Constructing liberal responsibilities and the Syria crisis
Transcription
Constructing liberal responsibilities and the Syria crisis
Constructing liberal responsibilities and the Syria crisis. Jason Ralph University of Leeds and University of Queensland This is work in progress. Please do not quote or cite. Paper for Panel SD74 The R2P and the Syrian Crisis: Constructivist scholarship and International Practice International Studies Association New Orleans, February 2015 Introduction Between March 2011 and April 2014 an estimated 191,369 people were killed in the conflict in Syria. 1 It is difficult to discern how many of these casualties were non-combatants, but the 7th Report of the United Nations (UN) Independent Commission of Inquiry, which was published toward the end of this period, provided evidence of continuing acts of unlawful killings by both state and non-state actors. In addition, the Commission of Inquiry reported continuing acts of arbitrary arrest, unlawful detention, hostagetaking, enforced disappearances, torture and ill-treatment, sexual and gender-based violence, and violations of children’s rights. Approximately 250,000 people remained besieged at the time of the Report. 2 In August 2014, the UN High Commissioner for Refugees stated that three million Syrians had registered as refugees outside of their country, while a further 6.5 million people are displaced within Syria. Almost half of all Syrians had been forced to abandon their homes due to the conflict. 3 The purpose of this paper is to examine what constructivist International Relations theory tells us about how the liberal state should respond to this situation. How states should act is of course a normative issue and for this reason the author might be accused of asking the wrong question. Constructivism, it might be claimed, is a social not a normative theory. It focuses on the ‘is’ without commenting on the ‘ought’. It can explain why the situation in Syria was a ‘crisis’ for liberal states even if their material interests were not at stake. Constructivists, at least in the conventional or positivist version, would argue that complying with humanitarian norms like the Responsibility to Protect (R2P) would be consistent with self-images of the liberal state and they would Price, et al. 2014 United Nations Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights 2014 3 Anonymous 2014 1 2 explain (non-)compliance in terms that referenced how well those norms had been ‘internalized’. 4 Constructivists as social scientists would not advocate a particular response to the Syrian situation nor would they judge state behaviour. That task would be left to normative theorists. 5 Recently, however, a number of well-known constructivist theorists have taken up Richard Price’s call to unite normative and social theory with the dual aim of substantiating the constructivist’s claim to explain ‘moral progress’ and to better inform ethical reasoning. 6 The objective here is to build on this work and to consider what kind of ethics emerge from constructivist theory of International Relations. The paper is structured in three sections. The first develops the argument that constructivism can, in present times, support a cosmopolitan ethic of protection. However, the constructivist emphasis on social and historical contingency of morality forecloses ‘foundationalist’ and ‘impartialist’ accounts of this kind of cosmopolitanism. A constructivist cosmopolitan position therefore is only ‘anchored’ in these ‘weak’ foundations. This encourages a degree of ‘fallibalism’, or an appreciation of the moral claims of other communities (national and international), as well as a recognition of the moral value contained in honest attempts to reconcile normative dilemmas, including attempts to reduce the necessity of tragic choice. Building on the theme of normative contingency, the second section draws on ‘critical’, ‘post-positivist’, ‘consistent’ or ‘reflexivist’ conceptions of constructivism to say something about the R2P as a norm. Drawing in particular on the work of Antje Weiner, and relating it to Jennifer Welsh’s recent articles, this section observes the significance this shift to a reflexivist approach has for the foreign policy of the liberal state. 7 Specifically, the paper argues that liberal states should be aware of the need to constantly (re)establish the normativity of the norm in a deliberative process at the international level. The danger of taking the meaning of the R2P norm as fixed is that the views of those opposing liberal states at the UN, for instance, are dismissed (variously) as rejectionist and obstructionist. Efforts to ‘socialize’ these positions by labelling them ‘hypocritical’ risks a backlash that undermines the international consensus on which certain aspects of the R2P norms depends. A reflexivist constructivist approach can inform a progressive approach to R2P, whereas a conventional constructivist approach promises a potentially selfdefeating and regressive policy. To illustrate how this informs a normative assessment of state behavior, the third section focuses on liberal state responses to the Syrian crisis. Much attention has been given to the Russian and Chinese The concept of internalization originates from norm life-cycle theory set out in Finnemore and Sikkink 1998. For a similar observation see Weber 2014, 520-1. 6 Price 2008a, b, c, d. See collection of essays building on this agenda in Price 2008e; also Price 2012a and Price 2012b. For an earlier call along these lines see Price and Reus-Smit 1998. On the ‘conventional’ (Weber 2014 prefers ‘mainstream’) constructivist shift away from its ‘critical’ origins see Hopf 1998. See also Reus-Smit 2008, 72, who notes how early constructivism shared with critical theory ‘a normative commitment to bettering the human condition’. He quotes Wendt 1995, 71 who argued it would ‘it would be irresponsible to pursue policies that perpetuated destructive old orders’ it constructivism demonstrated that change is possible. See also Hurd 2008; Fierke 2013. 