & Hazan, A. (2000). Learners' knowledge in optics: interpretation, structure, and analysis. International Journal in Science Education, 22(1), 57-88. 59 Tseitlin, M. & Galili I. (2005). Teaching physics in looking for its self: from a physics-discipline to a physics-culture, Science & Education, 14 (3-5), 235-261. 60 Galili, I. & Kaplan, D. (2002). ‘Students’ interpretation of water surface orientation and inertial forces in physics curriculum’. Praxis der Naturwissenschaften Physik in der Schule, 51(7), pp. 2-11 36 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Technology provides another strong motivation to deal with inertial forces. Modern society is saturated with different manifestation of inertial forces: all kind of centrifuges for separation of different materials in their densities, regulators of rotation speeds (Watt's centrifugal regulator), rotational satellite (meanwhile available only in science fiction movies like "2001: A Space Odyssey" by Kubrik), etc. Each teacher for car driving uses the concept of centrifugal force to explain why one should not drive too fast on a curved road. Seemingly, inertial forces are used everywhere but in the physics class. This ignoring reality is not a recommended curricular policy in all educational approaches. Centrifugal regulator of spinning rate Rotational space station providing weight to its inhabitants. The idea is used in science fiction movies such, such as "2001: A Space Odyssey" by Stanly Kubrik, seen by many students. Another aspect of the relevance of treating inertial forces in physics class may stem from the research reports that inform about students' naïve materialization ("reification") of abstract physical quantities such as heat, force, light, electric current, gravity, potential, light ray, etc.61 Discussion of inertial forces – existed to some observers, but not to the others, may lead to the remedy of this naïve knowledge. Confusing terminology The force of inertia is the notion that may cause confusion for its multiple meanings used by different authors. Perhaps the most striking problem is related to the impression on students and teachers of the titles "fictitious" and "pseudo" often attached to the inertial force. In this regard, one may recollect that these terms were introduced into physics with regard to d'Alembert results, not understood for a very long time beyond a trick 61 Reiner, M., Slotta, J.D., Chi, M.T.H., & Resnick, L.B. (2000). Naive Physics Reasoning: A Commitment to Substance-Based Conceptions. Cognition and Instruction, 18(1), 1–34. Galili, I. & Lavrik, V. (1998). Flux concept in learning about light. a critique of the present situation. Science Education, 82 (5), 591-614. 37 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force of theoretical physics.62 It is recommended, therefore, to check the time when this or other quote of the scientist, used as a reference, was made. The clarification of the status of the non-inertial observers was performed only by Einstein and never before. In the modern physics, forces are defined operationally, and therefore, inertial forces are legitimate dynamic characteristics of physical situation, keeping in mind the particular frame of reference used for the description. Another kind of confusion is possible with regard to the meaning of centrifugal force. Some authors still use it in the meaning of Newton, that is, as an interactive partner of the centripetal force. In this definition, the centrifugal force is the force acting on the constraint (the rope, sling, hand or thread that causes the object revolving around certain axis). This use has nothing to do with non-inertial observers. As the way to avoid confusion, it is recommended to carefully clarify the meaning of inertial force used by the particular author or lecturer. The importance of the concept definitions in physics teaching was demonstrated.63 It illustrates physics as an exact science. The need for rigor definition of concepts became a characteristic feature of the scientific knowledge in contrast to arts. The relationship of inertial forces with weight Since the gravitational force is identical in effect to the inertial force, as stated by the principle of equivalence, the operational definition of weight ("weight is the result of weighing") allows both gravitational and inertial forces equally contribute to the weight of the object. Therefore, teaching inertial forces could be related to teaching weight (including Weight in the rotational cabin of the spaceship as shown in movie Stanly Kubrik "2001: A Space Odyssey". weight due to the centrifugal force) and thus making learning physics more conceptually interrelated and therefore more meaningful. 62 The formal designation of F=-ma as a force of inertia was made more than one hundred years after d'Alembert by French mathematician and astronomer Charles Delaunay who presented the results of d'Alembert. We, however, may not change the tradition of ascribing this step to d'Alembert. 63 Galili, I. & Lehavi, Y. (2006). Definitions of physical concepts: a study of physics teachers' knowledge and views. International Journal of Science Education, 28 (5), 521-541. 