ON AGREE AND MERGE Susi Wurmbrand University of Connecticut
Transcription
ON AGREE AND MERGE Susi Wurmbrand University of Connecticut
Revised course notes from Problems in Syntax (Spring 2011) This is work in progress which is constantly evolving. Feel free to e-mail me if you have questions and/or comments. June 2011 ON AGREE AND MERGE Susi Wurmbrand University of Connecticut 1. INTRODUCTION Main goals • • Theory of syntactic licensing/dependency relations Working hypothesis: There is a single syntactic licensing relation, Reverse Agree, which allows the creation of a syntactic dependency between two (or more) elements. Empirical domain used as a starting point: feature composition of the verbal domain • • • • • Verb morphology English VP-ellipsis Parasitic morphology (Wurmbrand 2010) Germanic verb clusters (Wurmbrand 2011a) Infinitivus pro participio (IPP; Wurmbrand 2010) Extensions: Reverse Agree in other domains • • • • • Case assignment Polarity licensing, negative concord Obligatory control Anaphor binding Phasehood of infinitives Reverse Agree as a condition on Merge • • • • • The Merge Condition Clausal complementation in English and German A new approach to embedded root clauses Anaphor agreement effect QR from infinitives 1 2. THEORIES OF AGREE 2.1 Agree à la Chomsky (2000, 2001) (1) (2) P(robe) Agrees with G(oal) iff: [Domain ignored] a. b. c. d. P c-commands G Both P and G are active P matches a feature of G A feature is uninterpretable iff it is unvalued. a. X uF Y iF uX b. *X uF Y uF c. *X iF Y uF d. *X iF Y iF Questions/issues • • • Activation condition (Bošković 2007) “Reflex” checking (essentially a case of Reverse Agree) Biconditional valuation/interpretability (see Pesetsky and Torrego 2007, Bošković To appear for separating the notion of interpretability [iF/uF] from the notion of valuation and for Agree being valuation-driven). 2.2 Feature sharing (Pesetsky and Torrego 2007) [5] Agree (Feature sharing version) (i) An unvalued feature F (a probe) on a head H at syntactic location α (Fα) scans its ccommand domain for another instance of F (a goal) at location β (Fβ) with which to agree. Replace Fα with Fβ, so that the same feature is present in both locations. (ii) [p. 268] 2.3 Other Agree approaches (3) Zeijlstra (2010: 14) [130] Agree is a relation between a probe α and a goal β, such that (i) α and β are in a proper local domain; (ii) α has some uninterpretable feature [uF]; (iii) β has a matching interpretable feature [iF]; (iv) α is c-commanded by β; and (v) there is no matching goal carrying [iF] in between α and β. iF [goal] (4) » uF [probe Haegeman and Lohndal (2010: 196) [22] α Agrees with β if α c-commands β, α and β both have a feature F, and there is no γ with the feature F such that α c-commands γ and γ c-commands β. 2 (5) Merchant (2011: 407) [35] DEFINITION: AGREE(X,Y;F) [Footnotes omitted] For any syntactic objects X and Y, where X bears a feature F with value Val(F) and Y bears a matching unvalued:± […] inflectional feature F’, and X c-commands Y […], let Val(F’) = { Val(F), {Val(F’)} }. X F: val (6) Y F’: val/unval [language specific; English only unval; Aleut val possible] Baker (2008) (also Baker and Willie (2010) [104] (7) » The Direction of Agreement Parameter [p. 215] (i) F agrees with DP/NP only if DP/NP asymmetrically c-commands F, or (ii) F agrees with DP/NP only if F c-command DP/NP, or (iii) F agrees with DP/NP only if F c-command DP/NP or vice versa. Adger (2003: 168) [65] Agree An uninterpretable feature F on a syntactic object Y is checked when Y is in a ccommand relation with another syntactic object which bears a matching feature F. 2.4 Reverse Agree (8) Reverse Agree (to be argued for here) A feature F: __ on a head α is valued by a feature F: val on β, iff i. ii. iii. β c-commands α There is no γ with a valued interpretable feature F such that γ commands α and is ccommanded by β. α is accessible to β [roughly within the same phase—see below] Notation used: iF uF i/uF: __ i/uF: x i/uF: x interpretable feature uninterpretable feature unvalued feature valued feature (feature value x) unvalued feature that has been valued with value x 3 3. VERBAL MORPHOLOGY 3.1 The issue (9) a. “Standard” Agree b. Reverse Agree 3 T … iT: __ 3 V uT: val 3 T … iT: val 3 V uT: __ Which element is valued? Pesetsky and Torrego (2007): (10) “[…] reason for assuming that the T-feature of Tns is unvalued, though interpretable: the fact that Tns appears to learn its value in finite clauses from the finite verb.” [p. 277] Why T from the verb and not the verb from T? Is this a chicken/egg problem? Maybe not. Motivation for downward valuation: o VP-ellipsis o IPP-construction o Parasitic morphology 3.2 Basic workings of Reverse Agree • • • • • Functional clausal heads have an iT feature (typically valued) corresponding to its semantic value (e.g., past, modal, perfect) All verbal heads have an uT, typically (but not necessarily) unvalued. Agree: uT __ is valued by the closest i/uF: val. uTs: not interpretable in semantics; must disappear before reaching LF. PF: the uT value is what is realized at PF. uT English lexical items uT: past -ed uT: pres ∅ uT: mod/irr infinitive uT uT: perf uT: prog uT: pass (11) ModP 3 MOD AuxP iT: mod 3 AUX PassP iT: perf 3 uT: mod PASS VP iT: pass @ uT: perf V uT: pass English lexical items participle -ing participle He must have been left alone. iT: mod iT: perf uT: mod iT: pass uT: perf uT: pass 4 must have + INF be + PART V + PART 3.3 VP-Ellipsis 3.3.1 Some old facts • VP-ellipsis: strict identity between the antecedent and elided VPs not always required (Quirk et al. 1972, reported by Sag 1976, Warner 1986, among others; all data from Lasnik 1995). (12) a. b. c. d. John slept, and Mary will too. John sleeps (every afternoon), and Mary should too. John was sleeping, and now Mary will. John has slept, and Mary will too. (39) (41) (68) (45) Chomsky (1995): • Lasnik (1995): assuming identity between the two VPs is necessary, it is hard to see how a lexicalist approach can handle these facts. (13) a. *John [VP slept.3SG.PAST ] …. Mary will [VP slept.3SG.PAST ] Pesetsky and Torrego (2007) • It seems the same issue arise for P&T’s feature system (14) a. b. T iT: __ V uT: val [past] *John T [iT: __ ] [VP slept [uT: past] ] …. Mary will [VP slept [uT: past] ] Relaxing the identity requirement? • • VP-ellipsis sometimes does require strict identity between the antecedent and elided VPs (Quirk et al. 1972, Sag 1976, Warner 1986, Lasnik 1995, Lasnik 1997, Nunes and Zocca 2005, and others) VPs with be or auxiliary have must be strictly identical (in form and function) to the antecedent VP. (15) a. b. c. *John was/is here, and Mary will too. *John was being obnoxious, and Mary will too. John will be here, and Mary will too. (16) a. *John has left, but Mary shouldn’t have left. John has left, but Mary shouldn’t leave. ?John should have left, but Mary shouldn’t have left. *The men have left, but the women shouldn’t have left. b. c. (47), (49) (55) (50) (57) (56) (58) Phonological identity is not enough (16c)—features matter! (17) a. T iT: __ V uT: val Pesetsky and Torrego (2007) 5 b. John was sleeping, and now Mary will sleep. T [iT: __ ] T [iT: __ ] c. was [uT: past] will [uT: pres] » » Prog [iT: __] » Inf [iT: __] » sleeping [uT: prog] sleep [uT: inf] *John was being obnoxious, and Mary will too be obnoxious. T [iT: __ ] T [iT: __ ] • » » » » was [uT: past] will [uT: pres] » » Prog [iT: __] » Inf [iT: __] » being [uT: prog] be [uT: inf] Main question: when is identity necessary, when not (see Lasnik 1997 for arguments against various alternatives trying to save a fully lexicalist approach). 3.3.2 Lasnik (1995) — “Syntactic Structures Meets the Minimalist Program” (18) a. b. c. English main verbs (whether regular or suppletive) are inserted into the structure in their bare form and must combine with the corresponding inflectional affix via PF affix hopping (no movement). Be and auxiliaries are inserted into the structure fully inflected, including inflectional features which must be checked against a corresponding head via movement. Following Sag (1976): verb phrase deletion precedes affix hopping. (19) a. b. c. d. InflFEATURE InflAFFIX *InflFEATURE *InflAFFIX …. …. …. …. VFEATURE VBARE VBARE VFEATURE Overt V-movement PF-merger; no movement *Unchecked features *Unchecked features (at least at LF) (20) a. b. c. d. John AFPAST [sleep] and Mary will [sleep] John was AFPROG [sleep], and now Mary will [sleep]. *John was PROG [beingPROG obnoxious], and Mary will [*beingPROG obnoxious]. John was PROG [beingPROG obnoxious], and M. was PROG [beingPROG obnoxious]. 3.3.3 Nunes and Zocca (2005, 2009) • • • [9] Lasnik’s account predicts that VPI must involve total identity whenever there is V-mov’t. Movement (strong) Featural Infl V needs matching features/be fully inflected no step where the verb is bare (which is needed to get mismatches). Brazilian Portuguese: movement, but mismatches are allowed exactly as in English (with main verbs, but not with auxiliaries). a. [9’] a. [10] a. Eu já comi, mas a Maria ainda vai I already ate.1SG but the Maria still goes ‘I’ve already eaten, but Maria’s still going to eat.’ … comi1SG + Infl1SG [VP comi1SG ] …. vai [comer] [eat.INF] [VP comi1SG ] *O João era famoso e o filho dele também vai the João was famous and the son of-his also goes ‘João was famous and his son will [be famous] too.’ 6 Should be *! [ser famoso] [be.INF famous] Solution — a (hybrid) Chomsky 2000/2001 Agree approach • • • • T probes for the subject and acquires the subject’s phi-features. If T is weak (not specified what exactly that means technically in this approach), nothing further happens in syntax; Affix hopping at PF (as in Lasnik’s approach). If T is strong: V-movement takes place Crucial difference: main verbs are never inserted inflected/valued (movement is not triggered by feature checking but by some strong feature on T). [9’’] a. … com + Infl1SG [VP com ] …. vai [VP com] Elided VP identical to copy [If spelled out, bare forms need to be realized as infinitives in Portuguese.] • Auxiliaries: Similar to Lasnik, N&Z assume that auxiliaries/be are inserted fully inflected (hence not allowing any mismatches). In their approach, this means: T iF: val (21) a. b. » V uF: val (Auxiliaries)/unval (main verbs) *John was here and Mary will too. * was3SG.PAST [VP was uF: 3SG.PAST here] …. will [VP was uF: 3SG.PAST here] Is this really an Agree approach à la Chomsky 2000/2001? • • uF: val/unval need to get valued by an iF to get deleted. Which way does Agree go? In Portuguese, there is movement, so, we cannot tell in which direction valuation goes; valuation could be before (Reverse Agree) or after V-movement (standard Agree where uF of V probes for the iF of T). (22) a. b. • T iF: val (strong) T iF: val (strong) V uF: __ V uF: val Portuguese Portuguese English is more interesting. If English main Vs also involve an uF (as opposed to the earlier Lasnik-style approach where main Vs are entirely bare), Reverse Agree will be necessary, since there is no movement in English, and V would have to be unvalued (to allow mismatches in ellipsis). (23) a. b. • Main verbs: Auxiliaries: Main verbs: Auxiliaries: T iF: val (weak) T iF: val (weak) V uF: __ ???? V uF: val; (strong F) English English N&Z are a bit unclear about what the features of English main verbs are. [Citation from 2005 version.] [p. 34: “If T does not have a strong feature, Lasnik’s proposal can be adopted in full. That is, V and T will merge in the phonological component.” p. 36: “As for be and have in English […], we may adopt Lasnik’s proposal that they are inherently inflected, slightly adapting it under Chomsky’s (2001) valuation approach to feature checking. More specifically, we may assume that the relationship between being interpretable and being valued is not a biconditional (see also Pesetsky & Torrego 2004 for relevant discussion). In other words, whereas [+interpretable] features will always be valued, as in Chomsky’s (2001) system, [-interpretable] features will be unvalued in the general case, but may be valued in some marked cases (perhaps associ- 7 ated with idiosyncratic morphology). Importantly, these marked cases will also require feature checking against [+interpretable] features so that they can be deleted for LF purposes.”] If verbs involve the same feature specification in English and Portuguese, which seems to be the null hypothesis given their identical behavior in ellipsis and the assumption that whether verbs move or not is encoded on T, Reverse Agree would need to be adopted. 3.3.4 Merchant To appear—A (true) Reverse Agree approach to ellipsis • Chung (2006), Merchant (2008): voice mismatches are allowed in English VP-ellipsis, but not in sluicing, fragment answers, and other larger ellipses (data from Merchant To appear): [5] a. b. c. *Someone murdered Joe, but we don’t know who by [Joe was murdered]. *Joe was murdered, but we don’t know who [murdered Joe]. Q: Who is sending you to Iraq? A: *ByBush. [6] a. b. The janitor must remove the trash whenever it is apparent that it should be [removed] The system can be used by anyone who wants to [use it]. [8] a. This problem was to have been looked into, but obviously nobody did. Important feature of this analysis: verbs do not come inflected/with values, but receive them by Agree with the higher head. 3.3.5 Reverse Agree (SW) • • • = Nunes and Zocca (2005, 2009) plus Merchant To appear plus Reverse Agree V-movement of main verbs in Portuguese (French, Icelandic…) is independent of valuation (similar to Nunes & Zocca, I take it to be a verbal EPP-like property of T; T has an additional unvalued T/V-feature in V-movement languages, which will pull up the verb; the same will be the case for C in V2 languages; see section 7.1). Valuation can occur after ellipsis (below, I will argue that valuation can occur at any point in the derivation, as long as it is before Spell-Out). 8 • • Main verbs are unvalued; auxiliaries (and be) are inherently valued. Different from Nunes and Zocca (2005, 2009), but following Pesetsky and Torrego (2007), Bošković (To appear), I assume that unvalued iFs are possible. (24) a. b. Main verbs: Main verbs: Auxiliaries: Auxiliaries: • • • T iF: val (+uV) T iF: val T iF: __ T iF: val V uF: __ V uF: __ AUX uF: val AUX uF: val Portuguese English Portuguese, English uF: __ on main Vs in both languages will allow mismatches in ellipsis. Feature valuation under Reverse Agree — no movement necessary to value V’s features. Auxiliaries: uF: val on AUX prohibits mismatches under ellipsis. For now, I assume that both options in (24b) are possible (see sections 6.2 and 6.3 for the licensing of valued uFs). Other cases • • Motivation for such a system comes from Germanic auxiliary-participle constructions. Specifically, in Wurmbrand (2010), I suggest that languages differ, based on their morphological inventory, regarding which element (AUX/PART) comes valued: generally, AUX comes valued and values V.PART (downward), but in languages with prexical/circumfixal PARTs, PART is valued. 3.3.6 Conclusion • • VPE raises questions for accounts that assume that verbs are inserted fully inflected/valued. Major insights of the above accounts: o Typically, verbs are inserted without features/values/inflection. o Certain lexically specified elements are inserted with features/values/inflection. o Crucially: this difference is reflected in different syntactic behavior, as for instance, seen in ellipsis or verb-movement. 3.4 Germanic Infinitivus pro participio (IPP) construction • • See also den Dikken and Hoekstra 1997 for a similar point Modals in AUX – MOD – V constructions do not (or only marginally in German; see Bader and Schmid 2009) occur in the participle form; instead, an infinitive (IPP) has to be used. (25) a. dat Jan het boek heeft kunnen that Jan the book has can.IPP ‘that Jan has been able to read the book’ lezen read.INF Dutch b. dass Jan das Buch hat lesen that Jan the book has read.INF ‘that Jan has been able to read the book’ können can.IPP German c. dass Jan das Buch gelesen / *lesen hat that Jan the book read.PART / *read.INF has ‘that John has read the book’ 9 (26) AUX » a. iAux: __ iMod: __ uAux: irr iAux: __ iMod: __ uAux: perf b. c. » MOD V uMod: irr Upward valuation approach Wrong valuation for AUX; *iAux: irr uMod: irr valuation for AUX, but wrong morphology b. Plus a special realization rule that changes perf inf/∅ post-syntactically • Question regarding c.: Why would MOD start out with u: perf at all? This seems to show that the value is in some crucial sense determined by AUX (the probe), and not by the morphological make-up of the goal (MOD). It is certainly not the case then that the higher iF: __ learns its value from the morphological form of the lower verb. • A detailed downward valuation (Reverse Agree) approach to the IPP is developed in Wurmbrand (2010). 3.5 Parasitic morphology • • • Scandinavian copying constructions (Wiklund 2001, 2005, 2007) Frisian parasitic participles (den Dikken and Hoekstra 1997) German “Skandal” [scandal] construction (Vogel 2009) (27) a. b. Jeg hadde villet lest I had want.PART read.PART ‘I would have liked to read the book.’ Han prövade o he try.PAST o ‘He tried to fry a fish.’ stekte fry.PAST boka book.DEF en fisk a fish Norwegian have » want [Wiklund 2001, 2005, 2007] Swedish [Wiklund 2005, 2007] c. hy soe it dien he would it do. PART ‘he would have liked to do it’ wollen ha Frisian want.PART have.INF have » want [den Dikken and Hoekstra 1997] d. hy soe it dien ha he would it do.PART have.INF ‘he would like to have it done’ wollen want.PART Frisian: “Upward” parasitic want » have [den Dikken and Hoekstra 1997] e. ohne es verhindert haben zu können without it prevent.PART have.INF to can.IPP ‘without having been able to prevent it’ German: Skandal have » can [Vogel 2009] Common properties • Optional: parasitic participles always alternate with infinitives (all of the above are grammatical with the parasitic form replaced by an infinitive). • Parasitic: only possible if there is an appropriate licensing head (parasitic participles only if there is an [overt or covert] AUX; as the German IPP construction shows, not necessarily a higher participle). 10 • Semantically vacuous morphology: parasitic past/participle are not interpreted as a past/perfective; meaning is identical to the meaning of the infinitival construction. [For a caveat about covert AUX and arguments against an obligatory covert AUX see Wiklund.] Previous approaches • Den Dikken and Hoekstra (1997) (Frisian): Checking approach; AUX checks features on one or more PART; PART needs to be in Spec-head relation with AUX. This works well for Frisian (cf. the obligatory 3-2-1 order), but cannot be extended to Scandinavian. • Wiklund (2005, 2007) (Swedish/Norwegian): copying relation is “top-down, syntactic, local”; Inverse Agree approach; parasitic forms transmitted top-down; notes inconsistency with the standard probe – goal approach; no specific account. (28) AUX » uT: __ PART1 » iT: perf uF: ?? PART2 Chomsky (2000, 2001) iT: perf uF: ?? • Empirical problem: wrong semantics! • Theoretical issue: o Activation condition: AUX needs to involve some uF: __ o What are those uF: __ on the participles and why they are obligatory? o To guarantee that there is a dependency between AUX and both PARTs, both need to involve some deficiency; if PART2 lacks uF: __, it couldn’t be a goal, and no Agree could be established; this would incorrectly generate participles in cases where there is no higher auxiliary (e.g., *He want.PAST read.PART). o Only way to derive parasitic participles under Agree as in Chomsky (2000, 2001): obligatory uF: __ on both PARTs; Multiple Agree as in Hiraiwa (2001, 2005). o Such a system, however, then essentially suggests that it is the uF: __ of the PARTs that drive Agree, rather than some deficiency of the auxiliary (see Zeijlstra 2010 for a similar point regarding multiple nominative licensing). Pesetsky and Torrego (2007) system? (29) or or AUX iT: __ iT: __ » PART1 uT: perf uT: __ » PART2 uT: perf uT: perf Can one AUX Agree with two uT: val? PART1»PART2; AUX»PART1 other feature sharing combinations The second option will make PART1 dependent on PART2, which seems counterintuitive; also potentially a problem for German, where “PART1” is an infinitive. A mechanism is needed that: • • • allows multiple dependencies between one element (e.g., AUX) and different verbs. doesn’t necessitate movement (Scandinavian; also some of the Frisian constructions) doesn’t involve interpretable participle features on the parasitic forms. 