7 Wiener 2004, 2009, 2014; Welsh 2013, Welsh 2014. 4 5 vetoes of the resolutions proposing international responses to the crisis and whether they were somehow provoked by liberal overreach during the Libya crisis. 8 This paper takes a slightly different track. It offers as a hypothesis the argument that the Security Council has failed to meet its responsibilities in part because Russia and China have been framed as R2P obstructionists, especially after the Libya intervention, and because liberal states have reacted to this by trying to shame them into reversing their approach. This is consistent with a conventional constructivist playbook but it is potentially counterproductive. This argument, should it be proven, by no means justifies the Russian and Chinese vetoes. The motives behind the vetoes are complex, as is their relation to R2P. The argument does, however, show how a reflexivist constructivist approach can lead to normative assessments of liberal state practice; and specifically in this instance, how it can lead to criticism of the liberal state response the Syria situation. ‘Embedded’ cosmopolitanism. Why should liberal states risk the lives and welfare of their citizens to protect vulnerable non-citizens like those caught in the Syrian conflict? Cosmopolitans would answer this question by insisting that national boundaries are morally arbitrary and should have no bearing on how this question is answered. The Syrian people are of equal moral value to those peoples residing in liberal states; and, as ‘citizens of the world’, the leaders of liberal states have a right and a duty to protect ‘foreign’ peoples just as they would protect their own. This ethical cosmopolitan position is commonly rejected by communitarians in three ways: epistemologically (how do we know morality?), sociologically (how is moral community constructed?) and normatively (what kind of morality is preferred?). From the communitarian position, cosmopolitans incorrectly assume that morality can be divorced from social settings to provide ‘impartial’ (and therefore authoritative) views of right behavior. Moreover, cosmopolitans are said to exaggerate the extent to which the moral boundaries of the state can be transformed, as well as to devalue the role particular communities, such as the nation, play in enabling the individual to live a fulfilling life. It is argued in this paper that constructivism lends support to the first of these points but it does not necessarily support the second or third. Accepting that morality is bounded by conceptions of the community does not mean accepting that a community’s moral boundaries are fixed around the nationstate. By demonstrating the processes by which these boundaries are socially (re)constituted, constructivism reveals how, at least in contemporary international relations, the liberal state and its citizens are in fact situated in various communities including, national, international and global communities. Each of these potentially has equal claim to moral value and authority. The pursuit of the fulfilling life is thus complicated by the existence of multiple social identities. Russia and China have exercised the so-called ‘double veto’ on four separate occasions: 4 October 2011; 4 February 2012; 19 July 2012 and 22 May 2014. Bellamy 2014b; Morris 2013; Ralph 2014; Ralph and Gallagher 2014. 8 The argument that constructivism poses a problem for ‘impartialist’ conceptions of cosmopolitanism is drawn from Toni Erskine’s criticism of Price’s attempt to unite social and normative theory into one ethical position. 9 For Price, constructivists have to engage with normative theory if they are to justify the claim that their approach illustrates the possibility of normative progress and not simply normative change. 10 An international intervention to protect the human rights of the Syrian people could only be classed as moral progress, for instance, if human rights were proven to be of moral value. This requires an argument grounded in normative theory. Erskine’s criticism is not that the constructivists who responded to Price’s call failed to do this. Rather, her criticism is that they did this but failed to remain committed to a key insight of constructivism, which is that moral agency is ‘radically situated and socially determined’. 11 To illustrate this, Erskine focuses mainly on Kathryn Sikkink’s response to Price’s challenge. For Erskine, Sikkink fails to articulate a constructivist ethic because she ‘outsourced’ the normative theorizing and defended her normative commitment to human rights by ‘borrowing from Rawls’. 12 Erskine’s concern here is not with this ‘division of labour’. Her concern instead is that Sikkink’s Rawlsian foundation is based on a thought experiment (the veil of ignorance), which assumes moral agents can detach themselves from their social settings and engage in moral reasoning from impartial standpoints. Sikkink’s approach addresses the call to provide a normative foundation, and it may even substantiate the claim that movement to a human rights culture is a form of moral progress, but it is not a constructivist ethic. This is because constructivism demonstrates that moral reasoning is inevitably influenced by the kind of social structures that deny the possibility of impartialist approaches. In those accounts (like Sikkink’s) that ‘outsource’ ethical reasoning to abstract normative theorists (like Rawls), constructivism remains a social theory concerned only with the process of implementing a progressive policy. It does not build the moral foundations that establish the ‘good’ toward which society should move. 13 This ‘ethically attenuated account’ is problematic for the claim to identify an ethic that is specifically constructivist. Indeed, the way that liberal cosmopolitan positions tend to appeal to impartialist starting points does seem radically at odds with constructivism’s own assumption that the identities of actors are defined by the institutionalized norms and values of their social contexts, making political agency (and arguably moral agency) radically situated and socially determined. This apparent obstacle to establishing an internally generated constructivist ethic deserves attention. 