38 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Teaching about the inertial force supports the operational definition of weight and facilitates it with the definition: "Weight is the force exerted by the object on its support. It could be due to either gravitational or inertial forces". This relationship between the two forces was foreseen by Huygens as early as in 1659. * * * Activities, methods and media for learning Questionnaires, inquiry suggestions, role-play activities It is very important to ask students straightforward conceptual questions to provide them with an opportunity to articulate their conceptual understanding. Among such questions regarding the subject of inertia and inertial forces, there could be the following: • Inertia was introduced by Kepler in the 17th century. How could scholars managed in describing the same reality before Kepler? Consider separately Aristotelian and medieval periods. • Descartes did not recognize inertial force and stated sufficient to account for reality by means of conservation of motion in collisions: big body receive less speed. Argue whether this approach allows avoiding inertial forces. • Is inertia a force? Illustrate your answer. • When we set in motion a heavy revolving door of a hotel, what do we struggle with: (a) the force of gravity, (b) friction, (c) inertia? – Explain your choice and refutation of other options. • What is the force of inertia? Bring few examples of action of inertial forces. • Describe physical situations which justify the use of inertial force. What is special in such situations? • Why physicists ascribed to label fictitious to the inertial force? What is wrong with these forces? Are they real? • Descartes and Huygens tried their best to explain gravitation by means of the centrifugal force. How could it be possible if the centrifugal force by its definition directs outwards, from the center of rotation whereas the gravitational force attracts bodies inwards, to the center of attraction? 39 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force • Explain the movement of the body of a driver in a suddenly stopping (or quickly accelerating) car. • Small helium balloon is floating inside a stopping car. Show the inertial force exerted on it and explain the movement of the balloon in a stopping (or accelerating) car. Relate your answer to the explanation of gravitation by Descartes and Huygens. • Imagine a debate between Newton and Einstein regarding the inertial forces. Newton would reject them and Einstein – support. Who was right in this debate? Explain. • Huygens did not consider his centrifugal force fictitious but real. Feynman in his course called inertial forces “effective” (acting as a force). Hertz thought that all forces are fictions. Who was right? • In Newton's famous thought experiment with a rotating bucket, water surface became curved and receives a parabolic shape.64 Try to explain this phenomenon with and without using centrifugal force. Which description is easier for you? Which one is correct? Furthermore, students are often interested in debates, defending description of either with or without inertial forces. Students may prepare themselves for such a debate by reading the related materials, including the excurse above and the mentioned here questions. Students may imagine their heroes as cultural and historical figures living in certain social historical environment. The Internet presents the most available recourse for the materials facilitating this kind of activity. Here are some useful links: http://www.rarebookroom.org/ – The "Rare Book Room" site may allow the visitor to examine and read some of the great books from the history of science. http://gallica.bnf.fr/?lang=en – "Gallica" an online library of the National Library of France makes available works of many authors from the history of science and philosophy. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Project_Gutenberg – Project Gutenberg is the Internet's oldest producer of free access to digital books. Among other resources of learning materials in the history of mechanics are: 64 Newton, I. (1687/1999). Op.cit., Definitions, Scholium, p. 407. 40 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force - the historical overview of mechanics by Lagrange, one of the major contributors to the formulation of classical mechanics in its canonical analytical form used today in theoretical physics;65 - Hertz's presentation of classical mechanics could be elucidating, since he suggested a different framework of forces and included inertial forces.66 - Einstein and Infeld made a historical overview of mechanics,67 where they explained the introduction of inertial forces in modern perspective. Discursive activity The appeal to the past is a cultural action in which knowledge appears as human product of continuous effort. Culture is commonly understood as dialogical by its very definition. Indeed, culture includes various ideas suggested by different people and in different historical periods. Every idea contributes to culture although does not play equal role in a particular inquiry. This perception presents an achievement of the philosophical thought of the 20-th century and could be referred to Bakhtin's dialogical approach68 to understanding and teaching. Within it, one may say that different viewpoints on the forces of inertia establish a discourse, or dispute, which investigates the subject from different point of view. To facilitate the class practice of this approach we extract here the historically separated ideas of inertia and inertial forces and suggest them as dispute positions in a cultural dialogue to be arranged in a class. This type of activity is quite unusual and therefore we present these views again in a list: Kepler: Inertia is laziness (sluggishness) of bodies by which they impede any motion, striving to remain at rest. (although this view originally addressed only planets we expanded it to all material bodies). Descartes: There is no inertia or inertial force at all. Objects obey conservation of motion and keep it naturally. No cause is required to proceed motion. 