11 The account in short • Main goal of Wurmbrand (2010): o Unified theory that derives parasitic participles in all of the above constructions. o Show how independent language-specific differences derive the differences among these constructions across Germanic. o Side issues covered: IPP and verb clustering (30) Jeg hadde villet lest / lese boka I had want.PART read.PART / read.INF book.DEF ‘I would have liked to read the book.’ 4 b. 4 iT: perf VMOD 3 uT: perf INF 3 iT: inf V … uT: inf INF *uT: perf (31) a. AUX Norwegian 4 4 iT: perf VMOD 3 uT: perf V … uT: perf PART AUX [An alternative to (30a) would be to treat modals as functional heads in the infinitival construction. In that case, the modal itself carries an iT: mod, which intervenes between the auxiliary and the main verb.] Parasitic Participles occur only in restructuring contexts (Wiklund 2005, 2007)— ‘smaller’ (e.g., vP, VP) infinitival complements; here: RIs lack heads with iT: inf). Frisian: Same syntax; head-final PF-linearization • • Since participles require valuation by AUX, the dependency of parasitic participles on a higher AUX follows. Since only AUX involves an iF: perf (iFs only occur on functional heads), parasitic participles are not interpreted (only realized) as participles. “Upward” parasitic participles (32) a. b. hy soe it dien ha wollen he would it do.PART have.INF want.PART ‘he would like to have it done’ soe 4 Base structure 4 MOD.PART 4 wollen AUX 4 ha V.PART dien 12 Frisian [den Dikken and Hoekstra 1997] • Two important facts about this apparent “upward” parasitism: o restricted to head-final languages (also in the Stellingwerf dialect; Bloemhoff 1979, Zwart 1995); impossible in the Scandinavian languages o only possible when the modal selecting want moves to C (no such restriction is in effect in the regular downward parasitic participle construction). (33) a. *omdat hy it dien ha kinnen soe because he it do.PART have.INF can.PART would ‘because he would be able to have done it’ *Mod final OK if Mod.INF b. omdat hy it dien wollen ha soe because he it do. PART want.PART have.INF would ‘because he would have liked to do it’ Downward parasitic [E. Hoekstra, p.c.] Account • • • Valuation can occur at any time during the derivation, before Spell-Out (cf. Abels 2003) Structure is built cyclically and merge operations must extend the structure, but feature valuation is not subject to the Extension Condition. Head-final orders: PF-linearization of sister nodes or syntactic movement (3-2-1 could involve syntactic movement, but 1-2-3 doesn’t) (34) a. 4 4 soe MOD 4 wollen AUX 4 ha V.PART dien MOD • • • • • • b. 4 4 iT: perf MOD 4 @ soe MOD tAuxP wollen uT: perf AUXP Movement of the auxiliary or auxiliary phrase above the cluster. Features of a head are also present on the projection of that head, AuxP can value an unvalued feature of a verb it c-commands (valuators can be XPs; Bošković 2007) Valuation could happen at stage (34a): want = infinitive Valuation could also be postponed until after movement of AuxP Frisian only allows fully descending orders: movement must target the top of the cluster. Agree AuxP»want can only be established if the highest verb (soe) gets out of the way—i.e., it moves to C. V2 restriction is result of locality of Agree. 13 4. OTHER REVERSE AGREE PHENOMENA 4.1 Case assignment Downward probing, but upward licensing (checking, valuation) (35) 4 T vP uϕ: __ 3 (EPP) DP … iϕ:val uK Agree à la Chomsky (2000, 2001) uF: __; iF: val; *all others Both probe and goal must be active Reflex checking of Case Movement: EPP • • • • Reflex checking: essentially shows that DP’s Case is licensed by T under Agree. Dispensing with Activation and Reflex checking (36) (37) 4 T vP iT: __ 3 (EPP) DP v’ uT:__ 3 v+V … uT: val Pesetsky and Torrego (2007): • • • • u/iF: __; u/iF: val Case is uT on NP Agree T»DP; T»v+V feature sharing Movement: EPP DP’s Case is licensed by T under Agree. 4 DP T’ iϕ:val 3 uCase T vP uϕ: __ 3 DP … iϕ:val uCase Bošković (2007): • • • u/iF: __; u/iF: val uF must act as a probe Movement: valuation driven Question: Case licensing in languages where subject movement does not (or not obligatorily occur; e.g., German; see Wurmbrand 2006) Downward valuation — Reverse Agree (38) 4 T vP iT: val 3 (uϕ: __) DP v’ uT: __ … iϕ: val • • • Case: uT on NP (but not crucial) Feature sharing can be dispensed with Movement: valuation driven (‘need’ of T) 14 4.2 Polarity licensing • Polarity mismatches under ellipsis (Sag 1976, Bresnan 1971, Ladusaw 1980, Hardt 1993, Fiengo and May 1994, Giannakidou 1998, Johnson 2001, Merchant To appear; the examples below and trees are from Merchant To appear) (39) a. • • John didn’t see anyone, but Mary did. b. John saw someone, but Mary didn’t. i. ... but Mary did see someone. ii. *... but Mary did see anyone. iii. ∃x.see (Mary, x) i. ii. iii. Merchant (15) (16) ≠... but Mary didn’t see someone. ... but Mary didn’t see anyone. ¬∃x.see (Mary, x) Lower elements (indefinites) are unvalued in some respect; valued under Reverse Agree. Different insertion rules for positive (some, a) or negative (any) indefinites. 4.3 Negative Concord Zeijlstra (2010), Haegeman and Lohndal (2010) (40) a. b. c. • K’(en)-een nooit niets I (en)-have never nothing ‘I have never seen anything.’ niet vele geen not many no ‘not many books’ niet not gezien. seen boeken books West Flemish (1) (18); *(niet) Cannot mean: *no books; *many books Ier en-leest er nooit niemand [DP niet vele geen boeken]. here en-reads there never no.one not many no books ‘No one ever reads many books around here.’ (19) DP-internal NC: geen is dependent on niet; niet must be uNeg, since it enters a NC relation with sentential NEG; if uNegs would need to move above iNeg (standard Agree approach) DP-internal n-words may be problematic. 15 • Although the authors above disagree on some technical details, they do agree that the licensing relation in NC contexts is as follows: o n-words involve a uNeg feature (since they do not contribute semantic negation) o an interpretable NEG head, overt or abstact iNeg, must license all uNegs under ccommand. o Reverse Agree 4.4 Anaphor binding Phases as binding domains • Binding domains can be reduced to phases: anaphors must be bound and pronouns free within vPs, CPs, and in some accounts (non-selected) PPs and DPs (Canac-Marquis 2005, Heinat 2006, Hicks 2006, 2009, Lee-Schoenfeld 2008, Quicoli 2008, Despić 2010). • Condition A: syntactic licensing condition requiring anaphors to enter an Agree relation with an element (antecedent or a head associated with antecedent) supplying the missing values (Reuland 2001, 2005, 2011, Fischer 2004, 2006, Heinat 2006, Chomsky 2008, Hicks 2009, among others). How does Agree work? • The deficient element is clearly the anaphor; anaphors are deficient, underspecified for certain feature values (Richards 1996, 1997, Reuland 2001, 2005, 2011, Heinat 2006, Hicks 2006, 2009, Johnsen 2008, To appear, among many others). • Disagreement: is anaphor licensed/valued by the antecedent directly (Hicks 2006, 2009, Schäfer 2008) or by a functional head Agreeing with the antecedent (Reuland 2001, 2005, Heinat 2006, Chomsky 2008, Kratzer 2009)? Mediated Agree? • • The motivation for anaphor binding being mediated by a functional head (SUBJECT » v; v » OBJECT) is most theory internal: Following standard Agree, the subject cannot bind the anaphor directly, since the subject is not active (it is not deficient). Empirical? Reuland (2005: 512, (10)): (41) a. b. Det it Thad There ble became introdusert introduced kom maðuri came a.man en manni a man for segi selv / *hami selv to SE SELF / *him SELF með börnin síni / *hansi with children SE / *him Norwegian Icelandic Claim: T c-commands the anaphor, but the nominative doesn’t: EXPL [ T [VP [ V DP.NOM ] [P REFL] ] ] BUT: • • Right branching VP structure (Pesetsky 1995) Multiple subject positions in Icelandic (Bobaljik 1995, 2002, Bobaljik and Jonas 1996, Bobaljik and Thráinsson 1998). 16 Against mediated Agree • • If object is valued through some feature sharing SUBJECT » v; v » OBJECT, it would be predicted that v should also share the features of the DPs. Anaphor agreement effect (Rizzi 1990, Woolford 1999, Tucker 2010) shows exactly the opposite — an anaphor must not agree with v, if object, with T if subject. Binding of possessors: v Agrees with DP containing the possessor (for Case) not with the possessor. (42) a. b. Honumi líkar bíllinn he.DAT like car.the.NOM ‘He likes his own car.’ sinni Hanni fílar bílinn he. NOM likes car.the.ACC ‘He likes his car (very much).’ sinni SE SE / / *hansi *his / / *hansi *his (í tætlur) (into shreds) Gísli Rúnar Harðarson, p.c. If valuation is directly by the antecedent, Reverse Agree is necessary. 4 NP 4 iϕ: val 4 Anaphor 4 iϕ: __ Anaphor iϕ: __ John talked to himself about himself 4.5 Obligatory control 4.5.1 Landau (2000 et. seq.) • Chomsky (2000/2001) style Agree: probe: uF; goal iF which is active. • Control: o probe: matrix functional head (T if subject control, v if object control), specifically the uϕ of that head o goal: PRO or infinitival Agr o Assumption: PRO and infinitival Agr are anaphoric (not clear what exactly this means), which makes them active for Agree. PRO comes valued. o Matrix F-head enters two Agree relations (controller and PRO/Agr): “This is made possible by delaying feature-erasure to the end of the superordinate phase” [p. 65] • PC: John decided to leave. o o o o • T+Agr Agrees with PRO in Spec,vP PRO moves to Spec,TP T+Agr moves to C Matrix F Agrees with T+Agr (in C) [will allow certain feature mismatches] EC: John tried to leave. o T+Agr Agrees with PRO in Spec,vP 17 o o o o PRO moves to Spec, TP No TC (since [-tense]) Matrix F Agrees directly with PRO [controller and PRO must match in all features] Crucially: F cannot Agree with Agr here (PIC). Some issues • Locality of Agree: F can Agree with PRO, but not T+Agr in EC cases; a revised version of the PIC is given that basically stipulates this. (43) Modified PIC [Landau 2000: p. 69] In a structure [ … X … [YP … Z … ], where YP is the only phase boundary between X and Z, Z is accessible to X: i) Only at the head or edge of YP, if Z is uninterpretable. ii) Anywhere in the YP phase, if Z is interpretable. • • Both AgrINF & matrix F Agree twice; this is possible by the assumption that checked features remain accessible (both as probes [F] and to activate a goal [Agr]) until the next phase up. Since it’s assumed that PRO comes valued, the assumption of it being anaphoric is necessary to make it an active goal for Agree. 4.5.2 Basic Reverse Agree account • • Reverse Agree eliminates the need for several unmotivated assumptions. Here’s the main idea of OC: o PRO (like anaphors) has iϕ: __, hence needs to get valued o DP iϕ: val (controller) can directly Agree with PRO and value its phi-features o Locality of Agree: see below • • • NOC: pro (valued ϕ-features); compatible with (in some cases necessarily) CPs. EC vs. PC? Either PC is not OC (Barrie, Hornstein etc.); or perhaps, PRO has a valued (semantic) plural features, and only inherits the other ϕ-features from the controller. Further evidence: QR (see section 10) 4.5.3 Infinitives lack CP — Slovenian 4.5.3.1 Marušič (2005) Slovenian feel like construction (44) a. b. Gabru se pleše Gaber.DAT SE dance.3SG.PRES ‘Gaber feels like dancing.’ [Marušič 2005: 66, (21)] Lini se še ne bo šlo ven Lina.DAT SE still neg aux.3SG.FUT come.NEUT.SG out ‘Lina still won’t feel like coming out.’ Not: Lina still doesn’t feel like coming out in the future.’ [Marušič 2005: 70, (28)] 18 p. 70: “[…] tense inflection on the lower verb in the FEEL-LIKE construction modifies the time of the FEELLIKE disposition, not the time of the overt verb’s event. Thus, future morphology in (28) actually signifies a future disposition, not a present disposition towards a future event.” [p. 72] • The transmission of T-morphology is exactly as expected under Reverse Agree and the definition of phases given here. Control infinitives Slovenian OC-infinitives do not involve a CP • Scrambling (based on Bošković 1997 for Serbo-Croatian): scrambling out of finite clauses yields WCO effects; scrambling out of infinitives doesn't (same for all types of infinitives). If CP A’-movement (WCO); if no CP A-movement. (45) a. Janezai je njegovj/*i oče reku, da se boji __ John.GEN AUX hisj/*i father said that SE fear ‘John, his father said he fears.’ [Marušič 2005: 109, (4)] b. Kogai je njegovj/*i oče reku, da se boji __ whom AUX hisj/*i father said that SE fear ‘Whom did his father say that he fears?’ [Marušič 2005: 109, (4)] c. Janezai je njegovi oče sklenil poslat v semenišče [Marušič 2005: 110, (6)] John.GEN AUX hisi father decided send to seminary ‘His father decided to send John to the theological seminary.’ • Inverse scope: scrambling out of finite clauses does not change scope relations (obligatory reconstruction); scrambling out of infinitives does. (46) a. b. Nekdo je rekel, da so vse punce vredne greha *∀»∃ somebody AUX said that AUX all girls worthy sin ‘Somebody said that all girls are worthy of sin.’ [Marušič 2005: 111, (12)] Vse punce, je rekel nekdo, da so vredne all girls AUX said somebody that AUX worthy 19 greha sin *∀»∃ (47) a. b. Vse punce se je nekdo odločil poklicati all girls SE AUX somebody decided call.INF ‘Someone decided to all call girls.’ po telefonu ∀»∃ on phone [Marušič 2005: 111, (13a)] Nekdo se je odločil poklicati po telefonu vse punce ∀»∃ somebody SE AUX decided call.INF on phone all girls ‘Somebody said that all girls are worthy of sin.’ [Marušič 2005: 111, (13b)] p. 111: “The interpretation of the non-scrambled sentence (13b) is not entirely clear. It seems that the universal quantifier can have a wide scope interpretation (at least with some degree of focus (and appropriate intonation))…” • • • Climbing of pronominal clitics: possible out of (certain) infinitives Partial wh-movement: possible in finite clauses, but not in infinitives (requires CP) Multiple wh-movement: no multiple long distance wh-movement out of finite clauses (Rudin 1988 only the first wh moves to Spec,CP, hence further); multiple wh-movement is possible out of infinitives. (48) a. Kaj je {*komu} rekel Vid {*komu} da je Peter dal *{komu}? what AUX whom said Vid whom that AUX Peter give whom ‘What did Vid say that Peter gave whom?’ [Marušič 2005: 115, (23)] b. Komu si kay pozabil dati? Whom AUX what forgot give ‘Whom did you forget to give what?’ [Marušič 2005: 116, (24)] c. Komu si koga sklenil predstaviti? Whom AUX who decide introduce ‘Who did you decide to introduce to whom?’ [Marušič 2005: 116, (24)] OC vs. NOC • • OC: entails lack of CP NOC: CP possible, but not necessary (many NOC/PC verbs also show transparency effects) convince • • PC; does not allow clitic climbing; no genitive of negation (fn. 104, p. 127) But lacks WCO, prohibits partial wh-movement, allows multiple wh-movement (49) [Marušič 2005: 127, (53)] a. *Zvone ji je Micko prepričal dati __ darilo Zvone her AUX Micka.ACC convinced give gift ‘Zvone convinced Micka to give her a gift.’ b. *Metko sem mu prepričal predstaviti Metka.ACC AUX him.DAT convinced introduce ‘I convinced Metka to introduce Slavc to him.’ 20 Slavca Slavc.ACC c. *Metko sem ga prepričal predstaviti Metka.ACC AUX him.ACC convinced introduce ‘I convinced Metka to introduce him to Peter.’ Petru Peter.DAT (50) [Marušič 2005: 127, (54)-(56)] a. Slavkai je Petro njegovi oče prepričal brcniti __ Slavko.ACC AUX Peter.ACC his father convinced kick ‘His father convinced her to kick Slavko in his fibula’ v piščal in fibular b. Kaj je Jože Zdenko prepričal komu what AUX Jože Zdenka convinced whom ‘Whom did Jože convince Zdenka to give Fiat 600.’ fičota? Fiat.600 c. Komu je kaj Marko prepričal Meto dati za rojstni dan what AUX what Marko convinced Meta.ACC give for birth day ‘Whom did Marko convince Meta to give what for birthday?’ date give 4.5.3.2 Reverse Agree Account here: Some similar conclusions • • • OC-PRO: vP and TP not phases; Spell-Out postponed and infinitive is fully accessible for Move & Agree (until the next phase is complete) CP always strong phase; blocks Move/Agree across it (forces intermediate A’-stopover). Marušič (2005): OC no CP; this follows nicely, since OC-PRO (but not NOC pro) needs to get valued by the controller, which would be impossible across a strong phase. Agree into infinitives — Genitive of negation • Neg in matrix licenses embedded genitive of negation in infinitives but not in finite clauses. (51) [Marušič 2005: 119, (35)-(36)] a. Meta ni vedela, da ji je Vili kupil bicikel / * bicikla Meta AUX.NEG knew that her AUX Vili bought bike.ACC / *bike.GEN ‘Meta didn’t know that Vili bought her a bike.’ b. Stane še ni sklenil kupiti Stane yet Aux.NEG decide buy ‘Stane hasn’t decided yet to buy a house.’ c. Petra Meti ni zapovedala kupiti avtomobila Stane Meta.DAT Aux.NEG order buy car.GEN ‘Petra didn’t order Meta to buy a car.’ hiše house.GEN “ Marušič (2005): “[…] the fact that the effect of negation is blocked in embedded clauses is most naturally correlated with the CP projection and the phase that it creates. CP being a phase blocks AGREE and without this long distance relation, genitive can not be licensed inside the embedded clause.” 21 • Left open: how Agree work (given that iNeg licenses a presumably uF: __ on the object); status other phases, e.g., vP. • Reverse Agree plus definition of phase-hood: this follows; iNeg » uNeg: __ [GEN]; further things to consider: o ni in/below v (Neg that originates higher should not license embedded genitive). o LD-genitive should only be possible with OC (unless there is movement of the embedded object, which would get it out of the embedded VP if a Spell-Out domain); Marušič (2005) notes that genitive of negation is impossible with convince, a NOC verb (but there could be a different reason for this restriction). o Intervening heads (infinitival T, v) must not block Agree (different features?). Agree into infinitives —Depictive secondary predicates • Controller and PRO must Agree with embedded predicate. (52) a. b. • Janez je prepričal obe punci ostati pri njemu pijani J.NOM Aux convinced both girls.ACC.DU stay at him drunk.ACC/NOM.DU ‘Janez convinced the two girls to stay at his place, when they were drunk.’ Janez je prepričal Meto ostati pri njemu *pijano / ??pijana J.NOM Aux convinced M.ACC stay at him *drunk.ACC / ??drunk.NOM ‘Janez convinced Meta to stay at his place, when she was drunk.’ Depictive structure à la Marušič et al. (2003) (53) VP 3 DP iϕ: 3SG uT: ACC V’ 3 V TP convince 3 PRO T’ uT: __ 3 iϕ: __ T vP iT: irr 3 PrP v’ # PRO uT: __ iϕ: __ • • • • • 2 drunk v uT: __ i/uϕ: __ VP iT: ∅/irr values NPs as NOM (like finite T; Landau 2004) drunk gets valued NOM by infinitival T; cannot get Case-valued by PRO [after PRO is valued by the controller] or anything in the matrix clause, since infinitival T is closer *ACC. PRO gets valued ACC (valuation after movement) or NOM (no movement or valuation before movement); since PRO is non-overt, the Case is not realized. Derivation where drunk gets valued NOM converges; cf. the speaker variation Marušič notes. If *NOM: Late PF-effect (?) — Depictive predicate only possible if the realized cases of all Agreeing elements match: case of DP and predicate must match. 