14 Erskine 2012 Price 2008c 11 Erskine 2012p.461. 12 Erskine 2012p.456. 13 See also Weber 2014. 14 Erskine 2012 p.461. 9 10 The obstacle Erskine refers to is recognizable to normative theorists as communitarianism; and of course Erskine’s work prior to her engagement with Price’s constructivist project explored this problem in great depth. 15 Specifically, Erskine examined ways in which a cosmopolitan commitment to the moral equality of outsiders could be reconciled with, or embedded within, a communitarian approach that situated morality within the context of a particular community, which in International Relations was often discussed in terms of the nation-state. She does this by drawing on feminist theory, specifically the concepts of the ‘dislocated’ community (i.e. communities that are not identified by territory), and the ‘complex’ self (i.e. a moral actor with multiple identities). This offers the possibility that a cosmopolitan ethic that insists on the moral equality of outsiders can emerge within a global community and that cosmopolitanism is not therefore reliant on abstract and impartialist theoretical notions that constructivist theory cannot sustain. Indeed, this insight suggests that constructivists like (and especially) Sikkink need not have outsourced their normative theorizing. Their work demonstrating the sociological significance of transnational advocacy networks can also be used to address Erskine’s concern that the constructivist’s commitment to human rights is internally inconsistent because it is not ‘radically situated or socially determined’. 16 The moral position taken by human rights advocates may not be situated in, or determined by, the nation but that does not mean it is inconsistent with the communitarian position that a constructivist understanding of norms requires. Human rights advocacy can be normatively anchored in transnational communities, the existence of which constructivist scholarship has charted. 17 Constructivist scholarship mapping the existence of these communities gives so-called 'norm-entrepreneurs' the moral authority to at least criticise those exclusionary conceptions of right conduct that would deny international assistance to vulnerable populations like the Syrian people. 18 The critical moral agency that is sometimes missing from communitarian approaches is thus generated in this account at the point where multiple identities produce and expose conflicting responsibilities. The idea that a moral position is ‘anchored’ in the shifting sands of contingent social structures rather than ‘grounded’ on the concrete foundations of impartialist standpoints is the concession a constructivist informed ethic must make if it is to remain true to its roots in social theory. The ‘anchor’ metaphor is used by those taking a ‘pragmatic’ approach to normative International Relations theory. 19 This does not mean a constructivist informed ethic of embedded cosmopolitanism lacks any foundation, it merely insists that its foundations are ‘weak’ because they are historically contingent. 20 This might be an unsatisfactory situation because it potentially leads to historical (if not cultural) relativism. It can be difficult for some liberals to accept that a cosmopolitan ethic has no foundation if the sociological Erskine 2002, 2008. Erskine 2012p.461. 17 Keck and Sikkink 1998 18 On norm entrepreneurship see Finnemore and Sikkink 1998 19 Cochran 1999. See also Booth 1995 119. 20 Cochran 1999. See also Hoffmann 2009, pp.241-3. 15 16 conditions are not realized, but that conclusion surely follows on from a constructivist ontology. 21 As Erskine reminds us: ‘[a]n inclusive moral purview is possible when the moral agent assumes a particularist starting point (a concession denied by assumptions underlying both communitarian realist and impartialist cosmopolitan positions); however, it cannot be guaranteed’. 22 Yet constructivism does defend liberal cosmopolitanism against the cultural relativist’s claim that there is not, never has been, nor can there ever be, a global community of humankind that demands the state’s moral concern. 23 Indeed, cosmopolitan liberals can take encouragement from the contemporary historical situation. Bukovansky et. al argue that communitarian realists ‘cannot deny that the processes of globalisation have reshaped and expanded social relations and the idea of moral and political community, along with the expansion of obligations to others and the spread of cosmopolitan norms, such as human rights (if typically thinly and unevenly).’ 24 Moral pluralism, contestation and international society Because constructivism shares with communitarianism the understanding that identity and morality is ‘radically situated and socially determined’ 25 it cannot necessarily dismiss as immoral the unwillingness of citizens to endure the costs and risks of humanitarian intervention. Nor can it discard the other side of the coin: the insistence that citizens should endure greater costs out of a duty to humankind. One might argue, however, that a moral standpoint can be found (to use Erskine’s phrase) at the ‘point where the circles [multiple identities] intersect’. 