65 Lagrange, J. L. (1788/1997). Analytical Mechanics (Introduction). Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht. 66 Hertz, H. (1894/1956). The Principles of mechanics presented in a new form. New York: Dover. http://www.archive.org/details/principlesmecha00hertgoog 67 Einstein, A. & Infeld, L. (1938/1967). Evolution of Physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 68 Bakhtin, Mikhail Mikhailovich (1895-1975) was Russian philosopher and literary critic. He is especially known in our days for his introduction of dialogism, and spatio-temporal description (chronotope) of social narratives and situations in their plurality of meanings. 41 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force Newton: The inertial force is the internal force by which any material body struggles with any external agent. The agent tries to change the state of the uniform rectilinear motion or rest of the body and the latter resists. Hugens: The inertial (centrifugal) force is a real force acting radially outward. The centrifugal force is exerted on the rotating body. This force is similar in nature to the gravity. Euler: Inertia is a faculty embedded in all bodies causing their ability to stay at the state of rest or continuous uniform rectilinear motion. The resistance to the change of motion manifests itself in the inertial mass of the body. The whole phenomenon is formally expressed by the second law of motion in the form: F=ma. Physicist of the 18-19 centuries: The inertial force is the name for the term in the equation of motion: -ma. This construct is not a force, although it has a dimension of force. This is because one cannot point to the pair of bodies interacting with such force. Therefore one may call it a fictitious force. Inertia of the body ie represented by inertial mass m in the second Newton's law. Modern technician-engineer: Inertia is the force acting on the spinning body pushing it radially outwards. It is this force that breaks the rope or thread holding the rotating body when the spinning rate increases. (Isn't that a proof that this force is real?) Modern physicist: The forces of inertia are forces, which allow the description of reality by non-inertial observers (the observer in accelerating systems). Inertial forces make possible using the same laws of motion by all observers. Expert in gravitation: The inertial force is indistinguishable (locally, that is, in a small area) from the force of gravitation and manifests the curvature of the space-time in the particular location. Although the teacher normally identifies him/herself with physicist's view, it is essential that students meet with multiple views. This type of teaching creates an 42 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force extended space of learning and teaches the goal concept in variation – the method proved to be effective for the meaningful learning.69 This approach also fits to the perception of modern scientific thinking as dialogical. The scientific knowledge allows multiple points of view. Cultural knowledge implies the knowledge of alternatives. This nature of science may be contrasted by the religious idea of a single truth, one reaches in a linear progress of learning and development, as represented by a ladder in popular images. * * * Obstacles to teaching and learning The main difficulty of the considered topic is that the forces of inertia are different from interactive forces, such as, for example, the force of electric or gravitational interaction, friction, buoyant force. Although each of them is special, all of them are interactive and none was labeled fictitious. This presents a difficulty to leaning and teaching. History of science reveals the controversy related to the inertial forces and explains the contradiction between the Newtonian framework of forces with the framework of the non-inertial observers. Instead of the straightforward rejection, physics teachers may afford a wiser, more subtle standpoint. They may suggest first to familiarize with the arguments of several sides, "for" and "contra" of inertial forces. Knowledge of the historical background may shake the rigidity of the extreme attitudes. Knowledge of several options (the space of knowledge) usually causes certain tolerance and plurality on behalf of the person who possesses such knowledge. Clarification of Newton's views on the inertial force, the criticism of Euler, Newton's interpretation of centrifugal force (the force on the constraint), the formal approach of d'Alembert, operational definition of force and evolution of the role of observer – may 69 Marton, F. & Tsui, A.B.M. (2004). Classroom discourse and the space of learning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. 