Whistle-Blowing and Employee Loyalty
Transcription
Whistle-Blowing and Employee Loyalty
Ethical Treatment of Employees (1990): 19-41; John M. Whelan, "Charity and the Duty to Rescue," Social Theory and Practice 17, no. 3 (1991): 441-56; and David Copp, "Responsibility for Collective Inaction, "Journal of Social Philosophy 22, no. 2 (1991): 71-80. See, for example, David Theo Goldberg, "Tuning In to Whistle Blowing," Business and Professional Ethics Journal!, no. 2 (1988): 85-94. For an explanation of why whistle-blowing is inevitably a high risk undertaking, see my "Avoiding the Tragedy of Whistleblowing," Business and Professional Ethics fournal 8, no. 4 (1989): 3-19. 5. After I presented this paper in Klamath Falls, Boisjoly told me that though his motive for testifying as he did was (as I surmised) to prevent falsification of the record, part of his reason for wanting to prevent that was that he wanted to do what he could to prevent the managers responsible for the disaster from having any part in redesigning the boosters. This secondary motive is, of course, consistent with the complicity theory. 155 De George, p. 210: "The notion of .smoMsharm might be expanded to include serious financial harm, and kinds of harm other than death and serious threats to health and body. But as we noted earlier, we shall restrict ourselves here to products and practices that produce or threaten serious harm or danger to life and health." See Myron Peretz Glazer and Penina Migdal Glazer, The Whistleblowers: Exposing Corruption in Government and Industry (New York: Basic Books, 1989) for a good list of whistle-blowers (with detailed description of each); for an older list (with descriptions), see Alan F Westin, Whistleblowing! Loyalty and Dissent in the Corporation (NewYork: McGraw-Hill, 1981). Compare De George, p. 211: "By reporting one's concern to one's immediate superior or other appropriate person, one preserves and observes the regular practices of firms, which on the whole promote their order and efficiency; this fulfills one's obligation of minimizing harm, and it precludes precipitous whistle blowing." (Italics mine.) Whistle-Blowing and Employee Loyalty Ronald Duska T h e r e are p r o p o n e n t s o n b o t h sides of t h e i s s u e — t h o s e w h o praise whistle-blowers as civic h e r o e s a n d those w h o c o n d e m n t h e m as "finks." Maxwell Glen a n d Cody Shearer, who wrote about the whistle-blowers at T h r e e Mile I s l a n d say, " W i t h o u t t h e courageous b r e e d of assorted c o m p a n y insiders known as whistle-blowers—workers who often risk their livelihoods to disclose information about construction a n d design flaws—the Nuclear Regulatory Commission itself would b e nearly as idle as T h r e e Mile Island. . . . T h a t whistleblowers deserve b o t h gratitude a n d protection is beyond disagreement." Still, while Glen a n d Shearer praise whisdeblowers, others vociferously condemn them. For Reprinted by permission of the author. example, in a now infamous quote, James Roche, the former president of General Motors said: Some critics are now busy eroding another support of free enterprise—the loyalty of a management team, with its unifying values and cooperative work. Some of the enemies of business now encourage an employee to be disloyal to the enterprise. They want to create suspicion and disharmony, and pry into the proprietary interests of the business. However this is labeled— industrial espionage, whistle-blowing, or professional responsibility—it is another tactic for spreading disunity and creating conflict.2 F r o m R o c h e ' s p o i n t of view, n o t only is whistle-blowing n o t " c o u r a g e o u s " a n d n o t d e s e r v i n g of " g r a t i t u d e a n d p r o t e c t i o n " as 156 Ethical Treatment of Employees Glen and Shearer would have it, it is corrosive and impermissible. Discussions of whistle-blowing generally revolve around three topics: (1) attempts to define whistle-blowing more precisely, (2) debates about whether and when whistle-blowing is permissible, and (3) debates about whether and when one has an obligation to blow the whistle. In this paper I want to focus on the second problem, because I find it somewhat disconcerting that there is a problem at all. When I first looked into the ethics of whistle-blowing it seemed to me that whistle-blowing was a good thing, and yet I found in the literature claim after claim that it was in need of defense, that there was something wrong with it, namely that it was an act of disloyalty. If whistle-blowing is a disloyal act, it deserves disapproval, and ultimately any action of whistleblowing needs justification. This disturbs me. It is as if the act of a good Samaritan is being condemned as an act of interference, as if the prevention of a suicide needs to be justified. In his book Business Ethics, Norman Bowie claims that "whistle-blowing... violate (s) a. prima facie duty of loyalty to one's employer." According to Bowie, there is a duty of loyalty