26 This poses the question of how a state reconciles the moral dilemmas that arise from the multiple social identities that embed this kind of cosmopolitanism. That is the subject of an alternative version of this paper. The focus here is on the specific dilemmas that arise from the state’s identification with a world society of humankind and an international society of states. The idea that constructivism cannot prioritize a cosmopolitan ethic of protection over a communitarian ethic of the national or international interest is potentially problematic for R2P advocates. These cosmopolitans tend to claim that constructivism is an ally of what they see as progressive change. R2P advocates have for instance adopted conventional constructivist language to explain the processes by which the ethic of protection can be ‘insititutionalized’ in the practices of states. 27 Here the 2005 World Summit Outcome Document is held up as the moment when R2P was adopted by states as a standard of appropriate behavior and, following constructivist social theory, a source of leverage over government practice. Because states are said to be guided by the logic of appropriateness, that is, cosmopolitan ‘norm Hoffmann 2009, p.246. Erskine 2008 p.178. 23 For a critique of this kind of ‘presentism’ see Booth 1999. 24 Bukovansky, et al. 2012. See also Linklater 2001; Linklater 2011; Bray 2013. 25 Erskine 2012p.461. 26 Erskine 2002. 27 Badescu and Weiss 2010; Badescu 2011 pp.101-35; Contarino, et al. 2012; Knight 2011; Shawki 2011. 21 22 entrepreneurs’ can compel R2P-consistent behavior by exposing inappropriate practice as ‘hypocrisy’. 28 There is from this cosmopolitan constructivist perspective linearity to moral progress. The definition of appropriate behavior (i.e. the normativity of the norm) remains fixed, and progress is judged by how close states are to fulfilling their responsibility to protect as a matter of course or habit (i.e. the normalness of the norm). This approach to constructivism, however, is now labelled ‘conventional’, ‘mainstream’, ‘behaviourist’ or ‘positivist’. A ‘critical’, ‘reflexive’ ‘consistent’ or ‘post-positivist’ approach has emphasized the intersubjectivity of the norm and the role language and discourse plays in repeatedly constructing its meaning. 29 This latter approach opens up the possibility of what Thomas Risse identified as a third logic of state behavior. In addition to the instrumentalist ‘logic of consequentialism’ and the rule based ‘logic of appropriateness’, state’s are said to act according to the ‘logic of arguing’, which implies openness to being persuaded by the better argument.30 It also implies that the meaning (or prescription if not proscription) of a norm is not always fixed, Furthermore, the logic of arguing does not ‘infantilize’ agents by reducing them to ‘cultural dupes’ with little impact on society. 31 As Risse noted, rule-guided behaviour rarely occurs as matter of course or habit. It is often a conscious process whereby actors have to figure out the situation in which they act, apply the appropriate norm, or choose among conflicting rules. The more norms are contested, the less the logic of the situation can be captured by the statement “good people do X” than by “what does ‘good’ mean in this situation?” or even “what is the right thing to do?” But how do actors adjudicate which norm applies? They argue. 32 More recently, Antje Wiener has developed this approach. 33 Writing against the backdrop of the US war on terror and the Bush administration’s interpretation of norms such as the Convention against Torture, Wiener noted how a ‘reflexive approach’ presupposes ‘that meanings – while stable over long periods of time and within particular contexts – are always in principle contested’. 34 The potential for contestation increases as the norm is transferred between different contexts. This is because differently socialized individuals – for example politicians, civil servants, parliamentarians, lawyers, lobbyists, journalists and so on – who have been trained in a variety of traditions and For constructivist analysis of hypocrisy, including the possibility that ‘it can also perform positive social functions, enabling the medium- to long-term achievement of seemingly incompatible goods’, see Reus-Smit 2008 pp.78-9. See also Gurowitz 2008; Lynch 2008. 29 Fierke 2013. See also Zehfuss 2001; Epstein 2013. 30 Risse 2000. See also Müller 2004; Deitelhoff and Müller 2005. 31 Barnett 1999, p.7. See also Doty 1997; Wiener 2004; Epstein 2012. 32 Risse 2000 p.6. 33 Wiener 2004, 2009, 2014; Wiener and Puetter 2009. 34 Wiener 2004, p.200. Although Wiener does not address the contested character of the anti-torture norm, Wiener and Puetter 2009 introduces a special issue that does. See in particular Liese 2009, Venzke 2009. 28 been socialized in different day-to-day circumstances seek to interpret them. While the potential for misunderstandings and conflicts can be kept at bay by adding a deliberative dimension to facilitate arguing and ultimately persuasion that one meaning should legitimately trump another, it is important to keep a key limitation of this approach in mind: Arguing takes place within a limited context of negotiation, say within one particular committee. It is hence conducive to establishing social recognition of a fundamental norm, say human rights, within that specific and limited context only. To warrant social recognition of human rights in another context, arguing would need to resume anew, and so on. 35 In her earlier work, Wiener does not elaborate on the normative implications of this insight, limiting her conclusion to the argument that constructivists should engage in discourse analysis, which can expose the way norms accommodate various ‘meanings-in-use’. 36 However, she has more recently developed the argument that contestation is a normative concept to be encouraged. 