22 • Under this structure of depictives, postponed Spell-Out would not be necessary to establish Agree between the matrix object and the depictive, since the latter is at the edge of the lower vP, This may then predict that depictives should be possible with both OC & NOC (cf. the example with convince). Non-simultaneous Spell-Out? • • • Marušič’s (2005): infinitives are not PF-phases (various intonation tests), but LF-phases CP is a PF & LF phase; infinitive (vP or TP) is an LF phase, but not a PF-phase. Main reason: quantifiers can be interpreted within an infinitive (infinitive is semantically a proposition, hence, according to Marušič, an LF-phase). • Reverse Agree and postponed Spell-Out provides an alternative account . PF-phase vs. LF-phase? Some thoughts… • • • Merging the matrix DP (controller) completes both the matrix and the embedded phases; but since at that point the matrix vP has already been built, the embedded VP (in fact, the whole infinitive) is spelled-out together (simultaneously) with the matrix VP. This may then yield the effect that the infinitive is not a separate PF-phase, but part of the matrix VP Spell-Out domain. What about LF? Suppose that QR applies, targeting infinitival vP (or TP if unaccusative). Due to PRO, SpellOut (both LF and PF) is postponed and the derivation continues. After the matrix vP is complete, matrix VP is sent to Spell-Out. For LF, this means that the structure needs to be interpreted. To do so, what’s required is that quantifiers are merged with appropriate sisters — constituents of type <t>. It seems that in this scenario, this would clearly be met, even if at some earlier stage of the derivation, vP/TP was not a phase and that portion of the derivation has not been sent to Spell-Out separately. Note also that QR within the infinitive is not obligatory; QR can also target the matrix predicate, which seems to indicate that the infinitive is not an inaccessible/inescapable Spell-Out domain. 5. SUMMARY REVERSE AGREE • • Agree is valuation driven (Pesetsky and Torrego 2007, Bošković 2009, To appear). No activation condition, reflex checking (Bošković 2007, Pesetsky and Torrego 2007). Reverse Agree • • • • Eliminates the need for feature sharing and allows direct Agree relations without (often stipulated) intermediaries. Since the deficiency is in the lower element, multiple dependencies can be established between one valuator and several ‘needy’ elements. Multiple Agree(ment) relations (e.g., NPIs, NC, SOT; see Zeijlstra 2010): typically are topdown dependencies; e.g. NPI licensing, if established syntactically, one licensor can licenses several dependent NPIs (He’s not having any problems with any of his clients anymore). One syntactic dependency that unites: Case, selection of verb morphology, anaphor binding, polarity licensing, negative concord, obligatory control… 23 6. THE MERGE CONDITION 6.1 Main issues addressed Deletion of uninterpretable valued features Conditions on Merge (and Move) Clausal complementation options in English and German (that-omission, V/T–to–C, features in wh-contexts…) The beginning of a syntactic account of selection. • • • • Theoretical context Reverse Agree Bošković (2007), Pesetsky and Torrego (2007): no activation condition, reflex checking, defectivity Pesetsky and Torrego (2007), Bošković (2009, To appear): i/uF: val; i/uF: __; Agree is valuation-driven • • • Deletion of uF • • • Uninterpretable features must delete (at least before reaching LF) How do uF: val delete? Freely or only if in a relation (e.g., Agree) with a corresponding iF? 6.2 The Thesis or Radical Interpretability (Pesetsky and Torrego 2007) [15] Thesis of Radical Interpretability (Brody 1997) Pesetsky and Torrego (2007) Each feature must receive a semantic interpretation in some syntactic location. 6.2.1 Verbal morphology and selection (54) *John has walks iT [ ] iT [3] has iT pres [ ] has iT pres [3] V uT pres [ ] V uT pres [ ] p. 272: “It is not sufficient to answer this question with reference to the selectional properties of higher verbs, since such an answer would beg the question of why the selectional properties are not otherwise.” In a Reverse Agree approach, this problem does not arise. 6.2.2 Subject CPs — feature sharing (P&T 2007 version) (55) a. b. • • That Mary likes chess annoyed Bill. That Mary likes musicals seemed to annoy Tom. Problem: CP, T(s), and V(s) all share a (single) T-feature. Different T value of CP and the rest: requires reference to Thesis of Radical Interpretability. This problem arises only due to the specific feature sharing view pursued there. 24 6.2.3 wh-features Pesetsky and Torrego (2007) • • Embedded interrogatives, relatives, free relatives share an overall syntax Restrictions on different wh-elements (56) a. b. c. (57) a. b. c. d. I wonder what/who Mary saw. the person who Mary saw… *the book what Mary saw… interrogative relative *relative I wonder when/why Mary left. the reason why Mary left… the exact time when Mary left… John left when/*why Mary left. interrogative relative relative free relative restricted p. 271: “If the matching of clause-type to wh-type is a variety of agreement, then C in these constructions must contain an unvalued feature that is valued when it probes and finds an appropriate wh-expression containing its goal.” (58) a. b. c. d. iQ: __ uQ: __ iQ: val uQ: val interrogative C declarative, non-interrogative C (successive cyclic movement) if wh-XP Movement: EPP-feature (59) • *Mary bought which book [uQ: wh] (*meaning: Mary bought this/a book) If uF: val could freely be deleted, this may be a problem (at least in some languages/constructions) Some issues (60) a. b. c. d. • • *I wonder (that) John bought what? I wonder what John bought. *Who does Mary wonder (that) John met __? What does Mary think that John bought __? Embedded C iQ: __EPP iQ: __EPP iQ: __EPP uQ: __EPP (60a,b): obligatory EPP of iQ. (60c,d): one single uQ: wh can value several uQ: __, but only one iQ. 25 wh-XP uQ: wh uQ: wh uQ: wh uQ: wh (61) Revised Thesis of Radical Interpretability? Each feature must receive a semantic interpretation in exactly one syntactic location. • • But this then again raises questions for the analysis of raising and CP-subject sentences (That Mary likes chess annoyed Bill.), where there are two T-values (though, per assumption a single feature) shared by the embedded T and the matrix T. Feature checking in intermediate positions (Bošković 2007) Bošković (2007) (62) a. b. c. d. • • • *I wonder (that) John bought what? I wonder what John bought. *Who does Mary wonder (that) John met __? What does Mary think that John bought __? Embedded C uF uF uF —— wh-XP (uF) uF uF uF Movement of uF wh-XPs is obligatory (uF must become a probe); (62a) excluded since no movement (uF), or no goal for C (if no uF on wh-XP) (62c): single uF can only probe once. (62d): successive cyclic movement, triggered by wh-XP’s need to become probe; no feature checking in phase edge positions. Selection (63) a. b. c. Who knows what John bought __? *Who thinks what (that) John bought __? Who wondered what John bought __? iQ: __/uF *iQ: __/*uF iQ: __/uF (64) a. b. c. Who knew that John bought what? Who thinks that John bought what? *Who wondered (that) John bought what? ?/ —— ?/—— *no iQ/*no uF wonder: think: know: obligatory interrogative complement obligatory declarative complement interrogative or declarative complement • • How do we know we need an interrogative C? This is only known when higher V is merged. Is there a connection (other than simply stating that a particular verb takes a particular type complement) between the features of C(P) and the selecting verb? If so, how can this be expressed in a feature driven model? 6.2.4 Gender features • • • Grammatical GENDER features challenge the Thesis of Radical Interpretability. Best candidate for a uF: val that never appears in any relation with an interpretable counterpart of that feature. Bošković (2009, To appear) assumes uF: val can freely delete. 26 (65) a. b. • Juče su uništena sva sela i sve yesterday are desroyed.PL.NEUT all villages.NEUT and all ‘All villages and all towns were destroyed yesterday’ Sva sela i sve varošice all villages.NEUT and all towns.fem su are varošice towns.fem (juče) uništene yesterday desroyed.PL.FEM Account of the distribution of first/last conjunct agreement builds crucially on the assumption that uF: val (gender) deletes without ever undergoing Agree (either after Match during the derivation or at Transfer). 6.2.5 Where I’ll be going • • • Somewhere in the middle… Give up the specific version of the Thesis of Radical Interpretability But maintain that uninterpretable features (unvalued as well as valued ones) need to be in particular configurations defined to allow them to be marked for deletion. 6.3 The Merge Condition (66) a. C’ 3 C iQ: __ • • • • • b. TP @ Q: val T’ 3 T uϕ: __ vP @ ϕ: val Movement occurs when the higher element has an unvalued F; to yield a convergent derivation, an appropriate valued F needs to Merge above F: __. Reverse Agree raises the question of how movement (of the licensor) is motivated (assuming no EPP). [Note that in this model, F: __ does not probe for a goal, instead the F:__ says that it has to be a goal.] The solution I propose is to locate the motivation for movement not in what triggers movement, but rather in what can/must Merge with a particular feature constellation at each point. This will lead to a highly local model: At each point in the derivation, Merge (internal and external) has to meet Last Resort. My version of Last Resort is inspired by Abels (2003): [92] Last Resort Abels (2003) A constituent may only be merged, i.e. base-merged or re-merged, if that leads to the immediate satisfaction of a previously unsatisfiable feature. Proposal: Each instance of Merge is subject to Last Resort as follows. (67) Merge Condition [Working hypothesis] Merge α and β if i. or ii. i. ii. α can value (a sub-feature of) the head of β. Every iF of α matches a corresponding [uF: val] on β. 27 [Valuation] [Complementation] (68) Deletion of uF: val A uF valued or matched under Merge is marked for deletion. (69) At the completion of a phase, features marked for deletion within that phase are deleted. [To be rephrased.] (70) • • i. X’ 4 X YP F: val 3 Y … uF: __ ii. XP 4 X YP uF: val iF uG: val iG Type i. covers internal Merge (e.g, subject movement to Spec,TP; wh-XP to interrogative Spec,CP), as well as external Merge of heads valuing their complements (e.g., verbal elements of the clause). Type ii. will be the main tool to implement selection (complementation) where no feature valuation takes place (cf. Pesetsky and Torrego’s 2006 Vehicle Requirement on Merge). More generally… • • • I borrow from P&T (2006) the idea that (in the typical case) Merge is restricted to certain feature combinations. In contrast to their approach, however, I do not consider this is an Agree relation (given the obligatory absence of valuation in these contexts). Merge is driven by uFs; uF must be eliminated before reaching LF; deletion is not free (not even for uF: val), but only possible if a feature is marked for deletion under Merge. A full reduction of Move to Merge may be possible if Move is eliminated altogether in favor of multiple external Merge of the same element (which then requires a mechanism for chain formation and copy identification). See below for a suggestion along these lines. 6.4 Deletion of uF: Gender — a new observation Disclaimer • The account below only covers gender features on nouns/NPs so far; an account of gender agreement is still under construction (as are other instances of morphological agreement). Gender on Nouns — basic idea • • • • • • • Let’s assume that there is a single set of ϕ features: [u/iϕ: PERSON, NUMBER, GENDER] Number on nouns is valued via Agree by D or some NUMBER head. Gender, unless semantic and hence interpretable, comes valued on the noun (uF: gender) D/Num Agrees with N and values NUMBER. After that, the entire uϕ of N is valued and marked for deletion. Crucial assumption is that uϕ: [NUM, GEN, …] counts as a single feature for deletion. That is, (67i.) allows deletion of uϕ: val, as long as some part of that ϕ-bundle is valued by a higher feature. 28 (71) NP/DP 3 D/Num iϕ: sg/pl NP # N uϕ: [ __NUM, FEM, …] • This predicts that there should be no language that has (uninterpretable) gender on nouns, but no instantiation of number in the NP. WALS summary Languages with no plural but gender: • • • • • • • • • Khmu’ (2) Maybrat (2) Tidore (3) Nicobarese (3) Paumarí (4) Pirahã (4) Oromo (2) [semantic] [semantic] [semantic] [semantic] [semantic] [semantic] [semantic or formal] The crucial property at stake here is that gender is uninterpretable (if it is interpretable, then there is no issue for deletion, since iF: GEN wouldn’t need to ever delete). That is, we only need to look at languages where gender cannot correspond to a particular semantic property. Systems of gender assignments (WALS): • • • Combining number with different types of gender assignments, reduces the 7 above to 1! No gender Semantic Semantic and formal 29 Oromo (Owens 1985) • • The above suggests that plural does exist in this language, but, for some reason, isn’t used. If it can be justified that the existence of plural as stated above is sufficient justification for assuming that Oromo does have number in syntax, the only counter-example disappears. Conclusion: • GENDER on N may not delete freely; the cross-linguistic correlation above could be taken to indicate that GENDER is dependent on N being valued by D/Num for NUMBER. • For the P&T system, GENDER remains a problem: in languages/constructions where gender is uninterpretable (i.e., determined by formal rather than semantic properties), the Thesis of Radical Interpretability would not allow uϕ: GENDER, since these features are never connected to a corresponding iF. 30 6.5 Basic Illustration of the Merge Condition • • A few things need to be said about how clausal categories meet the Merge Condition. I assume that verbs (V) can include the following three types of features: o uT: __ (verbal morphology) o uϕ: val, uQ: wh (complement) o uV: Agent/Become/Cause/?Goal (VP-shells) • At first sight this may look like an arbitrary complication. But what this does is to build argument structure and complementation into the syntax, and hence makes the syntactic computation more deterministic (rather than letting syntax do whatever it wants and then put the burden on semantics, filtering out certain structures, or on lexical subcategorization rules). (72) a. b. c. d. e. John left (the house). John wore *(a hat). John melted the ice. The ice melted. John kicked the ice. *The ice kicked. John arrived (*an airplane) (uϕ: val), uV: Agent uϕ: val, uV: Agent uϕ: val, (uV: Agent) uϕ: val, uV: Agent uϕ: val iV: Agent: • • • • • uV: Agent: requires that the main V(P) Merges with a verb (v) that is specified as iV: Agent (to mark uV: Agent for deletion under Merge). This has the (welcome) effect that whether a subject is required or not with a particular verb is now information locally available on each verb in the syntax. But, following standard assumptions, the Agent itself is not “selected” by the verb, but introduced by the usual v head (with Kratzer’s Agent semantics, hence iV: Agent). Thus, standard lexical subcategorization, which is not visible in syntax and often comes in somewhat magically can be dispensed with. A further advantage: ACC assignment; tying ACC to v with iV: Agent directly reflects the common effect that ACC is dependent on a Case competitor (the NOM, typically the Agent). How is the subject Merged? • • v: uϕ: __ (same for T in languages with the EPP phenomenon; but there is no actual EPP.) And yes, I will at some point work out morphological agreement, but not now. Mod, Aux etc. • • “Selecting” head has iT: val Every verbal head (also) has uT: __, which requires valuation by the higher head (which licenses Merge). How far do I want to go with this? • • I do not intend to get rid of s-selection altogether. Certain semantic properties/incompatibilities/anomalies will be left to the semantics: e.g., He speaks two languages/#two waffles vs. He ate two waffles/#two languages/#a table. In addition, it will be necessary to keep certain broad semantic requirements of predicates (such as s-selection of a proposition). 31 Some complementation examples (73) a. b. c. • John ate <something> John told us <something> John asked <something, a question> For ϕ-features on verbs, I assume that the value is some default value compatible with any ϕ feature: He likes me, you, her, him, them…. (74) a. VP 3 V XP: iϕ [s-selection: eatable thing] eat DP: uϕ: val CP: ? [maybe free relatives; but controversial whether there is also a DP on top of CP] b. c. • • uϕ: val an apple uϕ: val, (uQ: val) a story, that/when she left uϕ: val, uQ: val a question, where Mary is VP 3 V XP: iϕ, (iQ) told us DP: uϕ: val CP: [s-selection: proposition, answer] VP 3 V XP: iϕ, iQ [s-selection: question] ask DP: [Concealed questions] uϕ: val, uQ: wh CP: [see below for the internal structure of embedded Qs] CSR/subcategorization/c-selection will be reduced to feature deletion under Merge. Structures where syntax imposes no restrictions are subject to semantic compositionality. 7. CLAUSAL COMPLEMENTATION IN ENGLISH AND GERMAN Summary Type of clause Matrix declarative Selected? not selected Matrix interrogative not selected Embedded interrogative selected Embedded declarative not selected selected Top value iT iT, iQ iQ, (iϕ); *iT iT iϕ 32 English TP German CP (V2) V/T–to–C CP (wh ) V/T–to–C CP (wh) *V/T–to–C TP CP (V2); V/T–to–C CP (that) CP (that) Generalization: • • • • Syntactically not selected clauses must be marked iT on their top projection. I’ll argue that there are two ways of achieving this: bare TP or CP with V/T–to–C. Syntactically selected clauses are either iϕ, iQ, or both — never iT. I won’t be able to fully derive the iT restriction for non-selected clauses, but the following considerations play a role: o A verb comes with uT:__, which encodes the morphological value coming from a higher head—the one that ‘selects’ the verb). To combine with an iT complement, a verb would have to be uT: val (which would mean the upward dependency is lost). o There are semantic restrictions on the distribution of non-selected clauses (e.g., German embedded V2 clauses [which I’ll argue are non-selected and iT] are only possible in contexts of assertions); iT restriction could be tied to semantic requirements. • • For now: A clause that is marked iT (on top) indicates that it is not selected. For embedded declaratives, this will be an interesting consequence that I come back to later. Merge of C and TP and (a somewhat clumsy) V/T–to–C movement • • • • • • that (iϕ: val) can combine with TP since uϕ: val of TP, though marked for deletion, is still present when C merges. iT tense features: tense (PRES, PAST), finiteness As a default, tense features are bundled together (on T), but they can also be split over T and C, if there is a reason. One scenario where splitting is necessary is when C is required (e.g., when C has iQ), which will not allow Merge of C and TP. In this case, iT: fin is placed on C (and a ‘placeholder’ uT: __ on T). Since all iT features also come with a uT: __, C would include both iT: val (fin) and uT:__ when the tense features are split. This will have the desired effect, that C can combine with TP (Merge per Agree), and movement of T–to–C takes place to value the uT: __ of C. This is a bit clumsy, but the idea is that sometimes features need to spread over two heads, but eventually they need to get together again. (75) a. C’ [iϕ] 3 C TP iϕ: val @ T uϕ: val, iT: [FIN, PRES] C’ [iT] 4 C iT: fin uT: __ TP @ T uϕ: val, iT: [PRES], uT: __ 7.1 Matrix declaratives (76) a. b. John has seen Peter. Den Peter hat der Hans gesehen the.ACC Peter has the.NOM John seen ‘John has seen Peter.’ ‘It was Peter that John has seen.’ 33 • • b’. Der Hans hat den Peter gesehen the.NOM Hans has the.ACC Peter seen ‘John has seen Peter.’ ‘It was Peter that John has seen.’ c. *Der Hans den Peter gesehen hat the.NOM Hans the.ACC Peter seen has ‘John has seen Peter.’ ‘It was Peter that John has seen.’ Obligatory V2 in German; simple TP in English. Matrix declaratives are not selected iT. In English, this is achieved by a simple TP. V2: • German has an additional restriction that non-selected declaratives must have a filled Spec,CP. I encode this as a property on C (e.g., information structure), given as X below. • Since it’s not clear which element (C or XP) has the interpretable feature, I leave this open here (either option will work). • Merge of i/uXP is possible since it Agrees with X: __ on C. • To end up with iT on the top projection (and to allow C to Merge with TP), the tense features need to be split as outlined above, yielding V2. (77) CP [?iX, iT] 4 C C’ [?iX, iT] XP 3 X: top T+C TP X: __ @ iT: val + uT: __ tT (78) Assumptions about presence/absence of V2 a. b. German: Non-selected declaratives encode IS properties on C. English: Project only structure that is necessary. The common properties of English and German matrix declaratives are: • • Matrix declaratives are not selected. The topmost projection (TP in English, CP in German) is marked iT: val. 7.2 Matrix interrogatives • In both English and German, obligatory V/T–to–C takes place (but no do-support in English subject questions, which I leave aside; see Bobaljik 1994, 2002). (79) a. b. Who did he meet __? Who (*did) __ met him? (80) a. Wer hat who.NOM has ‘Who met him?’ [unless emphatic] ihn he.ACC getroffen? met 34 a’. Wen hat who.ACC has ‘Who did he met?’ b. *Wer who.NOM c. *Wer who.NOM (81) dass that er he.NOM getroffen? met ihn he.ACC getroffen met hat? has ihn he.ACC getroffen met hat? has CP [iQ, iT] 4 C C’ [iQ, iT] XP 3 uQ: wh T+C TP iQ: __ @ iT: val + uT: __ tT uQ: wh is Merged with C’ via Agree uQ: wh is marked for deletion by iQ of C’. The common properties of English and German matrix interrogatives are: • • Matrix interrogatives are not selected. The topmost projection (CP, assuming there must be an iQ in C) is marked iT: val. 7.3 Embedded declaratives (82) a. b. John said Mary saw Peter. John said that Mary saw Peter. (83) a. Sie glaubt [CP den Peter mag [TP niemand den Peter mag ]] V2 She thinks the.ACC Peter likes nobody.NOM the.ACC Peter likes ]] ‘She thinks nobody likes Peter’ b. Sie glaubt [CP dass [TP niemand den Peter mag ]] that She thinks that nobody.NOM the.ACC Peter likes ]] ‘She thinks that nobody likes Peter’ c. *Sie glaubt [CP den Peter dass [TP niemand den Peter mag ]] She thinks the.ACC Peter that nobody.NOM the.ACC Peter likes ]] ‘He thinks that nobody likes Peter’ c’. *Sie glaubt [CP niemand dass [TP niemand den Peter mag ]] She thinks nobody.NOM that nobody.NOM the.ACC Peter likes ]] ‘He thinks that nobody likes Peter’ d. • *Sie glaubt [CP mag [TP niemand den Peter mag ]] She thinks likes nobody. NOM the.ACC Peter likes ]] ‘He thinks that nobody likes Peter’ The distribution of that and embedded V2 casts doubt on the claim that that is a pronunciation of T in C (P&T). In German, both the finite V and dass are possible in C, however, the distribution is clearly distinct. 35 Main claim: • • English and German embedded declaratives are alike in that both allow two options: a thatCP or an XP corresponding to a matrix declarative (TP in English, CP in German). [See Hegarty 1991, Webelhuth 1992, Doherty 1993, 1997, 2000, Bošković 1997, Svenonius 1994, Franks 2005 among others for the claim that that-less clauses are TPs/IPs in English.] (84) a. VP 3 V believe uϕ: val • • CP iϕ: val that-clause V believe VP ??? XP: iT: val E: TP G: CP (V2) In both languages, the that-less version is again of type iT: val (rather than iϕ: val). This is supported by the impossibility of both that-less versions occurring as subjects (see section 8.4 for the full picture of restrictions on that-less clauses). (85) a. b. c. d. • b. [That Sue will buy the book] is obvious/was expected by everyone. *[Sue will buy the book] is obvious/was expected by everyone. [CP Dass den Peter niemand that the.ACC Peter nobody.NOM ‘That nobody likes Peter is mean’ mag] likes] *[CP Den Peter mag niemand ] the.ACC Peter likes nobody.NOM ] *‘Nobody likes Peter is mean’ ist is ist is that *no that gemein that mean gemein mean *no that In the system proposed here, a that-less embedded clause is syntactically not selected—it is in no syntactic (featural) dependency with any element in the matrix clause. Essentially, it cannot Merge with the verb. We will return to how these clauses combine with the matrix clause and show that this leads to a very interesting new account of that-less clauses. The common properties of English and German that-less embedded declaratives are: • • That-less embedded declaratives are not syntactically selected. The topmost projection (TP in English, CP in German) is marked iT: val. German V2 ≈ that-omission • • • The above summary suggests that a unified account seems desirable. It is hard to see how that can be achieved in the P&T system. Furthermore: German V2 does not involve a zero C/affix; a PF-account is hence unlikely to extend to German. Question to return to: • How do non-selected embedded clauses combine with the matrix clause? 36 7.4 Embedded interrogatives • In both English and German, V/T–to–C is excluded in embedded interrogatives. (86) a. b. c. (87) a. • Bill asked what Mary bought. *Bill asked what did Mary buy. *Bill asked what that Mary bought. Er fragt sich wen He asks himself who.ACC ‘He wonders who John met.’ der Hans getroffen the.NOM John met b. %Er fragt sich wen dass He asks himself who.ACC that ‘He wonders who John met.’ der Hans the.NOM John c. der Hans the.NOM John *Er fragt sich wen hat He asks himself who.ACC has ‘He wonders who John met.’ hat has getroffen hat met has getroffen met OK as direct question Claim: verbs embedding questions are specified for uQ: val and uϕ: val (below for evidence) (88) a. VP 4 V CP [iϕ, iQ] ask 3 uϕ: val, uQ: wh wh-XP C’ [iQ, iϕ] uQ: wh 3 C … iϕ: val, iQ: __ • • • Merge of wh-XP is possible due to Agree; C’ marks uQ: wh for deletion; uQ: wh survives until Transfer, but once the CP is completed (before the structure extends), all uF: val marked for deletion delete and are hence inaccessible from outside (even if at the edge). CP successfully Merges with a V with uϕ: val, uQ: wh (and marks those Fs for deletion). CP could not Merge with a V hat lacks uQ: wh (such as think). (89) Merge Condition [Repeated] Merge α and β if i. or ii. i. α can value (a sub-feature of) the head of β. ii. Every iF of α matches a corresponding [uF: val] on β. (90) a. b. c. • Who knows what John bought __? *Who thinks what (that) John bought __? Who wondered what John bought __? [Valuation] [Complementation] know: (uQ: wh) think: no uQ wonder: uQ: wh think: uQ: wh cannot Merge with C’ if there is no iQ on C; if there is an iQ, the CP cannot merge with think. * 37 • The situation is different for wonder, which requires an interrogative complement, hence only an iQ CP can Merge with wonder (note that Merge is overt; it hence follows that covert wh-movement, if possible at all, couldn’t get to C in time to value it). (91) a. b. c. • *I wonder (that) John bought what? *Who wondered (that) John bought what? I wonder what John bought __. Who wondered what John bought __? *Who does Mary wonder (that) John met __? C needs iQ; wh must value iQ “ Who cannot value two iQ, since it is marked for deletion in the embedded clause. When CP is complete, all uFs are deleted. Further movement and Re-Merge of who in the matrix clause is excluded. Why no uT in embedded C? • • • Recall that V/T–to–C is excluded in embedded interrogatives in both English and German. Spreading the tense features over T and C would derive V/T–to–C, and the result would be a CP with iT. This will then exclude Merging the CP with the matrix verb. Embedded questions are always selected hence they must not be iT. Evidence for iϕ: val? • • Optionality of dass in dialects Ability of embedded interrogatives to occur as subjects, topics etc. (92) a. b. [Which book Mary read yesterday] is not known. [Which person read the book] is not known. (93) a. [CP Dass den Peter niemand that the.ACC Peter nobody.NOM ‘That nobody likes Peter is mean’ b. c. *[CP Den Peter mag niemand ] the.ACC Peter likes nobody.NOM ] *‘Nobody likes Peter is mean’ [CP Wen niemand mag] who.ACC nobody.NOM likes] ‘Who no one likes is widely known’ ist is mag] likes] ist is ist is gemein mean gemein mean that *no that allgemein bekannt commonly known Why no that in English and Standard German? (Definite answer left open) Note: an optional uϕ: val on the selecting verb will allow that-less embedded questions. But the question is how that is prevented in contexts where we have reason for assuming that there is an iϕ on C(P) (embedded interrogatives that occur as subjects). 38 • • Option 1: PF deletion of that (Chomsky and Lasnik 1977, Pesetsky 1998) Option 2: Blocking effect among lexical insertion rules o iFs on C: [iQ: wh, iT: val, iϕ: val] o C iT: val [will, would, did…] iQ: wh [∅] iϕ: val [that] o C [iQ: wh, iT: val]: iT » iQ o C [iQ: wh, iϕ: val]: iQ » iϕ • What did John eat? I wonder what ∅ John ate. Option 3: C is not inserted valued (not that), but as iϕ: __, and receives a value from wh-XP via Agree (together with iQ: __). C valued by wh-XP does not correspond to a particular lexical item. While this ties the zero C to the presence of a wh-XP, it would raise a question for how C can Merge with TP in the first place. 7.5 Exclamatives • • • P&T: obligatory NOM–to–Spec,CP; no T–to–C due to the exclamative stipulation. Looking at English is somewhat misleading since the linear order does not provide clear evidence for where the nominative DP is. German shows that NOM–to–C is not necessary. (94) a. b. What a silly book Mary bought! P&T: NOM–to–C; no T–to–C Was für einen Schmarrn hier schon wieder jeder what for a nonsense here already again für modisch hält! everyone.nom for fashionable considers ‘What kind of … stuff everyone considers fashionable here again!’ d. %Was für einen Schmarrn dass da what for a nonsense schon wieder jeder für modern that here already again everyone.nom for modern haltet! considers ‘What kind of … stuff everyone considers fashionable here again!’ • Rather, exclamatives behave like embedded questions. (95) a. • EXCL 4 EXCL OP CP [iϕ, iQ] uϕ: val, uQ: wh 3 wh-XP C’ [iQ] uQ: wh 3 C … iϕ: val, iQ: __ While this works, this is a rather uninteresting suggestion; there is obviously more to understand here (see recent Syntax Square handout by P. Grosz). 39 Excursus: Is there ever NOM–to–Spec,CP? • According to P&T, NOM–to–Spec,CP takes place in the following constructions in English. (96) a. b. c. d. e. • • • • Mary thinks [Sue will buy the book]. G: not necessarily (V2); (83a) What a silly book Mary bought! G: no; (94) Who do you think [John will meet__]? G: no; (134) Who met him? G: yes (wh), but also V/T–to–C; *that; (80) Who do you think [ (*that) __ will read the book]? G: yes (wh), but also that or V/T–to–C; (135) German is obviously different. NOM–to–Spec,CP is only possible, when it can be seen as part of V2 or wh-movement. In all these cases, it must be accompanied by V/T–to–C or that (but the choice is not always free). One could now pursue a line in which German and English differ in that German does not allow a NOM to check/value the uT: __ of C. But an equally valid strategy is to pursue the option that in neither language, NOM can check/value the uT: __ of C, as is done here. This then leaves two case in English to account for: T–to–C asymmetry in matrix questions (e.g., Bobaljik 1994, 2002) and the that-trace effect (there are numerous options for that). 8. PUTTING IT ALL TOGETHER Since I haven’t made up my mind about successive cyclic wh-movement, I postpone discussion these construction (section 8.5.2). 8.1 Transfer How does Transfer work? (97) a. b. A completed phase is subject to Transfer. Transfer consists of the following operations: 1. Copy valuation: Mark uF: __ on X as valued if X is c-commanded by a copy of X. 2. Deletion of uFs marked for deletion; deletion of copies 3. Spell-out: complement of phase head. (uF (val) cancel the derivation.) • Let’s look how (97) is intended to work. (98) John said Mary left. a. b. c. d. e. f. Build ➀: [Mary left]TP said: uT: __; uV: Agent; no uϕ ➀ Cannot merge with anything at this point [see below for a clarification] Leave ➀ in workspace Build ➁: [John v [said]]vP Vv movement (for V uT: __ to escape Spell-out; V [uV: Agent] Merges with v [iV: Agent]; Merge satisfied) 40 g. • • • Transfer vP 1. Lower copy of V is marked valued: uT: val ! Merge ➀ and ➁; at this point (uT: val & iT: val) 2. Copy choice and deletion of lower copy of V 3. Spell-Out of VP (now including the embedded TP). The crucial part of this derivation is that Merge of ➀ and ➁ is part of Transfer. This is enforced since the lower copy of the V counts as uT: val only once Transfer has started. The effect of this, which I will show below is a very welcome outcome, is that TPs merged as part of Transfer, are frozen. No syntactic movement of these TPs is possible anymore (see below for (apparent) movement out of these TPs). Merge at Transfer also goes well with the claim made by Reis (1997) that embedded V2 clauses in German are “syntactically relatively non-integrated embedded clauses” [my translation]. If the TP is not merged (at all), nothing will go wrong in the syntactic derivation: V will be valued, since it’s a copy, and the uT: val of V will be deleted as party of copy deletion. But: the structure would not be interpretable correctly, since V s-selects a proposition, and at the point of interpretation, no complement would be present (*John said). The relevance of Merge • • • • Merge establishes a relation between the two ‘mergees’. I assume that (the history of) this relation is retained throughout the derivation (even after uF: val is deleted), and translated, in case of objects, into functional application configurations at LF (the way predicates combine with their arguments). If Merge occurs in syntax, syntactic movement of elements part of a Merge configuration is possible (e.g., wh-movement, topicalization, extraposition etc.); the history of the Merge relation is kept. If proper Merge (Merge satisfying the Merge Condition) occurs during transfer, the same semantic configuration can be established, but no syntactic movement is possible anymore (but certain PF-linearization options could change the word order, but never the syntactic structure; see below for one example involving relative clauses). There is one other option: Merge could occur during transfer and not meet the Merge Condition. This will entail that there is neither syntactic nor semantic selection, and that the structure, if interpretable, will not involve functional application. Modifiers are such a case. Modifiers • • • • • • Modifiers are not selected, neither syntactically nor semantically. I therefore assume that modifier attachment is not subject to syntactic restrictions, but only to semantic compositionality (yielding predicate modification). Working hypothesis: modifiers are merged at Transfer in the position they are interpreted. Islandhood of adjuncts follows. This also provides an account for the well-known late insertion option of modifiers (Lebeaux 1991, 1995, 2009, Fox and Nissenbaum 1999, Fox 2000). This is very reminiscent of Lasnik and Saito’s (1984) assumption that arguments and adjuncts are licensed at different levels—arguments at SS, adjuncts at LF (to account for the different behavior of subjects and adjuncts regarding the that-trace effect) 41 Syntactic selection Features of V uϕ: val, uQ: val No syntactic selection, but s-selection No selection — (iT complement) — Timing before Transfer: syntactic mov’t during Transfer: frozen during Transfer: frozen Semantics functional application during Transfer? predicate modification functional application 8.2 Relative clauses • Structure of relative clauses is controversial: operator structure and/or head-raising structure. From: Lechner, Winfried, 2008. Lecture notes (Linearization, Multiple Dominance and Cyclic Spellout). Full handout available at: http://users.uoa.gr/~wlechner//MD2008%2003.pdf Some head-raising diagnostics (Brame 1968, Schachter 1973, Vergnaud 1974, Bhatt 2002) (99) a. b. • John was satisfied by the amount of headway (that) Mary made. Mary liked the picture of himself (that) John sent. Empirically most adequate account: both options exist (Summary from Lechner) 42 That-less relative clauses • • • Doherty (1997): TP-structure (assuming A’-chain formation without movement) The account here provides another way to achieve the same result. That-less relatives are head-raising configurations, once a copy relation is established. (100) • • • • • NP/DP the book and the TP Sam wanted to read the book are created separately. At Transfer they combine. Copy identification (chain formation) of the two occurrences of the book; lower copy deleted (exactly as in the movement structure; presumably some lambda-abstraction at LF) The only successful Merge position (which will allow copy reduction and yield the right interpretation) will hence be with NP/DP. Movement constraints (islands, WCO) need to be seen as constraints on chain formation. (101) a. b. • • NP/DP 3 NP/DP TP the book % Sam wanted to read the book that-relative clause: that-less relative clause: matching or head raising head raising The matching structure of relative clauses involves an operator, hence obligatorily a CP. Since that drop is not obligatory, I assume that there are two possible structures for headraising relative clauses. Some evidence • Doherty (1997): that-less relatives cannot be stacked 43 (102) a. b. • • • the man [Mary met] [who John likes] *the man [(that) Mary met] [John likes] For copy identification, the NP/DP needs to be sister to TP; only the first relative clause can be in such position. The second relative clause involves an operator structure, which could be identified by the larger NP (the NP + that-less relative clause). Similarly: that-less relative clauses cannot be stacked after a head raising relative clause (cf. the idioms). [I haven’t worked through all possible derivations] (103) a. b. c. the headway [that John made] [that we talked about] *the headway [that John made] [we talked about] *the headway [John made] [we talked about] that-less relatives must be interpreted in situ (104) a. b. c. • • • • I showed himi [the book] yesterday [that Sami wanted to read]. *I showed himi [the book] yesterday [Sami wanted to read]. ?I showed Bill [the book] yesterday [Sam wanted to read]. The contrast between (104a) and (104b) clearly shows that that-less relatives are must be interpreted in situ. Note that some speakers allow ‘extraposition’ of that-less relatives (see section 8.4.3). (104c) is possible (though marked), which shows that the problem in (104b) is binding. Under the account here, relative clauses are Merged at Transfer in the position they are interpreted in, and no syntactic movement is possible afterwards (though PF-linearization options could change the word order). This places the that-clause in (104a) above the VP, hence in a position where Sam would not be c-commanded by him (I assume binding applies at LF). For a that-less relative the situation is different: it cannot be merged in a position other than sister to NP, since that-less relative clauses require copy identification, which is subject to ccommand. Thus the only derivation for (104c) would be: c’. I showed Bill [NP [NP the book] [TP Sam wanted to read the book ]] yesterday c’’. I showed Bill [NP [NP the book] [TP Sam wanted to read [the book] ]] yesterday c’’’. I showed Bill [NP [NP the book] — ] yesterday [TP Sam wanted to read [the book] ] PF • • Extraposition cannot be syntactic, but only a PF-linearization choice (which is restricted). Same derivation is possible for (104b), but: unavoidable Condition C violation. [The situation is somewhat more complex, as there also needs to be covert movement of the book in (104a). I set covert movement aside here.] Further evidence (105) a. b. c. *I showed himi [the book (that) Sami wanted to read] yesterday. I showed himi [the book ?