that prohibits one from reporting his employer or company. Bowie, of course, recognizes that this is only a prima facie duty, that is, one that can be overridden by a higher duty to the public good. Nevertheless, the axiom that whistle-blowing is disloyal is Bowie's starting point. Bowie is not alone. Sissela Bok sees "whistleblowing" as an instance of disloyalty: Bowie and Bok end up defending whistleblowing in certain contexts, so I don't necessarily disagree with their conclusions. However, I fail to see how one has an obligation of loyalty to one's company, so I disagree with their perception of the problem and their starting point. I want to argue that one does not have an obligation of loyalty to a company, even a prima facie one, because companies are not the kind of things that are properly objects of loyalty. To make them objects of loyalty gives them a moral status they do not deserve and in raising their status, one lowers the status of the individuals who work for the companies. Thus, the difference in perception is important because those who think employees have an obligation of loyalty to a company fail to take into account a relevant moral difference between persons and corporations. But why aren't companies the kind of things that can be objects of loyalty? To answer that we have to ask what are proper objects of loyalty. John Ladd states the problem this way, "Granted that loyalty is the wholehearted devotion to an object of some kind, what kind of thing is the object? Is it an abstract entity, such as an idea or a collective being? Or is it a person or group of persons?" 5 Philosophers fall into three camps on the question. On one side are the idealists who hold that loyalty is devotion to something more than persons, to some cause or abstract entity. On the other side are what Ladd calls "social atomists," and these include empiricists and utilitarians, who think that at most one can only be loyal to individuals and that loyalty can ultimately be explained away as some other obligation that holds between two people. FiThe whistle-blower hopes to stop the game; but nally, there is a moderate position that holds since he is neither referee nor coach, and since he that although idealists go too far in postulating blows the whistle on his own team, his act is seen some superpersonal entity as an object of loyalty, as a violation of loyalty. In holding his position, he has assumed certain obligations to his colleagues loyalty is still an important and real relation that and clients. He may even have subscribed to a loy- holds between people, one that cannot be disalty oath or a promise of confidentiality. .. . Loymissed by reducing it to some other relation. alty to colleagues and to clients comes to be pitted There does seem to be a view of loyalty that against loyalty to the public interest, to those who may be injured unless the revelation is made.4 is not extreme. According to Ladd, "'loyalty' is Ethical Treatment of Employees taken to refer to a r e l a t i o n s h i p b e t w e e n persons—for instance, between a lord a n d his vassal, between a p a r e n t a n d his children, or between friends. T h u s the object of loyalty is ordinarily taken to b e a p e r s o n or a g r o u p of persons." 6 But this raises a p r o b l e m that Ladd glosses over. T h e r e is a difference between a person or a g r o u p of persons, a n d aside from instances of loyalty t h a t r e l a t e two p e o p l e such as lord/vassal, p a r e n t / c h i l d , or f r i e n d / f r i e n d , there are instances of loyalty relating a person to a g r o u p , such as a p e r s o n to his family, a person to this team, a n d a person to his country. Families, c o u n t r i e s , a n d teams a r e p r e sumably groups of persons. They are certainly ordinarily construed as objects of loyalty. But to what am I loyal in such a group? In being loyal to the group am I being loyal to the whole group or to its members? It is easy to see the object of loyalty in the case of an individual person. It is simply the individual. But to whom am I loyal in a group? To whom am I loyal in a family? Am I loyal to each a n d every individual or to s o m e t h i n g larger, a n d if to s o m e t h i n g larger, what is it? We are tempted to think of a group as an entity of its own, an individual in its own right, having an identity of its own. To avoid the p r o b l e m of individuals existing for the sake of the group, the atomists insist that a g r o u p is n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n t h e individuals who comprise it, nothing other than a mental fiction by which we refer to a g r o u p of individuals. It is certainly n o t a reality or entity over a n d above the sum of its parts, a n d consequently is n o t a p r o p e r object of loyalty. U n d e r such a position, of course, n o loyalty would be owed to a company because a comp a n y is a m e r e m e n t a l fiction, since it is a g r o u p . O n e would have obligations to the individual m e m b e r