37 This stems from a concern that a norm lacks legitimacy (and thus stability) if stakeholders (i.e. those impacted by its social power) are denied an opportunity to contest it. Thus, creating the opportunity for regular contestation can help preempt conflict and the outright rejection or instrumental use of a norm. 38 This clearly has implications for the way the liberal state should respond to situations like Syria. From a critical or reflexive constructivist point of view, the liberal state should expect, accept and indeed encourage the contestation of norms like R2P, and this fits with the above argument that the cosmopolitan ethic on which R2P rests is necessarily fallible. To be sure, contestation does not mean the outright rejection of the cosmopolitan claim that the liberal state has a responsibility to end mass atrocity in any given situation. Rather, the normative concept of contestation insists that the cosmopolitan argument be tested by processes of deliberation that are inclusive of different arguments. It is not unreasonable to expect the liberal state to meet this standard of behavior. This is because deliberation ‘reflects the central assumption that is common to the range of approaches to democratic constitutionalism, namely, that in principle, the norms, rules and principles of governance ought to be contestable at any time by those governed by them.’ 39 Wiener 2009, p.181. Emphasis added. See also Wiener 2008. This can help explain some of the frustration with R2P as a norm, to the extent advocates cite the increased frequency of R2P references within the limited context of UN discourse while recognising international society’s wider failing to respond in a timely and decisive way in Syria. See Bellamy 2014b. 36 Wiener 2004, 2009; Wiener and Puetter 2009. 37 Wiener 2014. 38 Wiener 2014. See also Acharya 2013; Weber 2014. Price 2008c p.11 hinted at this when he wrote: ‘rather than simply ordain an ethical evaluation from a perspective one might defend on deontological or utilitarian grounds, constructivism would additionally encourage the empirical embodiment of a dialogic ethic to open up and buttress the grounds of such assessments’. 39 Wiener 2014, p.4. 35 What is valued in this commitment to deliberation is a procedural ethic; and to the extent that is outcome neutral (impartial) one could argue that it remains consistent with the moral agnosticism of constructivist social theory. It does insist that those who hold substantive moral positions (communitarians, cosmopolitans) approach deliberation as a ‘truth seeking exercise’ and this of course requires openness to moral compromise. 40 But then this too fits with the constructivist argument that these positions are necessarily fallible and that the state will inevitably engage in some form of a deliberation because of the ontological imperative to construct a coherent conception of its essential Self. It also remains consistent with the pragmatist argument that normative value is found in the manner in which a substantive argument is offered. 41 In other words, an arguing position that tries to persuade should also accept the possibility that it will be persuaded. In terms of assessing the liberal state’s response to situations such as Syria this involves governments encouraging deliberation in, for instance, the legislative chamber and Security Council, participating in that process and then accepting the outcome. 42 To be sure, the argument here is not that ‘the better argument’ will prevail, or that moral ‘truth’ will emerge from this process. Critical constructivism recognises that power can still influence access, and participants may not deliberate in the spirit demanded by Habermasian discourse ethics. 43 The argument instead is that this process is a factor in understanding and assessing the policy response of states to normative questions. Assessing the response to the Syria vetoes. The purpose of this section is to illustrate how the reflexivist constructivist position of Wiener and Welsh makes us look differently at the liberal state’s response to the Syria crisis. The commitment to deliberation as a means of testing the normativity or appropriateness of a norm (and norm-inspired action) is crucial to this approach; and in this respect reflexivist constructivists would welcome the apparent commitment to coordinating an international response to the Syria crisis through the UN. Of course, there have been moments – especially August 2013 – when a coalition of liberal states (the US, UK and France) appeared willing to use force without Security Council authorization; but they ultimately pulled back from this to pursue the disarmament of chemical weapons through a diplomatic process coordinated through the UN. Recognizing the importance of the United Nations to ending the violence and atrocity in Syria, these states have sought to pass Security Council resolutions on numerous occasions. On four of these occasions Russia and China have exercised a double veto. On the 4 October 2011, France, Germany, Portugal and the UK proposed a resolution that recalled ‘the Syrian Government’s primary responsibility to protect its population’, condemned the ongoing violence, demanded Risse 2000 Cochran 1999 42 See also who finds a ‘a responsibility to consider’ how best to respond to mass atrocity in ‘post-positivist’ constructivism. Welsh 2013. 43 Risse 2000. 40 41 accountability and humanitarian access, and called upon all states ‘to exercise vigilance and restraint over the direct or indirect supply, sale or transfer to Syria of arms and related materiel’. 44 On 4 February 2012, 19 states proposed a resolution that did not refer to R2P, reaffirmed ‘its strong commitment to the sovereignty, independence, unity and territorial integrity of Syria, emphasizing its intention to resolve the current political crisis in Syria peacefully, and noting that nothing in this resolution authorizes measures under Article 42 of the Charter’. It demanded that Syria act in accordance with the Plan of Action of the League of Arab States, and fully supported the League’s decision ‘to facilitate a Syrian-led political transition to a democratic, plural political system, in which citizens are equal regardless of their affiliations or ethnicities or beliefs’. 