(that) Samk wanted to read] yesterday. *I showed himi yesterday [the book (that) Sami wanted to read]. OK if no coreference 44 • • • (105a): CP/TP merged in surface position; *Condition C (105b): CP/TP merged in surface position; Condition C (105c): i) PF-extraposition *Condition C (if coreference) ii) Merge in surface position is excluded for NP objects (NP needs to mark uϕ:val of V for deletion) * iii) NP in object position » syntactic extraposition » Relative clause merged: syntactic extraposition impossible (*I showed him yesterday the book.); the only option is HNPS, which I assume is a PF-phenomenon. Comparison with Fox and Nissenbaum (1999) • • • F&N: High position of relative clause triggers high scope of the object. Relative clauses: early or late merger Choice of copy at PF & LF (106) a. b. (105) c. *I looked [for anything] very intensely [that would help me with my thesis]. I looked very intensely [for anything that would help me with my thesis]. *I showed himi yesterday [the book (that) Sami wanted to read]. (106a): o F&N: QR of NP; relative clause inserted after QR; PF low QP copy; LF high QP copy (must be together with relative clause) *NPI/free choice licensing. o SW: Relative clause merged in surface position; QR of NP Relative clause OP identified, but *NPI; no QR of NP *Relative clause OP not identified (106b): o F&N: early insertion of relative clause; QR of [NP+CP]; PF high copy; LF low copy. o SW: Relative clause merged with object in base position; PF-extraposition; no effect on NPI licensing (105c): o F&N should allow the following derivation: QR of (just) NP; followed by late insertion of the relative clause; PF and LF high. This should obviate Condition C. o SW: No late merger of NP+CP; no syntactic (overt) movement of NP. 8.3 Movement out of TP-clauses (a bit unorthodox) • The account given for relative clauses, in particular, the assumption of copy identification of two identical externally merged items, now gives us a way to deal with “extraction” from that-less clauses. (107) a. b. • Since the embedded clause lacks that, it would be a TP, which has to Merge during Transfer. (108) a. b. c. • What did John say Mary bought? Who did John say left? [vP what John [say]] + [TP Mary [vP what [bought]]] [vP what John [VP say [TP Mary [vP what [bought]]]]] [vP what John [VP say [TP Mary [vP what [bought]]]]] … 45 two parts built separately Merge Copy identification, deletion 8.4 That-omission in more detail 8.4.1 Summary of main accounts ?: Not discussed (account may be available) Construction Doherty John said Mary left IP that-omission licensing — B&L CP PF-affix P&T CP NOM-to-C John said that Mary left CP CP John gloated that he had been fired John gloated *(that) he had been fired *He liked linguistics was widely believed *John likes Mary Jane didn’t believe I hope *(that) this book you will read I heard about the fact *(that) Mary did it. It seems to me (that) John likes Mary. It seemed at that time # *(that) he had left. CP CP CP (T–to–C) CP Franks TP T (features) must incorporate TP (PF that-insertion) CP CP (adjunct) that IP must be complement of X0 IP must be complement of X0 *adjunction to argument CP (adjunct) that IP ? [could assume CP=adjunct; *PF] *PF-affixation ? CP that *CP w/o iT attracted by T ? *T-feature mov’t *NOM-to-C (TP is closer) N requires iT CP NOM–to–C or T–to–C ? *adjunction to argument ? NOM–to–C TP IP must be complement of X0 John convinced me (that) IP he wasn’t the traitor. *PF-affixation ? Null C must attach to [+V] Null C can attach to any category Prosodic phrase boundary blocks PFaffixation IP [CP when that is present?] or TP; PF-that no extraposition? CP that extraposition T–to–C 8.4.2 My account • • • • • • • That-less clauses cannot undergo any syntactic movement. This covers subject clauses, topicalization, (syntactic) extraposition. Cases of apparent extraposition, which could be analyzed as involving V-movement are also readily accounted for (e.g., It seems to me John likes Mary). The distribution of extraposition is very mixed (see 8.4.3 for a summary); a preliminary suggestion is that the variation is due to the option of PF-extraposition, which is subject to prosodic factors not taken into account. The data on RNR are rather controversial; I have not found any way to tease apart conflicting judgments. Non-bridge verbs: uϕ: val obligatory (this is an oversimplification; in German, there are also clear semantic effects involved in embedded V2, which need to still be incorporated into the analysis). That-less complements to nouns: I believe this restriction is not entirely correct. That-less complements to nouns are possible in German, and have been documented for English as well (see section 8.4.5). There are certainly cases that are impossible, but what is also clear is 46 • that a categorical exclusion of that-less complements of nouns is not adequate. What is still missing is an account that differentiates the possible from the impossible cases. Prohibition against that-less clauses with initial topics in English (in German embedded V2 can occur with topics): I hope *(that) this book you will read. (cf. This book, you will read.). I do not have a good answer, but one option would be to assume that topics project a head, even in English, which has the effect that the topmost projection is not iT anymore. An alternative may be that topics block the semantic association of the verb with the TP. 8.4.3 Extraposition — sometimes possible, sometimes not Doherty (1997: 210), citing Aoun et.a. (1987: 374-375) (109) a. b. I believe sincerely *(that) Kay will be elected. It was believed by everybody *(that) Kay was a fool. =(37) (110) a. b. c. I think in general people tend to like him. They said last year (that) the economy would be better by now. I believe myself (that) she is a good person. =(39) (111) a. b. It seems to me (that) she’s on the right track. I said to Mary (that) he was in error. =(40) (112) I thought just now *(that) I saw Karen Franks (2005) Bošković and Lasnik (2003) (113) a. It seemed at that time *(that) David had left. =(3/4a) (114) a. ??What did they believe at that time [that Peter fixed what]? b. *How did they believe at that time [that Peter fixed the car how]? c. At that time, what did they believe [that Peter fixed what]? d. At that time, howi did they believe [that Peter fixed the car how]? (115) a. b. ?Who do you believe sincerely [who likes Natasha]? *What do you believe sincerely [Natasha likes what]? =(7) =(15) =(16) Corpus Data (accepted by a speaker) (116) a. b. United management wrote a letter to the Board stating they believed at that time they should be considered a single carrier. ... Search: “did they believe at that time”: [“hard to parse, but unobjectionable”] Did they believe at that time we should sit at nights from 7 o'clock to 11? Did they believe at that time an electronic image of a redacted document posted on the campaign website of a candidate for the Democratic nomination for President at the behest of the Communications Director of the candidate’s campaign, which image is only accessible with the aid of a computer screen; is tantamount to evidence that the nominee wannabe is Constitutionally qualified for the job? 47 Two types of extraposition — syntactic and PF-linearization Current account: • • • that-less clauses are Merged at Transfer and have hence missed their chance to undergo syntactic movement. Extraposition may occur as part of PF-linearization, and if so, it will be subject to prosodic constraints (e.g., Truckenbrodt’s 1995 locality constraint, according to which a extraposition must place XP right outside the prosodic phrase it originates in — no further, no closer). Variation could then be located in different prosodic structures. For instance: (117) a. b. *It [seemed TP]π [at that time]π *[David had left]. PF: expraposition too far * Syntax: no TP to move * It [seemed TP at that time]π [David had left]. PF: expraposition OK • This should then correlate with whether a speaker gets extraction effects in the corresponding that-clauses: Speakers of type (117b) should have no extraction problems (since PFextraposition doesn’t create an island); whereas speakers of type (117a) should only allow syntactic extraposition of that-clauses, which creates islands. • I have found two cases supporting this so far: Bošković and Lasnik (2003) give the extraction data below and (117a); another speaker accepts (117b) and also the extraction cases below. (118) a. ??What did they believe at that time [that Peter fixed what]? b. *How did they believe at that time [that Peter fixed the car how]? c. At that time, what did they believe [that Peter fixed what]? d. At that time, howi did they believe [that Peter fixed the car how]? • =(7) What would obviously be necessary is to investigate whether the prosodic parses are different for different speakers. 8.4.4 Right Node Raising Data not clear — some OK, some * with RNR (119) Bošković and Lasnik (2003) They suspected and we believed *(that) Peter would visit the hospital. =(3b) (120) Doherty (1997: 210) a. b. c. I really think but Mary doubts the referendum will pass. The Unionists doubt but most Nationalists strongly believe the peace talks will begin before Christmas. The Serbs think and the Muslims openly claim he is dishonest. 48 8.4.5 That-omission in complements to nouns • • • Below is a summary of some of the data from the literature and a very preliminary corpus search. It seems clear that that-less complements of N are possible, and in some cases even frequent. There are restrictions on when that-omission is possible (which may be similar to the restrictions on embedded V2 in German), and a careful investigation of these restrictions is still outstanding. Impossible (121) Pesetsky and Torrego (2004, 2006) a. b. c. d. (122) a. b. We proved Mary could not have committed the crime. We demonstrated John was insane. your proof *(that) Mary could not have committed the crime the demonstration *(that) John was insane I heard about the fact that Mary did it. *I heard about the fact Mary did it. Bošković and Lasnik (2003) The fact he left caused a storm. The reason he stayed wasn’t apparent. Doherty (1997: 49) Possible (123) a. b. (124) Huddleston and Pullum (2002) p. 954: “In […] it is complement to a noun; omission [of that, SW] is not impossible in this construction, but it is unlikely with a morphologically complex noun like insinuation (compare The fact it was illegal didn’t seem to worry him” Proof isn’t proof (125) a. b. c. d. e. f. g. h. Then when you have seen enough proof he loves you, confess your love! then you have proof he loves you that's proof he loves you U.S. officials have received proof he is alive “proof he loves you”: 99,100 hits “proof she cheated”: 41.800 hits “proof she is a man”: 1,010,000 hits “received proof he is”: 12,000 hits (126) a. b. The lawyer had proof Mary was innocent. proof = confirmation The lawyer presented a proof *(that) Mary was innocent. proof = step by step process, set of logical arguments c. They received proof (that) Mary could not have committed the crime 49 JDB, Corina Suggestion (127) a. In a Boston courtroom, Judge Maria Lopez, reacting to a prosecutor's suggestion the sentence she handed down to an admitted sex offender was too light. [not a complete sentence: it's a parenthetical to introduce a quote] b. Ralph Brown, the institute's attorney, praises Salah and rejects the suggestion the center's money found its way “to any kind of improper activity, let alone terrorist activity.” Evidence (128) First up, the week began with [...] more evidence the president is losing the power of the center that got him elected. Belief (129) a. b. c. d. Drafting Tebow might be even less plausible (Jags don't have a second-round pick) despite pleas from fans and [owner Wayne Weaver's belief the Florida star could fill empty seats in Jacksonville]. McDaniels came to the Broncos when he had other choices, because...of his belief the Broncos organization strives to be the best. Additionally, there is a belief the committee keeps a running total of berths various conferences receive during the selection process, thus establishing quotas. Klimek told USA TODAY his original ruling was based on the belief the teen loaded the gun himself and pulled the trigger within close range of his head. Claim (130) a. b. Cheney rejected the claim the Bush administration is to blame for the faltering economy… CNN Despite the claim it has no territorial ambitions, the need to create buffer zones has prompted Israel… Military History 8.5 Technical issues, problems, open questions 8.5.1 Coordination (131) I believe … a. b. c. d. • • [∅=clause]TP [that clause]CP [that clause]CP [∅=clause]TP and and and and [∅=clause]TP [that clause]CP [∅=clause]TP [that clause]CP Could be coordination of embedded TP The last case is the interesting one in the current proposal The assumption that needs to be made: features marked for deletion are ‘invisible’ for ATBmovement (the two Vs count as identical). 50 (132) a. b. c. d. e. f. g. h. I believe he is right and that you are wrong I [VP believe ] & [VP believe [CP that …]] Merge [uT: __] & [uT: __; uϕ: val] Mark for deletion I believe [VP believe ] & [VP believe [CP that …]] ATB Vv [uT: __] [uT: __] & [uT: __; uϕ: val] [uT: __] [uT: val] & [uT: val; uϕ: val] copy valuation [uT: val] [TP he is right] & [uT: val; uϕ: val] Merge TP [uT: val] [TP he is right] & [uT: val; uϕ: val] Mark for deletion [uT: val] [TP he is right] & [uT: val; uϕ: val] Mark for deletion 8.5.2 Successive cyclic wh-movement • • • English and German are alike in that there are two options: that-CP or that-less version. In German, the that-less version corresponds to a matrix declarative: the verb is in V2 position, assuming the trace of the wh-XP is in Spec,CP position (see Thiersch 1978). In English, the famous that-trace effect arises (which I’m not attempting at explaining; see the numerous approaches already out there.) (133) a. b. What do you think [(that) Mary read __]? Who do you think [(*that) __ read the book]? optional that *that (134) a. Wen glaubst du [CP wen who.ACC think you who ‘Who do you think John will meet?’ wird will [TP der Hans treffen ]] the.NOM John meet ]] b. Wen glaubst du [CP wen who.ACC think you who ‘Who do you think John will meet?’ dass that [TP der Hans treffen wird the.NOM John meet will c. *Wen glaubst du [CP wen who.ACC think you who ‘Who do you think John will meet?’ (135) a. Wer glaubst du [CP wer who.NOM think you who ‘Who do you think will meet John?’ ]] ]] der Hans {wird} treffen {wird}]] the.NOM John {will} meet {will}]] wird will [TP den Hans the.ACC John treffen ]] meet ]] b. Wer glaubst du [CP wer dass who.NOM think you who that *‘Who do you think that will meet John?’ [TP den Hans the.ACC John treffen wird meet will c. *Wer glaubst who.NOM think du [CP wer you who den Hans the.ACC John ]] ]] {wird} treffen {wird}]] {will} meet {will}]] Options for that-CPs (not decided yet) • Intermediate C has uQ: __; this will allow/force the wh-XP to Re-merge in Spec,CP, to value C. Movement of uQ: val can and must continue, since it has not been marked for deletion (embedded C is not iQ). 51 • • • Problem: this will mean that there is feature checking in intermediate positions. Intermediate C has no uQ: __; wh-XP uQ: val has to reach a position where it is Merged with iQ; this provides motivation for movement. However, Merge in intermediate Spec,CP would not be allowed, unless we exempt successive cyclic movement from the Merge requirement, for instance by a Last Resort version as in Bošković (2007): “Last Resort should be formulated as follows: X undergoes movement iff without the movement, the structure will crash (with crash evaluated locally).” [p. 610] Problem: This diminishes the power of Merge. that-less TPs/CPs (see 8.3) • • iT claues cannot Merge with V before Transfer. Movement would have to be done via copy identification. wh in situ? (136) a. b. • Who knew that John bought what? Who thinks that John bought what? Options for wh-in situ: unselective binding; another option would be to maintain that all whXPs are uQ: wh, and allow covert (feature) movement (which is likely not to be subject to the Merge Condition, and could hence stop over in the relevant phase edge positions (in the absence of Q: __, if necessary.). This wouldn’t affect the ungrammaticality of in situ wh in embedded interrogative contexts, since there movement is necessary to value iQ. (137) a. *I wonder (that) John bought what? *Who wondered (that) John bought what? C needs iQ; wh must value iQ “ 8.5.3 Semantic effects of embedded V2 A further important point: “Bridge verb” restriction • • • • that omission is not generally possible, but is dependent on the higher verb, and on (very complex) semantic properties, illocutionary force and others (Wechsler 1991, Reis 1997, Truckenbrodt 2006). that omission appears to be freer than embedded V2, but is also not possible with every verb. The fact that the nature of the higher verb plays a role is not expressed in a system such as P&T’s where the difference between that or no that is determined solely within the embedded clause.. Although I haven’t built specific restrictions into the system proposed here yet, and only used the simple term ‘proposition’ for complements of bridge verbs, it is easy to see how this could be done. There are two places where restrictions on that-omission can be built in: o iϕ: val of matrix verb (if the feature is obligatory, as for instance with factive verbs in German, that will be obligatory) o s-selection, and perhaps the semantic process that combines the that-less clause with the higher verb. If, as is often stated, V2 clauses are only possible in contexts of assertions, this could be an effect of the particular way ‘unselected’ clauses combine with the higher verb, or the nature of iT clauses. 52 9. THE ANAPHOR AGREEMENT EFFECT 9.1 Main claims (138) The anaphor agreement effect [Rizzi 1990; Woolford 1999: 257 (2)] Anaphors do not occur in syntactic positions construed with agreement. (139) The anaphor agreement effect (modified) [Woolford 1999: 264 (22)] Anaphors do not occur in syntactic positions construed with agreement, unless the agreement is anaphoric. Disclaimer: I will be assuming the generalizations and claims made in the literature. I am in no position to evaluate their validity. 9.2 The anaphor agreement effect with object anaphors 9.2.1 Summary of main constructions (140) a. b. • • John likes himself. Baa-mé tánge he-ERG SELF ‘He is hitting himself.’ pi-ly-á-mo hit-PRES-3SG.SUBJ-AUGMENT [Woolford 1999: 268 (31)] [Lang 1973:49] English, Enga have no object agreement — anaphors are possible. Languages with object agreement: anaphors and agreement do not co-occur (different strategies in object anaphor constructions). Inuit: • • verb–SUBJ–OBJ Object reflexives: no object agreement; no object or oblique object (141) a. b. (142) a. Angutip arnaq taku-vuaa man.ERG woman.ABS see-IND.3SG.3SG ‘The man sees the woman.’ *Hansiup immi Hansi.ERG himself.ABS ‘Hans washed himself.’ Asap-puq. wash-IND.3SG ‘He washed himself. asap-puq wash-IND.3SG.3SG b. [Bok-Bennema 1991:51] Angut immi-nut taku-vuq man himself-DAT see-IND.3SG ‘The man sees himself.’ [Bok-Bennema 1991:50; Woolford 1999: 266 (25)] Swahili: • • [Woolford 1999: 265 (24)] [Bok-Bennema 1991:28] SUBJ–tense–OBJ–verb (pronouns optionally overt) Object reflexives: no object agreement, but reflexive marker 53 (143) a. b. Juma a-li-m-busu Juma 3SUBJ-PAST-3OBJ-kiss ‘Juma kissed her.’ (yeye) (her; contrastive) [Vitale 1981:117; Woolford 1999: 264 (20)] Ahmed a-na-ji-penda Ahmed 3SUBJ-PRES-REFL-love ‘Ahmed loves himself.’ (mwenyewe) (himself.EMPHATIC) [Vitale 1981:137; Woolford 1999: 264 (21)] Selayarese • • SUBJ–verb–OBJ Object reflexives: no object agreement, but agreement with possessor (object reflexives always trigger third person agreement) (144) a. b. La-jañjang-i kalen-na 3ERG-see-3ABS SELF-3 ‘He saw himself’ La-—alle-i doe—-iñjo i Baso— 3ERG-take-3ABS money-the DET Baso ‘Baso took the money.’ Ku-alle-i doe—-iñjo 1SG-take-3ABS money-the ‘I took the money.’ Ku-keo—-ko 1SG-call-2FAMILIAR ‘I called you.’ Ku-jañjangkaleng-ku 1SG.ERG-see-3ABS SELF-1SG ‘I saw myself’ Mu-jañjang-i kalem-mu 2FAMILIAR-see-3ABS SELF-2FAMILIAR ‘You saw yourself’ To-jañjang-i kalem-ba 1EXCLUSIVE-see-3ABS SELF-1EXCLUSIVE ‘We (exclusive) saw ourselves.’ c. d. e. f. g. [Finer 1994; Woolford 1999: 275 (48)] [Finer 1994; Woolford 1999: 275 (49)] [Finer 1994; Woolford 1999: 275 (51)] [Woolford 1999: 275 (51)] [Woolford 1999: 275 (50)] [Woolford 1999: 275 (50)] [Woolford 1999: 275 (50)] 9.2.2 An account • • Object agreement: realization of ϕ-features on v Languages without object agreement: o SUBJECT merges with [v’ v VP] o v valued by SUBJECT subject agreement (perhaps in some combination with T) o If there is object shift: OBJECT merges above SUBJECT o Object anaphors as above (valued by subject) 54 • Languages with object agreement: o OBJECT (re-)merges with [v’ v VP] o v valued by OBJECT object agreement (subject agreement via T) o SUBJECT merges above OBJECT Anaphor agreement effect (145) Merge Condition: Merge α and β if i. or ii. i. ii. • • α can value (a sub-feature of) the head of β. Every iF of α matches a corresponding [uF: val] on β. Only a DP with ϕ: val can Merge with v’ [iV:Agent, uϕ: __] Anaphors can never merge with v’! (142) b. Angut man immi-nut himself-DAT (143) b. Ahmed Ahmed a-na-ji-penda 3SUBJ-PRES-REFL-love • • [Agree] [Complementation] taku-vuq see-IND.3SG (mwenyewe) (himself.EMPHATIC) Inuit: subject Merges with v’; subject agreement is triggered (perhaps in conjunction with T; for oblique Case see below). Swahili: subject valuing v and object yields a reflexive marker on v? Some further technical details • How can the second DP (subject or shifted object) Merge with v’? o First DP values uϕ: __ of v; it marks it for deletion; but actual deletion is a process of transfer and does not happen until the vP is complete. Features marked for deletion are accessible until the phase is sent to transfer. o v/v’ after first DP is merged: [iV:Agent, uϕ: val] o Merge condition allows v’ to Merge with (multiple) iϕ (this, in a sense, derives edge movement). • How can an anaphor Merge as an object the verb (first Merge)? o V is uϕ: val, can Merge with any iϕ. o This provides support for the claim that anaphors are iϕ (but unvalued). Prediction • • • Anaphors should always be excluded from Merging with v, if v is uϕ: __ Largely true: nominative anaphors are impossible in many languages (see below). But: the current account does not yet entirely capture the lack of anaphor agreement effect in contexts where there is no agreement: infinitives, languages without subject agreement, oblique subjects. 55 9.3 The anaphor agreement effect with subject/nominative anaphors Lack of agreement (146) a. b. c. • • • • • *John said that himself left. John believes himself to be smart. zhangsani shuo ta-zijii hui Zhangsan say he-SELF will ‘Zhangsan said he [lit. himself] will come.’ lai come [Haddad 2007:370] Languages/constructions that lack subject agreement allow subject anaphors, provided they are properly bound/valued (i.e., there is a higher DP within the Agree domain to value the unvalued ϕ-features of the anaphors). Lack of agreement means that v cannot be unvalued (otherwise valuation, and hence agreement, would be triggered). Suggestion: non agreeing v (perhaps also T) is specified as uϕ: val English infinitives (whether PRO or ECM); v/T in languages without subject agreement. For now, this is somewhat forced by the Merge Condition (simply omitting ϕ-features will not allow subjects to Merge with v’ without further assumptions). But it does reflect the general idea of how arguments are selected (cf. V uϕ: val). Oblique vs. agreeing subjects … Icelandic [how could that happen?] (147) a. Húni sagði að séri þætti She.NOM said that SELF.DAT was.SUBJ ‘She said that she [lit. herself] was fond of me.’ b. *Jóni segir að sigi elski John.NOM says that SELF.NOM loves.SUBJ ‘John says that he [lit. himself] loves Mary.’ vænt fond um mig of me [Maling 1984: (8b)] Maria Maria [Rizzi 1990: 33] • Datives do not agree in Icelandic; dative subject anaphors are possible (when properly bound; subjunctive CPs allow binding, subjunctive CPs are not phases) • Question: how/why can DATIVE, but not NOMINATIVE. subject anaphors Merge with v/T? • Note: Agreement must play a crucial role, since underlying nominative objects are impossible in both German and Icelandic, despite the fact that they are not subjects in the latter. But in both languages, the NOMINATIVE agrees with the verb. (148) a. b. Jóni elskar sigi John.NOM loves SELF ‘John loves himself.’ / *hanni / *him Honumi líkar bílinn he.DAT like car ‘He likes his own car.’ sinni SELF.POSS 56 / *hansi / *his c. Joni veit að Maria elski Jon.NOM knows that Mary.NOM love.SUBJ ‘John knows that Mary loves him.’ d. *Siggai telur að mer líki Sigga.NOM thinks that me.DAT likes.SUBJ ‘Sigga thinks that I like her [lit. herself].’ sigi /hanni SELF.(ACC)/ him sigi SELF.(NOM) [Rizzi 1990: 33] Preliminary account — assumptions • • • DPDAT cannot value uϕ: __ of v/T (I do not know why, but it’s a fact). DPDAT: uV: DAT (I assume lexical Case is lexically valued) DAT—NOM constructions: involve an experiencer/applicative v [iV: EXP (DAT); uϕ: __]; verbs like like hence come with a uV: EXP (not Agent), and uϕ: val. (149) a. DAT subject object like.NOM Icelandic = German Icelandic German NOM object subject Merges with V VP Merges with v [iV: EXP (DAT); uϕ: __] • • NOM • At this point, there is a choice: either NOM (re-)Merges or DAT Merges (since it is lexically valued for Case [uV], it can Merge with a corresponding iV) • Icelandic, German are not object agreement languages, hence the subject must Merge first o German: NOM (re-)Merges first and values v (resulting in subject agreement); DAT Merges second; v’ is iV: EXP (DAT), which marks its uV: DAT (lexically valued Case) for deletion. o Icelandic: DAT Merges first (v’ marks uV: DAT for deletion); NOM (re-)Merges second (since it’s still within vP, it can value v, the head of its mergee); this also yields agreement with the NOM, but technically, it’s object agreement. [Since the DAT cannot, for whatever reason, value v’s ϕ-features, it should follow that it also does not block valuation by the higher NOM across it.] • In short: there is a v head requiring valuation/agreement in these constructions, and only the NOMINATIVE can do so. Crucially… • • • In either derivation, Merge of a NOM anaphor is impossible (since it satisfies neither part of the Merge Condition). Thus NOM anaphors are successfully excluded. This now also finally gives us an answer why DATIVE subject anaphors are possible: what licenses Merge of the DATIVE is not valuation of v (agreement; which requires valued ϕfeatures), but the need of the DATIVE to get rid of its uV: val. For that purpose, it doesn’t matter whether its ϕ-features are valued or not — all it needs is a corresponding iV: DAT. 57 9.4 Some of the open ends… Italian vs. Icelandic • • Icelandic: Default agreement is only possible when there is no DPNOM Italian: Default agreement is marginally possible (which then allows a DPNOM) (150) a. b. c. d. • • • A me interessano solo loro to me.DAT interest.3PL only they.NOM ‘I am interested only in them.’ *A loro interessano solo se stessi to them.DAT interest.3PL only SE SELF.NOM ‘They are interested only in themselves.’ A loro importa solo di se stessi to them.DAT matter.3SG only of SE SELF (GEN) ‘All that matters to them is themselves.’ ?A loro interessa solo se stessi to them.DAT interest.3SG only SE SELF.NOM ‘They are interested only in themselves.’ [Rizzi 1990: (14b)] [Rizzi 1990: (15b)] [Rizzi 1990: (15a)] [Tucker; fn. in Woolford] Italian has the same experiencer construction as Icelandic; when the NOMINATIVE agrees, it cannot be an anaphor. There are two ways to express that construction: GENITIVE anaphor (could this be a possessor construction?), and marginally, no agreement on the verb. The no agreement option appears to be dispreferred (and it is excluded in Icelandic), indicating that Merging a nominative must be enforced somehow. Is it just about agreement or is there also a nominative anaphor effect? (Everaert 1991) • The famous Icelandic construction (Zaenen et al. 1985, Marantz 1991 among many others) (151) a. b. • • *Jóni telur mér finnast REFLi John believes me.dat find SELF.NOM ‘John believes me to consider him strange.’ Jóni telur mér finnast hann (sjálfur)i John believes me.dat find he.NOM (SELF) ‘John believes me to consider him strange.’ skrýtinn strange skrýtinn strange Everaert (1991): SELF in hann sálfur is emphatic; true pronouns (not just “reflexives in disguise”); allow strict and sloppy interpretation under ellipsis, *topicalization, SELF follows pronoun (but would precede sig). There is no agreement in these cases; yet NOMINATIVE anaphors are excluded… 58 10. QR This has been revised from the original version. This section is based on the handout of the following talk: http://wurmbrand.uconn.edu/Papers/ZAS.pdf 10.1 Some puzzles of Q(uantifier) R(aising) • QR (English) is typically clause-bound: impossible across finite indicative CPs. (152) a. b. % c. d. • *∀»∃ *∀»∃ *∀»∃ Johnson (2000): (6a) (6b) Fox (2000): 62 “ QR is possible from infinitives and subjunctive CPs. (153) a. b. c. • It’s Mary that I told someone you would visit tMary. I told someone you would visit everyone. #Someone said that every man is married to Sue. #Someone said that Sue is married to every man. He demanded that we read not a single book. QP»demand Kayne (1981, 1998) A different student tried to stand near every visitor. ∀»∃ Johnson (2000): (22) A different student wanted to read every book. ∀»∃ (25) QR from infinitives cannot be reduced to restructuring (mono-clausal configurations; Hornstein 1994, 1995); QR is possible from all control and ECM infinitives, including nonrestructuring infinitives (Kennedy 1997). ∀»∃ ∀»∃ ∀»∃ (154) a. b. c. At least one American tourist expects to visit every European country this year. At least one American tourist hopes to visit every European country this year. Some government official is required to attend every state dinner. (155) a. b. At least one professor believes Mary to have read every book. ∀»∃ John believes the students to know everything Mary does [believe the students to know]. • QR from raising infinitives is impossible (Lebeaux 1995:65, Fox 1999:160, Fox 2000:144). (156) Mary seems to two women [to be expected [to dance with every senator. ]] *∀»2 (157) a. b. c. At least one soldieri seems (to Napoleon) [t to be likely to die in every battle]. ∀»∃ #At least one soldieri seems to himselfi [t to be likely to die in every battle]. *∀»∃ #At least one soldieri seems to hisi commanders [t to be likely to die in every battle]. “ (158) a. b. #This soldier seems to someone to be likely to die in every battle. John seems to a (#different) teacher to be likely to solve every one of these problems. #The ball seems to a boy to be under every shell. cf. Every shell seems to a (different) boy to be over the ball. c. *∀»∃ *∀»∃ *∀»∃ Questions arising regarding QR: Why is there no successive cyclic QR (vs. other A’-movement)? What is the difference between (non-restructuring) infinitives/subjunctives and finite clauses? How can raising infinitives allow A-movement but not QR? 59 10.2 The account in short 10.2.1 Two types of QR — Fox (2000) • Obligatory QR (type-driven); optional QR (scope-driven) (159) Scope Economy Scope-shifting operations (SSOs) cannot be semantically vacuous. [Fox 2000: 3] (160) Shortest Move [Fox 2000: 23] QR must move a QP to the closest position in which it is interpretable. In other words, a QP must always move to the closest clause-denoting element that dominates it. Why is there no successive cyclic QR (vs. other A’-movement)? (161) a. #Someone said that every man is married to Sue. a’. [vP someone said [CP *∀QP [CP that [IP ∀QP a’’. [CP *∀QP [vP someone said [CP that [IP ∀QP …]]] *Scope Economy …]]] *Shortest Move b. #Someone said that Sue is married to every man. b’. [vP someone said [CP that [IP *∀QP [IP Sue is [vP ∀QP [vP …]]]]]] *Scope Economy b’’. [CP *∀QP [vP someone said [CP that [IP Sue is [vP ∀QP [vP …]]]]]] *Shortest Move What is the difference between (non-restructuring) infinitives/subjunctives and finite clauses? (162) a. b. Someone expects Sue to marry every boy. He demanded that we read not a single book. ∀»∃ not a single book » demand Fox [2000: 65] “The first possibility is that the sentences in (91) contain null (modal) operators that provide motivation for the necessary intermediate instances of QR. The second possibility is that Shortest Move is a weaker condition than I have assumed.” (163) Option 1: a. b. c. [vP demand [CP SUBJ [IP ??? [vP QP [vP …. tQP ]]]]] QP vP: Shortest (obligatory) Subjunctive/modal operator: either QP IP or QP CP would violate Shortest (two modal operators would be needed) (164) Option 2: a. [CP QP [vP he demanded [CP-SUBJ that [IP we [vP QP [vP …]]]]]] (161)b’’. [CP *QP [vP someone said [CP that [IP Sue is [vP QP [vP …]]]]]] Shortest Move *Shortest Move What is special about either finite indicative clauses or infinitives and subjunctives and how does this difference translate into a locality restriction for QR (excluding QR in the former but not in the latter)? How can raising infinitives allow A-movement but not QR? 60 10.2.2 Main proposal • • • Two types of QR: Type-driven (target ⟨t⟩); scope-driven — subject to Scope Economy No Shortest Move restriction (but see section ·) Cyclic spell-out model • Completed cycles (phases) are subject to transfer Transfer (simplified): Spell-out of the complement of a phase head (former PIC) Accessibility: A spelled-out domain is inaccessible for further syntactic operations (Agree, Move). Consequence: QR (any form thereof) is phase-based (see Cecchetto 2003, 2004, Takahashi 2010 for similar approaches; see section · for some comparison). (165) YP 3 • QPOBJ YP 3 • Y XP *(Q) 3 X vP 3 QPOBJ vP 3 QPSUBJ v’ 3 v VP phase # V QPOBJ Type 1 QR: must target Spec,vP. Type 2 QR: possible only if movement is across another quantificational element, and if the moving QP is accessible (if XP is not a phase). Spelled-out after vP is completed Finite clauses (Fox 2000 translated into a cyclic spell-out model) (166) vP 3 • Derivation : *Scope Economy QP VP * 3 • Derivation (one step movement): V CP *Accessibility said 3 QP C’ * 3 C … that 3 Spelled-out after … vP phase CP is completed # QPOBJ vP # QPSUBJ v’ # … 61 QR vs. other A’-movement — “Need vs. luxury” • • A’-movement: The moving element, e.g., wh-XP (uQ: wh), and/or the moved to head (Cwh) has a need, which must be satisfied (which overrides Economy/Last Resort). Merge of wh-phrase in Spec,CP is allowed. (167) • • CP 3 XP C’ uQ: wh 3 C … i/uQ: ___ @ Type-driven QR can also be seen as ‘need’-based, hence not subject to Scope Economy. Scope-driven QP-movement: subject to Scope Economy (I leave open how QR interacts with the Merge Condition). Raising (168) vP Mary seems to two women … to dance with every senator 3 *∀»∃ ∀QPOBJ VP * 3 ∃QPEXP V’ to two women 3 • Derivation : *Scope Economy V XP • Derivation : *Accessibility seem 3 ∀QPOBJ X’ * 3 X vP 3 ∀QPOBJ vP phase 3 DPSUBJ v’ # … But: Movement of DPSUBJ to/through Spec,XP is possible, since the subject has a need (Case), which allows movement in accordance with Last Resort. Questions to be addressed: • • What is XP? What determines phasehood? 62 Control, ECM, Subjunctives (169) vP At least one professor believes Mary to have read every book. 3 At least one professor claims to have read every book. ∀QPOBJ vP He demanded that we read not a single book. 3 ∀»∃; not a single » demand ∃QP/we VP 3 V XP Not a phase believe/claim/demand 3 X … 3 vP 3 ∀QPOBJ vP 3 DP/PRO v’ # … 10.3 Tense and aspect in infinitives 10.3.1 Eventive predicates—two types of infinitives (170) a. b. c. • • • Leo sings in the shower (*right now). Leo sang in the shower right then. Leo will sing in the shower right then. Non-stative, non-generic, episodic predicates Used to diagnose tense in infinitives (Pesetsky 1992, Bošković 1996, 1997, Martin 1996, 2001). Against the above: eventive predicates do not distinguish between raising/ECM and control (but they do tell us something about tense). Two (of three) Classes of infinitives • • Future infinitives: always allow eventive predicates Simultaneous infinitives combining with propositional verbs (claim, believe, expect): never allow eventive predicates (see also Abusch 2004). (171) Future infinitives: Eventive a. b. Leo decided/plans to bring the toys tomorrow. The printer is expected to work again tomorrow. The bridge is expected to collapse tomorrow. The train is expected to arrive late tomorrow. Control ECM Passive with an inanimate (surface) subject is evidence for ECM (cannot be control). 63 (172) a. b. c. d. e. A solar eclipse is forecast to occur in Württemberg in August 2019. The petition is projected to have over 20,000 signatures by next week. The party is thought to start at 10 p.m. The storm is anticipated to hit the East Coast tomorrow. The storm is predicted to hit the East Coast tomorrow. Future ECM (173) Propositional simultaneous infinitives: *Eventive a. b. c. d. Yesterday, John claimed to be leaving (right then). *Yesterday, John claimed to leave tomorrow. *Yesterday, John claimed leave right then. Yesterday, John claimed to be leaving tomorrow. cf. I am leaving tomorrow. Control *Future *Eventive Planned future e. f. g. h. Yesterday, John believed Mary to be leaving (right then). *Yesterday, John believed Mary to leave tomorrow. *Yesterday, John believed Mary to leave right then. Yesterday, John believed Mary to be leaving tomorrow. ECM *Future *Eventive Planned future Future infinitives pattern with finite future regarding eventive predicates Simultaneous infinitives pattern with finite present regarding eventive predicates Analysis (see Wurmbrand 2011b for details) • Finite future is indexical/absolute; infinitival future is relative (Dowty 1982, Abusch 1988 et seq., Ogihara 1996). (174) a. b. • Leo decided a week ago to go to the party yesterday. According to a report I read last week, the bridge was expected to collapse yesterday. Leo decided a week ago that he will go to the party (*yesterday). According to a report I read last week, it was expected that the bridge will collapse (*yesterday). Simultaneous tense ≠ PRES tense (175) a. b. c. d. (176) a. #5 years ago, Julia claimed that she is pregnant. #5 years ago, it was believed that Julia is pregnant. 5 years ago, Julia claimed to be pregnant. 5 years ago, Julia was believed to be pregnant. Finite future b. Future infinitives TP VP 2 2 T ModP V ModP PRES 2 decide, expect 2 Mod vP woll vP will woll @ @ 64 double access “ double access not necessary “ c. Simultaneous infinitives VP 2 V TP claim, believe 2 T vP ∅ @ • • • Future (Abusch 1985, 1988): TENSE (absent in infinitives), plus the abstract modal woll which contributes a modal force yielding posteriority (see e.g., Thomason 1970, Condoravdi 2001, Copley 2002, Kaufmann 2005 among others). woll part of future is crucial for eventive predicates (cf. (170a); see the QR Appendix for a more detailed analysis of eventive predicates). zero tense (as in sequence-of-tense [SOT] contexts) is incompatible with eventive predicates. (177) a. a’. b. b’. John said that Mary was reading Middlemarch. [PAST say [PAST/∅ was reading …]] [Portner 2003] true PAST or simultaneous (SOT) John said that Mary read Middlemarch. [PAST say [PAST/*∅ read …]] true PAST; *simulataneous *SOT Distinction between woll and ∅-tense infinitives: selectional property of the matrix verb. 10.3.2 A third type of infinitive • Simultaneous infinitives combining with implicative, aspectual verbs, try, seem. (178) a. b. (179) • TP 3 T … ╲ VP 3 V AspP 3 Asp vP # PRO/DP to VP V = {manage, try, begin, seem…} Eventive predicates depend on the tense of the matrix predicate. (180) a. b. (181) a. b. • Yesterday, John tried/began/managed to sing in the shower (*tomorrow/*next week). The tower began/seemed to fall over (*tomorrow/*next week). Leo seems to sing in the shower (*right now). cf. Leo seems to be singing right now. Leo seemed to sing in the shower (right then). The tower seems to fall over (*right now). cf. The tower seems to be falling over right now. The tower seemed to fall over (right then). Wurmbrand (2011b): distribution of eventive predicates is an effect of aspect; in short (see Appendix), PRES and ∅ tense are only compatible with IMPERFECTIVE, which corresponds to -ing in English (PERFECTIVE is not realized in English). (182) a. b. PRES PAST » » seem seem » » IMPERFECTIVE/*PERFECTIVE IMPERFECTIVE/PERFECTIVE 65 » » sing (180a), (181a) sing(180b), (181b) • • Seem etc. infinitives are truly tenseless (extended vPs; no IP-projections) Simultaneous propositional infinitives show no dependency of embedded aspect on the matrix tense (cf. the examples above did not allow eventive predicates in matrix PAST context). Infinitive Irrealis future Propositional Non-/Semiintensional Examples Syntax decide, plan expect, forecast claim believe, expect manage, try begin, seem Control ECM Control ECM Control Raising Eventive predicates Temporal composition of infinitive Structure possible woll wollP impossible zero tense TP dependent on maaspect trix tense AspP One further argument for infinitival aspect (based on Keshet 2008) • Later-than-infinitive interpretation in implicative constructions (originally discussed in Kusumoto 2005) Time of making the final four/losing follows the time of picking in the context given. Relative clause modifies NPI object which forces the object+relative clause to stay in a position lower than fail/embedded negation. (183) Context as in Keshet (2008:306): NCAA basketball “March Madness” tournament and the betting pools concerning this tournament. The way such betting proceeds is that you must choose a winner for every game in every round before the tournament begins. So, if there are four teams – call them A, B, C, and D –, you might choose A to beat B and C to beat D in round one, and choose A to beat C in round two. The second-to-last round of the tournament is called the “Final Four,” since there are four teams left. Now, let us say that I placed such a bet before the tournament began. After the tournament, I can say: a. b. I failed to pick any team that made the final four. I managed not to pick any team that lost in the first round. Keshet’s analysis: (184) VP 4 manage 4 not 5 DPi 5 %PERFECTIVE # any team that PRO pick ti PERFECTIVE lost in the first round • The same interpretation is possible with seem. (185) Embedded clause: PERFECTIVE below NEG; time of picking is a subinterval of matrix time (time of managing). Relative clause: SOT (non PAST); PERFECTIVE the time of losing is a subinterval of a higher time. NPI: must stay below negation, but can move above infinitival aspect Relative clause outside the scope of infinitival PERFECTIVE: time of losing is not ordered w.r.t time of picking. John seemed not to pick any team that lost in the first round. 