s of the company, b u t o n e could never b e justified in overriding those obligations for the sake of the "group" taken collectively. A company has n o moral status except in terms of the individual m e m b e r s who 157 comprise it. It is n o t a p r o p e r object of loyalty. But the atomists go too far. Some groups, such as a family, d o have a reality of t h e i r own, whereas groups of p e o p l e walking down the street d o not. F r o m Ladd's p o i n t of view the social atomist is wrong because h e fails to recognize t h e kinds of groups that are h e l d together by "the ties that bind." T h e atomist tries to reduce these groups to simple sets of individuals b o u n d together by some externally imposed criteria. This seems wrong. T h e r e d o seem to be groups in which the relationships and interactions create a new force or entity. A g r o u p takes o n an identity a n d a reality of its own that is determined by its purpose, a n d this purpose defines the various relationships a n d roles set u p within the g r o u p . There is a division of labor into roles necessary for the fulfillment of the purposes of the group. The membership, then, is not of individuals who are the same but of individuals who have specific relationships to one another determined by the aim of the group. Thus we get specific relationships like parent/child, coach/player, a n d so on, that don't occur in other groups. It seems then that an atomist account of loyalty that restricts loyalty merely to individuals and does not include loyalty to groups might be inadequate. But once I have admitted that we can have loyalty to a group, d o I n o t o p e n myself u p to criticism from the p r o p o n e n t of loyalty to the company? Might n o t the p r o p o n e n t of loyalty to business say: "Very well. I agree with you. T h e atomists are shortsighted. Groups have some sort of reality a n d they can be p r o p e r objects of loyalty. But companies are groups. T h e r e fore companies are p r o p e r objects of loyalty." T h e point seems well taken, except for the fact that the kinds of relationships that loyalty requires are just the kind that o n e does not find in business. As Ladd says, "The ties that bind the persons together provide the basis of loyalty." But all sorts of ties bind people together. I am a m e m b e r of a group of fans if I go to a ball game. I am a m e m b e r of a group if I merely walk down 158 Ethical Treatment of Employees the street. What binds people together in a business is n o t sufficient to require loyalty. A business or corporation does two things in the free enterprise system: It produces a good or service a n d it makes a profit. T h e making of a profit, however, is the primary function of a business as a business, for if the production of the good or service is n o t profitable, the business would b e o u t of business. T h u s nonprofitable goods or services are a means to an end. People b o u n d t o g e t h e r in a business are b o u n d together n o t for mutual fulfillment a n d support, but to divide labor or make a profit. Thus, while we can jokingly refer to a family as a place where "they have to take you in n o matter what," we c a n n o t refer to a c o m p a n y in that way. If a worker does n o t p r o d u c e in a company or if cheaper laborers are available, the company— in order to fulfill its purpose—should get rid of the worker. A company feels n o obligation of loyalty. T h e saying 'You can't buy loyalty" is true. Loyalty depends on ties that d e m a n d self-sacrifice with n o expectation of reward. Business functions o n the basis of enlightened self-interest. I a m devoted to a company n o t because it is like a parent to me; it is not. Attempts of some c o m p a n i e s to create "one big h a p p y family" ought to be looked on with suspicion. I am n o t devoted to it at all, n o r should I be. I work for it because it pays m e . I am n o t in a family to get paid, I a m in a company to get paid. T h e cold h a r d truth is that the goal of profit is what gives b i r t h to a c o m p a n y a n d forms that particular g r o u p . Money is what ties t h e g r o u p together. But in such a commercialized venture, with such a goal, there is n o loyalty, or at least n o n e n e e d b e expected. A n employer will release an employee a n d an employee will walk away from an employer when it is profitable for either o n e to d o so. Not only is loyalty to a corporation n o t required, it more than likely is misguided. T h e r e is n o t h i n g as pathetic as t h e story of the loyal employee who, having given above a n d beyond the call of duty, is let go in the restructuring of the company. H e feels betrayed because h e mis- takenly viewed the company as an object of his loyalty. Getting rid of such foolish romanticism and coming to grips with this h a r d b u t accurate assessment should ultimately benefit everyone. To think we owe a company or corporation loyalty requires us to think of that company as a p e r