45 On 19 July 2012 France, Germany, Portugal, UK and US proposed a resolution that again did not refer to R2P and again reiterated ‘its strong commitment to the sovereignty, independence, unity and territorial integrity of Syria’. Acting under Chapter VII, it demanded ‘the urgent, comprehensive, and immediate implementation of all elements of the [UN] Envoy’s six-point proposal’; and it decided ‘that, if the Syrian authorities have not fully complied with paragraph 4 above within ten days, then it shall impose immediately measures under Article 41 of the UN Charter’. 46 And finally, on 22 May 2014, the French proposed referring the Syrian situation to the International Criminal Court. 47 On each occasion, the resolutions commanded healthy majorities but were blocked by the Russian and Chinese votes. 48 The majorities at the Security Council have normative significance. It suggests Russia and China lost the argument. They certainly added to the French, UK and US frustration. What is important here, however, is how these states responded to the vetoes at the Security Council; and the point being made is that this response looks as if it emerged from a conventional constructivist playbook. As noted, the argument among conventional constructivists is that norm outliers can be socialized into pursuing norm compliant behavior if their actions are exposed as being hypocritical or shameful. Norm-entrepreneurs are therefore advised to engage in the public shaming of norm-outliers and this, it appears, is how the UK and, in particular, the French and the US responded to the double vetoes. To be sure, the responses at the Security Council did not explicitly refer to state responsibilities under the R2P doctrine, and one might argue that the US, UK and France did not necessarily see themselves in any specific sense as defenders of the commitments made at the World Summit Outcome Document. Nevertheless, it is clear that they all made the argument that the Security Council had a special responsibility to do what it could to end the humanitarian crisis in Syria, and they all claimed that the double veto had prevented the Council from meeting that responsibility. http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/2011/612 http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/2012/77 46 http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/2012/538 47 http://www.un.org/en/ga/search/view_doc.asp?symbol=S/2014/348 48 Only during on the 19 July 2012 proposed resolution was the majority less than 13. Pakistan and South Africa abstained. 44 45 The public shaming of Russia and China is evident in the following quotations taken from the S/PVs of the above votes. “Let me be clear. The United States believes it is past time for this Council to assume its responsibilities and impose tough, targeted sanctions and an arms embargo on the Assad regime, as we have done domestically. Yet today, the courageous people of Syria can now see clearly who on this Council supports their yearning for liberty and universal human rights, and who does not. … Those who oppose this draft resolution and give cover to a brutal regime will have to answer to the Syrian people and, indeed, to people across the region who are pursuing the same universal aspirations.” US Ambassador Susan Rice, 4 October 2011 (S/PV.6627). “Others claim that strong Security Council action on Syria would merely be a pretext for military intervention. Let there be no doubt: this is not about military intervention; this is not about Libya. That is a cheap ruse by those who would rather sell arms to the Syrian regime than stand with the Syrian people.” US Ambassador Susan Rice, 4 October 2011 (S/PV.6627). “We cannot and must not overlook the harrowing conclusion that two permanent members of the Council have systematically obstructed all its action. They do so in the full knowledge of the tragic consequences of their decisions for the Syrian people. And in so doing, they are making themselves complicit in the policy of repression being implemented by the Damascus regime. … Whatever they may claim, they have de facto taken the side of the Al-Assad regime against the Syrian people.” French Ambassador, Gérard Araud 4 February 2012 (S/PV.6711). “History will judge harshly those countries that have prevented the Council from offering its support to the courageous efforts of the Arab League to implement its plan. In so doing, they have without scruple aligned themselves with a regime slaughters its own people. In so doing, they have judged that their presence in the Middle East now depends on the future of the Al-Assad. That presence and that regime will endure the same fate.” French Ambassador, Gérard Araud 4 February 2012 (S/PV.6711). “The United States is disgusted that a couple of members of this Council continue to prevent us from fulfilling our sole purpose here, which is to address an ever-deepening crisis in Syria and a growing threat to regional peace and security. … For months, this Council has been held hostage by a couple of members. Those members stand behind empty arguments and individual interests, while delaying and seeking to strip bare any text that would pressure AlAssad to change his actions. That intransigence is even more shameful when we consider that at least one of those members continues to deliver weapons to Al-Assad.” US Ambassador Susan Rice, 4 February 2012 (S/PV.6711). “Yet some Council members argued that the draft resolution imposed regime change. It said no such thing. But in an attempt to reach consensus, we provided further assurances in the text. The same minority argued that the text could somehow be used to authorize military intervention. It did no such thing. It was a Chapter VI resolution. But in an attempt to reach consensus, we provided further assurances