43 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force all soften the rigidity of those ignoring inertial forces in favor of the "simple truth" of inertial account. The arguments in favor of the reality of inertial forces often refer to the "real effect produced by inertial forces". Thus, the rotating stone may break the sling when one increases the rate of rotation, testifying for the reality of the tension caused by the centrifugal force. Could it be merely fictitious? This seems to some being a cut edge argument, an ultimately convincing claim, but in fact, it suffers from a serious logical shortcoming. Arguing by real effect does not say anything regarding forces which are a tool of description not a real object. Indeed, the tension is the string is real, but in the viewpoint of an inertial observer it has another cause – the inertial mass of the rotating stone, striving to proceed along the line tangential to the circle. At a sufficiently high speed of the body, the effort to cause it the required turn is beyond the ability of the thread to sustain such tension it breaks. It is only the rotating (non-inertial) observer, who does not observe any motion of the stone, needs "the real cause" for breaking the thread introduces the centrifugal outward force. The main "problem" (or simply – the feature) of inertial forces is that they are not interactive (no action-reaction pair of interaction). But is it possible that we simply do not know the second partner? Einstein revealed that inertial forces could be always interpreted as a certain gravitational field. The latter is known as a regular interaction between bodies. This idea develops Mach's hypothesis (principle)70 stating to the cause for inertial forces to be interaction with the distant stars and galaxies, the interaction depending on the relative acceleration between the masses. This consideration, however, presents an open problem in physics for the complexity to evaluate the dynamic gravitational interaction of this type.71 Meanwhile, one cannot be very certain in negating the noninteractive nature of the inertial forces. Another difficulty for the learner appears in some advanced courses of mechanics, stating that inertia increases with the speed of the body, being a relativistic effect. The careful treatment, however, reveals the limits of this claim.72 Although energy 70 This idea comes back to the philosophizing of G. Berkeley (1726). The Principles of Human Knowledge. §§111–117, 1710 71 Sciama, D. W. (1971). Modern Cosmology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 72 Okun, L. B. (1989), The Concept of Mass, Physics Today, 42 (6): 31–36. 44 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force and momentum do increase with velocity, the construct m=E/c2, in general case of any velocity, does not present a relativistic quantity. It is only the rest mass, m=E0/c2, which presents a relativistic scalar, that is, a fundamental invariant constant. The rest mass (inertial mass) of a body does not change regardless the speed. * * * Pedagogical skills Teaching about inertial forces requires from a teacher a special pedagogical skill. The difficulty of the subject is not formal but rather due the conceptual complexity of inertia, the concept of force, in general, and the inertial force, in particular. Indeed, as mentioned, the concepts of inertia and the force of inertia possess controversy. This means that the topic is difficult because it requires a dialectical view. This aspect touches on a more general requirement of teaching physics. At the introductory level, physics requires presentation as a dialogue of ideas. At least, this is a dialogue between the teacher and student (constructivism). In practice, however, physics is rarely taught as such. Too often students' views are ignored and teaching becomes a univocal indoctrination. Although this way might seem easier to perform and assess, it does not adequately represent the subject matter. The topic of inertial forces and inertia is inherently plural, both in addressing the concept, as well as in the need of different types of observers. Presentation of this issue in class requires the pedagogical skill of dialectic (many faceted) presentation. The ability to teach by using dialectic approach is not genetic and can be developed. The least confusing way to present the subject of the inertial forces is seemingly displaying its historical evolution as was done in this excurse. The important feature of such pedagogy is presenting different views of scholars even if some of them seem less justified or wrong. They together create a dialogue and invite consideration, discussion, analysis, which lead to learning. These views expand the subject and relate it to other topics. In short, this pedagogy creates Cultural Content Knowledge. This way the teacher better matches the interest and skills of different personalities among the students, as required in presenting physics in the modern society. * * * 45 Excurse to the History of Inertial Force