s o n or as a g r o u p with a goal of h u m a n fulfillment. If we think of it in this way we can b e loyal. But this is t h e w r o n g way to think. A company is n o t a person. A company is an ins t r u m e n t , a n d a n i n s t r u m e n t with a specific p u r p o s e , t h e m a k i n g of profit. To treat a n instrument as an e n d in itself, like a person, may n o t be as b a d as treating an e n d as an instrum e n t , b u t it does give t h e i n s t r u m e n t a moral status it does n o t deserve; a n d by elevating the i n s t r u m e n t we lower t h e e n d . All things, instruments a n d ends, b e c o m e alike. R e m e m b e r that Roche refers to the "management team" a n d Bok sees the name "whisdeblowing" coming from the instance of a referee blowing a whistie in the presence of a foul. What is perceived as b a d a b o u t whistle-blowing in business from this perspective is that o n e blows the whistle o n one's own team, thereby violating team loyalty. If the company can get its employees to view it as a team they belong to, it is easier to d e m a n d loyalty. T h e n t h e rules governing teamwork a n d team loyalty will apply. O n e reason the appeal to a team a n d team loyalty works so well in business is that businesses are in competition with o n e another. Effective motivation turns business practices into a game a n d instills teamwork. But businesses differ from teams in very important respects, which makes the analogy between business a n d a team dangerous. Loyalty to a team is loyalty within the context of sport or a competition. Teamwork a n d team loyalty require that in the circumscribed activity of the game I cooperate with my fellow players, so that pulling all together, we may win. T h e object of (most) sports is victory. But winning in sports is a social convention, divorced from the usual goings o n of society. Such a winning is most times a harmless, morally neutral diversion. Ethical Treatment of Employees But the fact that this victory in sports, within the rules enforced by a referee (whistle-blower), is a socially developed convention taking place within a larger social context makes it quite different from competition in business, which, r a t h e r t h a n being defined by a context, permeates the whole of society in its influence. Competition leads n o t only to victory b u t to losers. O n e can lose at sport with precious few consequences. T h e consequences of losing at business are m u c h larger. Further, the losers in business can be those who are n o t in the game voluntarily (we are all forced to participate) b u t w h o are still affected by business decisions. People c a n n o t choose to participate in business. It permeates everyone's lives. T h e t e a m m o d e l , t h e n , fits very well with the m o d e l of the free m a r k e t system, because t h e r e c o m p e t i t i o n is said to b e the n a m e of the game. Rival companies compete a n d their object is to win. To call a foul o n one's own t e a m m a t e is to j e o p a r d i z e o n e ' s c h a n c e s of winning a n d is viewed as disloyalty. But isn't it time to stop viewing corporate machinations as games? These games are n o t controlled a n d are n o t e n d e d after a specific time. T h e activities of business affect the lives of everyone, n o t j u s t the g a m e players. T h e analogy of the corporation to a team a n d the 159 c o n s e q u e n t appeal to team loyalty, although understandable, is seriously misleading, at least in the m o r a l s p h e r e w h e r e competition is n o t the prevailing virtue. If my analysis is correct, the issue of the permissibility of whistle-blowing is n o t a real issue since there is n o obligation of loyalty to a company. Whistle-blowing is n o t only permissible b u t expected when a company is h a r m i n g society. T h e issue is n o t o n e of disloyalty to the company, b u t of w h e t h e r the whistle-blower has an obligation to society if blowing the whistle will b r i n g h i m retaliation. NOTES 1. Maxwell Glen and Cody Shearer, "Going After the Whistle-Blowers," Philadelphia Inquirer, (August 2, 1983), Op-Ed, p. 11A. 2. James M. Roche, "The Competitive System, to Work, to Preserve, and to Protect," Vital Speeches of the Day (May 1971), p. 445. 3. Norman Bowie, Business Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1982), 140-43. 4. Sissela Bok, "Whistleblowing and Professional Responsibilities," New York University Education Quarterly 2 (1980): 3. 5. John Ladd, "Loyalty," Encyclopedia of Philosophy 5: 97. 6. Ibid. LEGAL PERSPECTIVES Warthen v. Toms River Community Memorial Hospital Superior Court of New Jersey Plaintiff C o r r i n e W a r t h e n a p p e a l s from a s u m m a r y j u d g m e n t of t h e Law Division dismissing h e r action against d e f e n d a n t Toms 488 A.2d 299 (1985). Opinion by Judge Michels. River C o m m u n i t y Memorial Hospital (Hospital) . Plaintiff sought to recover damages for h e r allegedly wrongful discharge in violation