in the text. The same minority argued that very modest language expressing concern about weapons was somehow tantamount to an arms embargo. It was not. But we took it out. They said that mere mention of Arab League sanctions was tantamount to United Nations sanctions. It was not. But we took it out in an effort to reach consensus. The facts speak for themselves. There is nothing in this text that should have triggered a veto. We removed every possible excuse. The reality is that Russia and China have today made a choice to turn their backs on the Arab world and the support tyranny rather than the legitimate aspirations of the Syrian people. They have failed in their responsibility as permanent members of the Security Council, and they have done so on the most shameful of days of the Syrian killing machine’s three hundred days of oppression.” UK Ambassador Sir Mark Lyall-Grant, 4 February 2012 (S/PV.6711). “I had hoped not to have to go through this ghastly list. By 4 October 2011, repression in Syria had already claimed 3,000 lives and Russia and China vetoed the Council’s action for the first time (see S/PV.6627). By 4 February, 6,000 Syrians had been cut down by the regime, and Russia and China exercised their second veto on the Council’s action (see S/PV.6711). Today, 19 July, we now count 17,000 men, women and children dead. We mourn their memory alongside the Syrian people, and Russia and China have just exercised their veto of the Council’s action for the third time.” French Ambassador Gérard Araud 19 July 2012 (S/PV.6180). “It is to Russia and China’s shame that they have chosen to block efforts to achieve justice for the Syrian people. It is disgraceful that they have yet again vetoed the Security Council’s efforts to take action in response to the appalling human rights violations being committed every day in Syria. Russia and China will have to justify their behaviour, not only to those States and organizations, but to so many of the Syrian people who continue to suffer under Al-Assad’s brutal regime”. UK Ambassador, Sir Mark Lyall-Grant, 22 May 2014 (S/PV.7180). One can clearly see from these quotations that the response of the liberal states among the P5 was to frame the double veto as a shameful betrayal of the Syrian people. It should be noted, to be fair to these states, that this was not their starting position. They did, in other words, (at least from the public statements) seek consensus. As the statement from the UK Ambassador on the 4 February makes clear, those proposing the resolutions made concessions to reassure the Russian and Chinese by meeting their concerns. It may also be significant that the reference to R2P that appeared in the proposed resolution of 4 October 2011 was dropped from subsequent resolutions on this topic. 49 To argue that France, UK and US did not approach the deliberations in the right way would therefore be unfair. The reflexivist-inspired criticism, however, is this: by setting out to shame Russia and China, these liberal states (potentially) reinforced the view that there was only one appropriate way to meet the Security Council’s responsibility, and that in turn (potentially) reinforced the distrust that the Chinese and Russians were carrying over from the Libyan intervention. Informed by the insights of the reflexivist approach, Tim Dunne and Katharine Gelber note that ‘arguing matters’ to how R2P is understood and received. What is being suggested here is that there is a way in which states can responsibly argue. The manner in which an argument is offered is important for its ability to command consensus. This means three things: first, trying to persuade; second, being open to persuasion; and third, accepting that a failure to persuade is not always because a state has acted unreasonably. It may well be the case, for instance, that Russia’s Syria policy has been dictated by a desire to protect its naval base in Syria. But that does not exclude the possibility that the normative arguments it makes against regime change are unreasonable. Liberal interventionists regularly argue that interests and values merge. To be sure, the argument here is not that Russia was right to veto these specific resolutions. As noted, the majorities for the resolutions suggest Russia had lost the debate in the Security Council. The argument instead is that Russia may have had reasons for voting against the resolutions that were not necessarily unreasonable and did not necessarily demand the kind of response recommended by the conventional constructivist approach. The fact that China voted against this resolution reinforces this This is not insignificant. While Bellamy 2014a Bellamy 2014b can argue the Security Council has continued to reference R2P, these references tend to be where there is not a threat of military force for the purpose of externally imposed regime change. In the Syria situation there was, rightly or wrongly, a perception that this was possible. Hence, R2P became problematic. 49 point. It does not have a particular interest in seeing the Assad regime survive and might therefore be deemed to be voting alongside Russia for reasons that are not necessarily unreasonable. More to the point, even if these votes were shameful, the reflexive constructivist would question why the US, UK and France would risk alienating states like Russia and China – neither of whom are necessarily responsive to public opinion – by using the kind of language that appeared in the Security Council debate. There is a final point to add. The strategy of shaming Russia and China on the Security Council has not worked in the way conventional constructivism suggests. This might be expecting too much of a theory which is supported by examples demonstrating how the power to shame works over a much longer timeframe, such as the Helsinki process, or the response to the Rwandan genocide. But it is noticeable how the dominant narrative surrounding the Syrian crisis has shifted in ways that reflect what Russia and China were saying at its beginning. This became glaringly apparent in the summer of 2014 when the US began airstrikes against ISIL and the Obama administration was forced to clarify that the US was not colluding with the Assad regime against their common enemy. 