66 10.3.3 The syntax of raising infinitives • • • Syntactic properties used to argue for TP in raising infinitives: binding, floating quantifiers Binding (examples attributed to Danny Fox, cited in Grohmann et al. 2000, Bošković 2002, Pesetsky and Torrego 2007, Castillo et al. 2009, among others): evidence for movement of the subject to/through an infinitival projection above vP (XP) If __ hosts a copy of the subject, it follows that himself can and must be bound by the subject (since closer than the experiencer); if no stop-over movement, these facts would be puzzling. (186) a. b. Johnj seems to Mary to appear to himselfj to be happy. *Mary seems to Johnj to appear to himselfj to be happy. (187) a. b. [John seems to Mary seems [XP __ to [appear to himself appear [vP John to be…]]]] *[Mary seems to John seems [XP __ to [appear to himself appear [vP Mary to be …]]]] • • Intermediate movement in raising constructions (Bošković 2002, Pesetsky and Torrego 2007) But: this position is not Spec,TP, but Spec, AspP. Why should there be movement to this position? • • • Movement is not driven by some EPP, but by locality (Bošković 2002). Back to phases: if AspP is phase, movement of the subject must stop-over in Spec,AspP to escape spell-out. Movement is allowed by Last Resort, since the subject needs to value/check its Case. Why is AspP a phase? • • Standard phase approach (Chomsky 2000, 2001): only vP, CP (maybe DP, PP) are phases. Dynamic phase approaches: • • Bobaljik and Wurmbrand (2005): complement of a lexical verb, whatever its label or size, is an agreement domain. Bošković (2010): the highest projection of the nominal domain counts as a phase. Proposal: the highest projection of the verbal domain (extended projection of V) is a phase. Raising infinitives: AspP is a phase. Back to QR • • Finite clauses (CPs): phases, as before Raising infinitives (XP in (168) = AspP): phases [One potential prediction, which I haven’t been able to test: Does the scope potential of QPs embedded in a raising infinitive change when the QP is modified by a relative clause which interacts scopally with embedded Asp? Judgments are too complex.] Now what about subjunctives, control and ECM infinitives? Short answer • • woll, zero tense, subjunctive are selected by the higher verb This type of selection voids phasehood. 67 10.4 Putting it all together 10.4.1 Selection • Tense of a finite embedded clause is not selected by the higher verb. (188) a. b. c. • Leo said that he is eating a cookie. Leo said that he will eat a cookie. Leo said that he ate a coookie. Aspect in a raising infinitive is not selected by the higher verb (combination of type of embedded predicate—stative vs. non-stative; and higher tense). (189) a. b. c. • John seems to be sleeping right now. John seems to sleep whenever the mailman comes. John seems to like bananas. Subjunctive is dependent on the higher verb. (190) a. b. • I demand that he listen to this. *I said that he listen to this. The type of infinitive is also dependent on the higher verb (191) a. Mary decided to leave tomorrow/to become/get/#to be pregnant (only if the decision is about achieving a future state). Mary claimed to be/*become/*get pregnant/*to leave tomorrow. b. Proposal • • Infinitival tense, subjunctive: selected by the higher verb. Difference to ‘regular’ selection: selected tense/Mod/C is interpretable. (192) a. Future infinitive VP 3 Vdecide ModP uF: woll 2 Mod vP iF: __ @ b. • • • Simultaneous infinitive VP 3 Vclaim TP uF: ∅ 2 T vP iF: __ @ c. Subjunctive VP 3 Vdemand CP uF: SUBJ 2 C TP iF: __ @ uF: woll/∅ is subject to Complementation Merge; hence can only combine with a corresponding iT. Typical configuration for selection (e.g., verbal morphology): iF: val values uF: __ Selection here involves the reversed configuration: uF:val values iF: __ Infinitival T becomes dependent on the higher verb. Matrix V becomes dependent on a particular complement. Consequences for phasehood 68 Assumption: Valuation voids phasehood • • • Only interpretationally complete units can be transferred. iF: __ in a potential phase projection postpones transfer. Similar ideas: Government transparency corollary (Baker 1988), Phase Extension (den Dikken 2007)—head movement voids barrierhood/phasehood; here I propose that headhead-selection (i.e., valuation) also voids phasehood. What about finite complements? • • Different type of selection — complementation merge Complementation merge does not involve valuation (of T, C) by V (C, that, comes valued) • The same is the case in for-infinitives (which are phases): (193) a. b. • A different student wanted to read every book. ∀»∃ A different student wanted for you to read every book. *∀»∃ Johnson (2000): (25) (27) for: matrix V cannot value embedded T across C (accessibility); for is inherently valued iT: woll (similar to that); for-CP combines with matrix V via complementation merge (like a finite CP). 10.4.2 Open issues, outlook, alternatives Implicatives • • • • The tense properties are the same as in raising infinitives; the structure should hence include Asp, but no other tense projections. Wide-scope of an embedded QP over the matrix subject is clearly possible. If the structures involve control, this means that QR from the infinitive must be allowed. One option is to assume that PRO (which can be analyzed as involving unvalued interpretable features) also postpones phasehood (Wurmbrand 2010). This assumption may also be necessary to account for QR across multiple control infinitives. The other option is to assume that these infinitives involve raising. I have not been able to test whether wide scope is possible over elements other than the subject (adding matrix modifiers, creates extraposition structures, which changes the scope potential, even for scope over the subject; cf. #Some woman managed on her/John’s birthday to marry every man). If these constructions involve raising (rather than control), the scope could be the result of reconstruction. (Non-)Restructuring? • Hornstein (1995), Cecchetto (2004) argue that QR is only possible out of restructuring infinitives (unless ACD is involved). (194) a. b. c. Someone persuaded John to attend every class. Someone hated to kiss everyone. Someone wanted for you to meet every woman. 69 *∀»∃ *∀»∃ *∀»∃ [Hornstein 1995] • • For for-infinitives see above. hate involves a factive infinitive, which may have additional structure above TP (e.g., a CP and/or NP); judgments vary significantly for factive infinities in English ((194b) is ungrammatical for many speakers independently of scope). Object control/double object constructions: • • This may be evidence for a Closest/Shortest restriction on QR (at least for speakers who disallow wide scope here—there are also speakers who allow ∀»∃ in (194a)). Suggestion: additional phasal structure in the matrix vP (split vP): [vP1 SUBJECT vP2: phase; VP spelled-out after vP2 is completed; DIRECT OBJECT can control/Agree into infinitive (not a phase) before spell-out. vP1: phase; v1 can Case-license DIRECT OBJECT. Wide scope of embedded object: QR would need to go through the edge of vP2, and VP (if Closest); VP-adjunction is motivated, since scope between persuade and QP changes; but second step would violate Scope Economy; one-step QR to vP2 is allowed if Closest is not in effect. v1 [vP2 DIRECT OBJECT v2 [VP persuade INFINITIVE ]]] Scope out of finite indicative clauses — who, when, how? (195) a. b. • %Someone said that every man is married to Sue. John said that you were on every committee that Bill did say that you were on. [Wilder 1997] Empirical situation of when wide scope out of finite clauses is possible is very unclear. Other phase-based approaches Italian (Cecchetto 2004) • Cecchetto assumes no cyclic spell-out of LF; covert movement occurs after (PF) spell-out and is constrained by the PIC (specifically, the version of Chomsky 2001); the PIC is hence a locality condition on movement and a condition on (PF) spell-out. • Main claim: Non-restructuring infinitives do not allow scope-driven QR; QR out of nonrestructuring infinitives is possible when QR saves ACD but only when embedded VPellipsis resolution is not available. • Italian non-restructuring examples given: o ammettere di fare (‘to admit doing’): factive (see above) o Object control verbs, which solidly disallow restructuring and QR (see above) o cercare di fare ‘to try doing’: marginally allows clitic climbing and QR (examples given as ?) o No future irrealis examples (e.g., decide, plan) are given to illustrate the impossibility of (scope-driven) QR out of these non-restructuring infinitives. 70 Assuming there is indeed a connection between restructuring and QR in Italian… • Difference between QR for inverse scope and QR to fix ACD is, as far as I can tell, only stipulated in Cecchetto’s account: ACD counts as motivation for QR, but scope inversion between a QNP and an intensional verb does not. • The account here could implement this as follows: Option 1: QR out of non-restructuring infinitives is blocked; ACD QR is ‘special’ Option 2: QR out of non-restructuring infinitives is possible in principle (no locality violation); additional (soft) restrictions on QR. • Option 1: Italian infinitives project a CP (di ≈ for—phase); ‘luxury’ QR is impossible (*accessibility or movement to the edge of CP violates Scope Economy); ACD QR is not subject to Scope Economy. Why? Last Resort: If no QR, the structure would crash (note that wide ACD resolution is only possible when embedded VP resolution is impossible). • Option 2: Same structure as in English, but QR is subject to “Fewest steps” in Italian; i.e., two-step QR is dispreferred (but not excluded by locality or Scope Economy); two-step QR is only possible when there are no other alternatives (cf. the impossibility of wide ACD resolution when embedded VP resolution is available); Cecchetto also notes a difference between QR of AcI-subjects, which, under my account, involves only one-step QR (Italian At least one pacifist has seen each of the policemen throwing a stone ?∀»∃) and objects embedded in an AcI complement, which requires two steps of QR (At least one journalist has seen the police officer beating each of the pacifists ?? ∀»∃); QR out of finite clauses violates either accessibility or Scope Economy, and is hence (firmly) excluded. Takahashi (2010) • • • Main claim: phases are defined by Case; scope driven QR is impossible after type-driven QR This is well-motivated for the scope properties of Japanese, but may not extend to English; differences between indicative and subjunctive complements, and between raising and ECM infinitives require additional assumptions. Japanese is similar to Italian (Option 2) in that only one step of QR is allowed; it remains to be determined whether this is also a soft constraint in Japanese. 10.5 Summary Theoretical tools used: • • • • • Reverse Agree, selection as feature valuation (or merge restriction imposed by uFs) Cyclic spell-out Dynamic phase approach Two types of QR and Scope Economy (Fox 2000) Semantic-based determination of infinitival structure 71 The complete picture I argued for: Complement Future infinitive Propositional infinitive Subjunctive Raising infinitive Finite CP Structure wollP TP CP AspP CP Highest head unvalued unvalued unvalued valued valued Phase no no no yes yes QR possible possible possible impossible impossible 10.6 QR Appendix 10.6.1 Eventive predicates • Informal definitions of aspect (see, e.g., Klein 1994, Kratzer 1998, von Stechow 1999): PERFECTIVE: event time interval has to be included in the reference time interval IMPERFECTIVE: reference time interval has to be included in the event time interval. • • • • (IM)PERFECTIVE aspect is projected syntactically in English in non-stative constructions. IMPERFECTIVE aspect: realized with progressive morphology. Consequence: progressive has to be used whenever the reference interval is included in the event interval). (196) Event interval (singing) included in reference interval (yesterday, tomorrow): PERFECTIVE a. b. John sang in the shower yesterday. John will sing in the shower tomorrow. (197) Reference interval (mailman’s arrival) included in event interval (singing): IMPERFECTIVE a. b. *John sang in the shower when the mailman arrived. cf. John was singing in the shower when the mailman arrived. *John will sing in the shower when the mailman arrives. cf. John will be singing in the shower when the mailman arrives. [(197b) is grammatical if it is interpreted in a way that John’s singing will start after (or at the same time as) the mailman’s arrival (e.g. the singing is used as a code or signal to indicate the mailman’s arrival). Under this reading the when clause takes scope over the future elements (i.e., it shifts the reference time to a time after the time of the when clause, which is compatible with a perfective interpretation.] • • • • • Non-generic PRES tense: reference interval (an interval corresponding to the utterance time, the speaker’s ‘now’) necessarily included in event interval; only IMPERFECTIVE. Generic/habitual interpretation: repeated occurrences of singing events, which are included in a larger reference interval; event intervals are included in the reference interval Stative constructions: no aspect is projected. SOT: zero tense associates reference interval of embedded clause with event interval of matrix (time of saying), embedded R is included in E (time of reading) IMPERFECTIVE. Shifted PAST: embedded PAST shifts embedded R to a time before the matrix E; embedded E (time of reading) is included in R (time before saying); PERFECTIVE possible. 72 (198) a. b. c. • John said that Mary was reading Middlemarch. John said that Mary read Middlemarch. [PAST say [∅ was reading/*read ]] SOT possible *SOT SOT Shifted interpretation: if embedded R is restricted to a short interval, e.g., by a when clause (mailman knocking), embedded R is included in embedded E again; progressive required. (199) a. b. John said yesterday that Mary was reading a week ago when the mailman knocked. *John said yesterday that Mary read a week ago when the mailman knocked. (200) a. TP 3 T AspP PAST 3 PRES Asp … ∅ IMPERFECTIVE c. TP 3 T AspP PAST 3 *PRES Asp … *∅ PERFECTIVE b. TP 3 T ModP PAST 3 PRES Mod AspP ∅ woll 3 can Asp … … (IM)PERFECTIVE 10.6.2 Two types of QR—Potential experimental evidence Hackl et al. (2010) (201) The lawyer was careful to remember ... =(27) a. b. c. the fact that the young defense attorney presented the fact that the young defense attorney did the fact that the young defense attorney was d. e. f. every fact that the young defense attorney presented every fact that the young defense attorney did every fact that the young defense attorney was ... during the second cross examination period. • • QPs (201e) facilitate ACD resolution compared to the-DPs (201b) during real time sentence processing in local ellipsis case. Evidence for local QR. Large ellipsis: reverse effect; QPs do not facilitate ACD resolution; non-local QR is different (involves additional processing steps). Moulton (To appear) • • Pen-and-paper questionnaires testing difficulty of QR out of (different types of) infinitives Context biased towards wide-scope 73 Experiment 1 (202) Sample Item: The restaurant was very busy on Saturday night. The head chef needed all his assistant chefs to pitch in. When he returned from the market, he was pleased that an assistant chef prepared/had begun/helped/decided to prepare every dish. How many assistant chefs prepared/had begun/helped/decided to prepare dishes? One Several (203) a. b. c. d. Mono-clausal .71 Restructuring: begin, start, try .61 Implicative restructuring: manage, bother, dare .61 Non-restructuring: decide, hope, expect .49 Mean Proportion of inverse scope responses Paired t-tests on an items analysis: Mono-clausal constructions significantly easier than restructuring Mono-clausal constructions significantly easier than non-restructuring Mono-clausal & implicative: not significant (a)/(b) (a)/(d) Paired t-tests on subjects performance: Mono-clausal constructions & restructuring not significant (not: (a)/(b)) Mono-clausal constructions significantly easier than non-restructuring Mono-clausal constructions significantly easier than implicative (a)/(d) (a)/(c) Experiment 2 (204) a. b. c. • Restructuring: begin, start, finish Potentially restructuring: want, try Non-restructuring: decide, hope, expect .37 .35 .32 Mean Proportion of inverse scope responses No significant difference between any of the above (but tendencies). Summary • • • The experimental evidence seems to show that QR in simple clauses is different from QR out of (any kind of) infinitives. This raises questions for accounts that assume that QR from these two domains is the same. Fox-style account captures this: simple clauses require only one step of QR (type-driven QR), whereas infinitives (whether restructuring, non-restructuring, ECM) require a second step of scope-driven QR, which may be unavailable in some languages. 74 11. REFERENCES Abels, Klaus. 2003. Successive cyclicity, anti-locality, and adposition stranding. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs. Abusch, Dorit. 1985. On verbs and time. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst. Abusch, Dorit. 1988. Sequence of tense, intensionality, and scope. In Proceedings of the 7th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. by Hagit Borer, 1-14. Stanford, Calif: CSLI Publications. Abusch, Dorit. 2004. On the temporal compostion of infinitives. In The syntax of time, ed. by Jacqueline Guéron and Jacqueline Lecarme, 27-53. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Adger, David. 2003. Core Syntax: A Minimalist Approach. Oxford, England: Oxford UP. Bader, Markus, and Schmid, Tanja. 2009. Verb clusters in colloquial German. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 12.3:175-228. Baker, Mark. 1988. Incorporation: A theory of grammatical function changing. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Baker, Mark. 2008. The syntax of agreement and concord. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baker, Mark, and Willie, Willie Udo. 2010. Agreement in Ibibio: From Every Head to Every Head. Syntax: A Journal of Theoretical, Experimental and Interdisciplinary Research 13.2:99-132. Bloemhoff, Henk. 1979. Heranalyse van een Stellingwerver oppervlaktestructuur. Us Wurk: Tydskrift foar Frisistyk 28:31-38. Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 1994. What does adjacency do? In The morphology-syntax connection, ed. by Heidi Harley and Colin Phillips, 1-32. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 22. Cambridge, MA: MIT, Department of Linguistics and Philosophy. Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 1995. Morphosyntax: The syntax of verbal inflection. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 2002. Realizing Germanic Inflection: Why Morphology Does not Drive Syntax. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 6.2-3:129-167. Bobaljik, Jonathan David, and Jonas, Dianne. 1996. Subject Positions and the Roles of TP. Linguistic Inquiry 27:195-236. Bobaljik, Jonathan David, and Thráinsson, Höskuldur. 1998. Two heads aren't always better than one. Syntax 1.1:37-71. Bobaljik, Jonathan David, and Wurmbrand, Susi. 2005. The domain of agreement. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 23.4:809-865. Bošković, Željko. 1996. Selection and the categorial status of Infinitival Complements. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 14:269-304. Bošković, Željko. 1997. The syntax of nonfinite complementation: An economy approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bošković, Željko. 2002. A-Movement and the EPP. Syntax 5.3:167-218. Bošković, Željko. 2007. On the locality and motivation of Move and Agree: An even more minimal theory. Linguistic Inquiry 38.4:589-644. Bošković, Željko. 2009. Unifying First and Last Conjunct Agreement. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 27.3:455-496. Bošković, Željko. 2010. Phases beyond clauses. Ms., University of Connecticut. Storrs. 75 Bošković, Željko. To appear. On unvalued uninterpretable features. In Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society Annual Meeting 39. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, GLSA. Bošković, Željko, and Lasnik, Howard. 2003. On the Distribution of Null Complementizers. Linguistic Inquiry 34.4:527-546. Bresnan, Joan. 1971. A Note on the Notion 'Identity of Sense Anaphora'. Linguistic Inquiry 2:589-597. Brody, Michael. 1997. Perfect chains. In Elements of grammar: Handbook of generative syntax, ed. by Liliane Haegeman, 139-167. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Canac-Marquis, Réjean. 2005. Phases and Binding of Reflexives and Pronouns in English. In Proceedings of the 12th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, ed. by Stefan Müller, 482–502. Stanford, Calif: CSLI Publications. Castillo, Juan Carlos, Drury, John E., and Grohmann, Kleanthes K. 2009. Merge Over Move and the Extended Projection Principle: MOM and the EPP Revisited. Iberia: An International Journal of Theoretical Linguistics 1.1:53-114. Cecchetto, Carlo. 2003. QR in the Theory of Phases. In Proceedings of the 22nd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. by Gina Garding and Mimu Tsujimura, 123-136. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla. Cecchetto, Carlo. 2004. Explaining the locality conditions of QR: Consequences for the theory of phases. Natural Language Semantics 12.3:345–397. Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. by Roger Martin, David Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 2008. On Phases. In Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory, ed. by Robert Freidin, Carlos P. Otero and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta, 133-166. Cambridge, MA: MIT. Chomsky, Noam, and Lasnik, Howard. 1977. Filters and Control. Linguistic Inquiry 8:425-504. Chung, Sandra. 2006. Sluicing and the lexicon: The point of no return. In Proceedings of the 31st Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, ed. by Rebecca T. Cover and Yuni Kim, 73-91. Berkeley: University of California, Berkeley Linguistic Society. Condoravdi, Cleo. 2001. Temporal interpretation of modals: Modals for the present and for the past. In Stanford Papers on Semantics, ed. by David Beaver, Stefan Kaufmann, Brady Clark and Luis Casillas. Stanford, Calif: CSLI Publications. Copley, Bridget. 2002. The semantics of the future. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Despić, Miloje. 2010. Phases, reflexives, and Spell Out domains. Ms. Storrs, Conn. Dikken, Marcel den. 2007. Phase Extension: Contours of a Theory of the Role of Head Movement in Phrasal Extraction. Theoretical Linguistics 33.1:1-41. Dikken, Marcel den, and Hoekstra, Eric. 1997. Parasitic participles. Linguistics 35:1057-1089. Doherty, Cathal. 1993. Clauses without that: The case for bare sentential complementation in English. Doctoral dissertation, University of California Santa Cruz, Santa Cruz. Doherty, Cathal. 1997. Clauses without complementizers: Finite IP-complementation in English. The Linguistic Review 14:197-220. Doherty, Cathal. 2000. Clauses without "that": The case for bare sentential complementation in English. New York: Garland Press. 76 Dowty, David. 1982. Tenses, time adverbs, and compositional semantic theory. Linguistics and Philosophy 9:405-426. Everaert, Martin. 1991. Nominative anaphors in Icelandic: morphology or syntax? In Issues in Germanic Syntax, ed. by Werner Abraham, Wim Kosmeijer and Eric Reuland, 277-305. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter. Fiengo, Robert, and May, Robert. 1994. Indices and Identity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fischer, Silke. 2004. Optimal Binding. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 22.3:481-526. Fischer, Silke. 2006. Matrix Unloaded: Binding in a Local Derivational Approach. Linguistics: An Interdisciplinary Journal of the Language Sciences 44.5:913-935. Fox, Danny. 1999. Reconstruction, binding theory, and the interpretation of chains. Linguistic Inquiry 30.2:157-196. Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and semantic interpretation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/MITWPL. Fox, Danny, and Nissenbaum, Jon. 1999. Extraposition and Scope: a case for overt QR. In Proceedings of the 18th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. by Sonya Bird, Andrew Carnie, Jason D. Haugen and Peter Norquest, 132-144. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press. Franks, Steven. 2005. What is that? In Indiana University Working Papers in Linguistics 5, ed. by Y. Kitagawa and Dorian Roehrs, 33-62. Indiana. Giannakidou, Anastasia. 1998. Polarity Sensitivity as (Non)Veridical Dependency. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Benjamins. Grohmann, Kleanthes K., Drury, John, and Castillo, Juan Carlos. 2000. No More EPP. In Proceedings of the 19th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. by Roger Billerey and Brook Danielle Lillehaugen, 153-166. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla. Hackl, Martin, Koster-Moeller, Jorie, and Varvoutis, Jason. 2010. Quantification and ACD: Evidence from real time sentence processing. Ms. Cambridge, MA. Haegeman, Liliane, and Lohndal, Terje. 2010. Negative Concord and (Multiple) Agree: A Case Study of West Flemish. Linguistic Inquiry 41.2:181-211. Hardt, Daniel. 1993. Verb phrase ellipsis: Form, meaning and processing. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia. Hegarty, Michael. 1991. Adjunct extraction and chain configurations. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Heinat, Frank. 2006. Probes, pronouns, and binding in the Minimalist Program. Doctoral dissertation, University of Lund, Hicks, Glyn. 2006. The derivation of anaphoric relations. Doctoral dissertation, University of York, Hicks, Glyn. 2009. The derivation of anaphoric relations. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Hiraiwa, Ken. 2001. Multiple Agree and the Defective Intervention Constraint in Japanese. In Proceedings of the MIT-Harvard Joint Conference (HUMIT 2000), ed. by Ora Matushansky, 67-80. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 40. Cambridge, MA: MIT, MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Hiraiwa, Ken. 2005. Dimensions of Symmetry in Syntax: Agreement and Clausal Architecture. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Hornstein, Norbert. 1994. An Argument for Minimalism: The Case of Antecedent-Contained Deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 25.3:455-480. 77 Hornstein, Norbert. 1995. Logical form: From GB to Minimalism. Oxford; Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. Huddleston, Rodney, and Pullum, Geoffrey K. 2002. The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Johnsen, Sverre. 2008. Binding in complements of perception verbs. Talk given at East coast workshop in syntax (ECO 5), University of Connecticut. Johnsen, Sverre. To appear. Non-local binding in tenseless clauses. In Papers from the 45th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago: University of Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society. Johnson, Kyle. 2000. How Far Will Quantifiers Go? In Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. by Roger Martin, David Michaels and Juan Uriagereka, 187-210. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Johnson, Kyle. 2001. What VP ellipsis can do, and what it can’t, but not why. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, ed. by Mark Baltin and Chris Collins, 439–479. Oxford: Blackwell. Kaufmann, Stefan. 2005. Conditonal truth and future reference. Journal of Semantics 22.3:231280. Kayne, Richard. 1981. Two notes on the NIC. In Theory of markedness in generative grammar, ed. by Adriana Belletti and Luigi Rizzi, 317--346. Pisa: Scuole Normale Superiore. Kayne, Richard. 1998. Overt vs. covert movement. Syntax 1.2:128-191. Kennedy, Christopher. 1997. Antecedent-contained deletion and the syntax of quantification. Linguistic Inquiry 28.4:662-688. Keshet, Ezra. 2008. Infinitival complements and tense. In Proceedings of SuB12, ed. by Atle Grønn, 303-317. Oslo: University of Oslo. Klein, Wolfgang. 1994. Time in language. London and New York: Routledge. Kratzer, Angelika. 1998. More structural analogies between pronouns and tenses. In Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory VIII, ed. by D. Strolovitch and A. Lawson, 92110. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University, CLC Publications. Kratzer, Angelika. 2009. Making a Pronoun: Fake Indexicals as Windows into the Properties of Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry 40.2:187-237. Kusumoto, Kiyomi. 2005. On the quantification over times in natural language. Natural Language Semantics 13.4:317–357. Ladusaw, William Allen. 1980. Polarity Sensitivity as Inherent Scope Relations. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst. Landau, Idan. 2000. Elements of control: Structure and meaning in infinitival constructions. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Landau, Idan. 2004. The scale of finiteness and the calculus of control. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22.4:811–877. Lasnik, Howard. 1995. Verbal morphology: Syntactic structures meets the Minimalist Program. In Evolution and revolution in linguistic theory: Essays in honor of Carlos Otero, ed. by Héctor Campos and Paula Kempchinsky, 251-275. Washington, D.C.: Gerorgetown University Press. Lasnik, Howard. 1997. A gap in an ellipsis paradigm: Some theoretical implications. Linguistic Analysis 27.3-4:166-185. Lasnik, Howard, and Saito, Mamoru. 1984. On the nature of proper government. Linguistic Inquiry 15:235-289. 78 Lebeaux, David. 1991. Relative clauses, licensing, and the nature of derivation. In Perspectives on phrase structure: heads and licensing, ed. by Susan D. Rothstein, 209-240. San Diego, Calif: Academic Press. Lebeaux, David. 1995. Where does binding theory apply? In Papers in Syntax, Syntax-Semantics Interface and Phonology, ed. by Ricardo Echepare and Viola Miglio, 63-88. College Park: University of Maryland, Department of Linguistics. Lebeaux, David. 2009. Where does binding theory apply? Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lee-Schoenfeld, Vera. 2008. Binding, phases, and locality. Syntax 11.3:281-298. Marantz, Alec. 1991. Case and licensing. In Proceedings of the Eighth Eastern States Conference on Linguistics, ed. by German Westphal, Benjamin Ao and Hee-Rahk Chae, 234-253. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University, CLC Publications. Martin, Roger Andrew. 1996. A minimalist theory of PRO and control. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs. Martin, Roger Andrew. 2001. Null case and the distribution of PRO. Linguistic Inquiry 32.1:141166. Marušič, Franc. 2005. On non-simultaneous phases. Doctoral dissertation, Stony Brook University, Marušič, Franc, Marvin, Tatjana, and Žaucer, Rok. 2003. Depictive secondary predication in Slovenian. In Formal Approaches to Slavic Languages 11, ed. by Wayles Browne, JiYung Kim, Barbara Partee and Robert Rothstein, 373-392. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications. Merchant, Jason. 2008. An Asymmetry in Voice Mismatches in VP-Ellipsis and Pseudogapping. Linguistic Inquiry 39.1:169-179. Merchant, Jason. 2011. Aleut case matters. In Pragmatics and Autolexical Grammar: In honor of Jerry Sadock, ed. by Etsuyo Yuasa Yuasa, Tista Bagchi and Katharine P. Beals, 382-411. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Merchant, Jason. To appear. Polarity items under ellipsis. In Diagnosing syntax, ed. by Lisa Cheng and Norbert Corver. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press. Moulton, Keir. To appear. Scope relations and infinitival complements. In UMOP: Processing and Semantics, ed. by Jan Anderssen. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications. Nunes, Jairo, and Zocca, Cynthia. 2005. Morphological identity in ellipsis. In Leiden Papers in Linguistics, ed. by Noureddine Elouazizi, Frank Landsbergen, Mika Poss and Martin Salzmann, 29-42. Leiden: Leiden University. Nunes, Jairo, and Zocca, Cynthia. 2009. Lack of morphological identity and ellipsis resolution in Brazilian Portuguese. In Minimalist Essays on Brazilian Portuguese Syntax, ed. by Jairo Nunes, 215-236. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Ogihara, Toshiyuki. 1996. Tense, attitude, and scope. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Owens, Jonathan. 1985. A Grammar of Harar Oromo (Northeastern Ethiopia). Hamburg: Helmut Buske Verlag. Pesetsky, David. 1992. Zero syntax II: An essay on infinitives. Ms., MIT. Cambridge, MA. Pesetsky, David. 1995. Zero syntax: Experiencers and cascades. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pesetsky, David. 1998. Some Optimality Principles of Sentence Pronunciation. In Is the Best Good Enough? Optimality and Competition in Syntax, ed. by Pilar Barbosa, Danny Fox, Paul Hagstrom, Martha McGinnis and David Pesetsky, 337-383. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press and MITWPL. 79 Pesetsky, David, and Torrego, Esther. 2004. Tense, case, and the nature of syntactic categories. In The syntax of time, ed. by Jacqueline Guéron and Jacqueline Lecarme, 495-537. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pesetsky, David, and Torrego, Esther. 2006. Probes, Goals and Syntactic Categories. In Proceedings of the 7th annual Tokyo Conference on Psycholinguistics. Keio University, Japan. Pesetsky, David, and Torrego, Esther. 2007. The syntax of valuation and the interpretability of features. In Phrasal and clausal architecture, ed. by Simin Karimi, Vida Samiian and Wendy Wilkins, 262-294. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Portner, Paul. 2003. The (Temporal) Semantics and (Modal) Pragmatics of the Perfect. Linguistics and Philosophy 26:459–510. Quicoli, A. Carlos. 2008. Anaphora by Phase. Syntax 11.3:299-329. Quirk, Randolph, Greenbaum, Sidney, Leech, Geoffrey, and Svartvik, Jan. 1972. A Grammar of Contemporary English. New York: Seminar. Reis, Marga. 1997. Zum syntaktischen Status unselbständiger Verbzweit-Sätze. In Sprache im Fokus. Festschrift für Heinz Vater zum 65. Geburtstag, ed. by Christa Dürscheid, Karl Heinz Rahmers and Monika Schwarz, 121–144. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Reuland, Eric. 2001. Primitives of binding. Linguistic Inquiry 32.3:439-492. Reuland, Eric. 2005. Agreeing to Bind. In Organizing Grammar, ed. by Hans Broekhuis, Norbert Corver, Riny Huybregts, Ursula Kleinhenz and Jan Koster, 505-513. Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter. Reuland, Eric. 2011. Anaphora and Language Design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Richards, Norvin. 1996. Toward a Feature-Movement Theory of Long-Distance Anaphora. Ms., MIT. Cambridge, MA. Richards, Norvin. 1997. Competition and disjoint reference. Linguistic Inquiry 28.1:178-187. Rizzi, Luigi. 1990. On the anaphor-agreement effect. Rivista di Linguistica 2:27–42. Rudin, Catherine. 1988. On multiple questions and multiple WH fronting. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 6.4:445-501. Sag, Ivan. 1976. Deletion and Logical Form. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Schäfer, Florian. 2008. The Syntax of (Anti-)Causatives: External Arguments in Change-of-State Contexts. Amsterdam, Netherlands: Benjamins. Stechow, Arnim von. 1999. Eine Erweiterte Extended Now-Theorie für Perfekt und Futur. Zeitschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Linguistik 113:86-118. Svenonius, Peter. 1994. Dependent Nexus: Subordinate predication structures in English and the Scandinavian languages. Doctoral dissertation, University of California Santa Cruz, Santa Cruz. Takahashi, Masahiko. 2010. Case, phases, and nominative/accusative conversion in Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 19.4:319-155. Thiersch, Craig. 1978. Topics in German syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA. Thomason, Richard. 1970. Indeterminist time and truth-value gaps. Theoria 36:264-281. Truckenbrodt, Hubert. 1995. Extraposition from NP and prosodic structure. In Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society Annual Meeting 25, ed. by Jill N. Beckman, 503517. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, GLSA. Truckenbrodt, Hubert. 2006. On the semantic motivation of syntactic verb movement to C in German. Theoretical Linguistics 32.3:257-306. 80 Tucker, Matthew. 2010. On the implications of the anaphor agreement effect for binding as Agree. Ms., UCSC. Santa Cruz. Vogel, Ralf. 2009. Skandal im Verbkomplex: Betrachtungen zur scheinbar inkorrekten Morphologie in infiniten Verbkomplexen des Deutschen. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 28.2:307–346. Warner, Anthony. 1986. Ellipsis conditions and the status of the English copula. In York Papers in Linguistics 12, 153-172. Webelhuth, Gert. 1992. Principles and parameters of syntactic saturation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wechsler, Stephen. 1991. Verb second and illocutionary force. In Views on phrase structure, ed. by Katherine Leffel and Denis Bouchard, 177–191. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Wiklund, Anna-Lena. 2001. Dressing up for vocabulary insertion: the parasitic supine. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19.1:199-228. Wiklund, Anna-Lena. 2005. The syntax of tenselessness: On copying constructions in Swedish. Doctoral dissertation, Umeå University, Wiklund, Anna-Lena. 2007. The syntax of tenselessness: Tense/mood/aspect-agreeing infinitivals. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Wilder, Chris. 1997. Phrasal movement in LF: de re readings, VP-ellipsis and binding. In Proceedings of the North Eastern Linguistics Society Annual Meeting 27, ed. by Kiyomi Kusumoto, 425–439. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, GLSA. Woolford, Ellen. 1999. More on the anaphor agreement effect. Linguistic Inquiry 30.2:257-287. Wurmbrand, Susi. 2006. Licensing Case. Journal of Germanic Linguistics 18.3:175-234. Wurmbrand, Susi. 2010. Parasitic morphology in Germanic: Consequences for the theory of feature checking. Ms., University of Connecticut. Storrs. [Detailed handout available at: http://wurmbrand.uconn.edu/Susi/Agree.html]. Wurmbrand, Susi. 2011a. Parasitic participles in Germanic: Evidence for the theory of verb clusters. Submitted to Taal en Tongval. Wurmbrand, Susi. 2011b. Tense and aspect in English infinitives. Ms., University of Connecticut. Storrs. [Available at: http://wurmbrand.uconn.edu/Susi/Infinitives.html]. Zaenen, Anne, Maling, Joan, and Thráinsson, Höskuldur. 1985. Case and grammatical functions: The Icelandic passive. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 3:441-483. Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2010. There is only one way to agree. Talk given at 33rd GLOW Colloquium, Wroclaw, Poland. Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 1995. A note on verb clusters in the Stellingwerf dialect. In Linguistics in the Netherlands 1995, ed. by Marcel den Dikken and Kees Hengeveld, 215-226. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 81