50 Indeed, by the beginning of 2015 reports emerged that western capitals were coming round to the view that the Assad regime was part of the solution to a more pressing counter-terrorism problem, and others, including the Syrian opposition, were coming round to the view that the solution to the Syrian problem lay in Moscow. 51 This does not mean Russia and China were right in vetoing the resolutions. Events may have unfolded very differently had they taken a different approach and had the Security Council been united and able to act purposefully to end the violence. The fact, however, that western governments have been forced to shift narratives, and in ways that in some respects reflect what Russia and China have been saying about the region, is significant. It suggests that the reasons given for the vetos were not entirely unreasonable and it suggests the shaming strategy adopted by the US, UK and France was not entirely warranted. Conclusion The purpose of this paper has been to explore how constructivism can inform an ethic that can, in turn, be used to provide a normative assessment of the liberal state’s response to the Syrian crisis. There are two approaches to this question. One is to hyphenate constructivism e.g. liberal constructivism. Here constructivism is reduced to a method of studying change and progress toward a liberal world order. The justification of liberal values is contracted out to normative theorists. Another approach is to recognize that constructivism says something significant about the substantive character of a value and not merely the social and political process of change. Informed by Toni Erskine’s critique of recent attempts to identify a constructivist ethic this paper explore some implications of this latter approach. The key point is that constructivism recognizes the historical and social contingency of all moral knowledge and an acknowledgement that norms rest only on weak normative foundations. That, in the pragmatic tradition, 50 51 Gearan 2014 Barnard 2015 encourages a sense of fallibalism and openness to deliberation, including a willingness to be persuaded by reasonable argument. This emphasis on contingency problematizes the normative guidance that is implied by the conventional constructivist approach and its tendency to sees norms as social facts with fixed meanings. It stresses the importance of the critical or reflexivist view that the meaning of norms is in a consistent process or iteration and contestation, which opens up questions about the normativity or legitimacy of a norm. Drawing on Antje Wiener’s theory of contestation the paper argued that there is normative value in regularizing the process of contestation and making it inclusive of those who are impacted by the norm’s social power. The third step in argument was to apply this insight to assess the liberal state’s response to the Security Council deliberations on Syria. The application of reflexivist constructivism offers a nuanced assessment of liberal state behavior. One has to be conscious here of the possibility that China and particularly Russia were using the veto to construct enmity between the great powers, and this of course makes it virtually impossible for liberal states to act in ways that encourage consensus. Indeed, one might also argue (as I have done in other context) that the veto loses legitimacy when it is exercised in the face of an overwhelming majority (and 13 votes on a 15 state council surely counts as that). 52 The majority is a sign that Russia and China’s arguments failed to persuade and one can understand US, UK and French frustrations in this context. The argument here, however, is that the use of shaming language used by these states has failed in two ways: first, it did not change Russia and Chinese policy, and in fact events have seemingly forced a change in the western perception of approach to the crisis; and second, by following the conventional constructivist approach and calling Russian and Chinese positions shameful (even ‘disgusting’) the US, UK and France entrenched division in the Security Council. Because aspects of R2P rely on the Security Council being united this is potentially a regressive step and what that could possibly be avoided had a reflexivist, instead of conventional, constructivist ethic informed liberal state practice. References Acharya, Amitav. 2013. "The R2p and Norm Diffusion: Towards a Framework of Norm Circulation." 5: 466-79. Anonymous. 2014. "Number of Syrian Refugees Tops 3 Million as Insecurity Grows – Un Agency." UN News Centre, 29 August Badescu, Cristina G. 2011. Humanitarian Intervention and the Responsibility to Protect : Security and Human Rights New York: Routledge. Badescu, Cristina G., and Thomas G. Weiss. 2010. "Misrepresenting R2p and Advancing Norms: An Alternative Spiral?". International Studies Perspectives 11: 354-74. Barnard, Anne. 2015. "Syria Peace Hopes Dim Further as Opposition Rejects Moscow Talks." New York Times, 13 January. 52 See Ralph 2011 for an analysis of the ‘unreasonable veto’ in the 1999 Kosovo and 2003 Iraq crises. Barnett, Michael. 1999. "Culture, Strategy and Foreign Policy Change: Israel's Road to Oslo." European Journal of International Relations 5: 5-36. Bellamy, Alex J. 2014a. "A Death Foretold? Human Rights, Responsibility to Protect and the Persistent Politics of Power." Cooperation and Conflict. Bellamy, Alex J. 2014b. "From Tripoli to Damascus? Lesson Learning and the Implementation of the Responsibility to Protect." International Politics 51: 23-44. Booth, Ken. 1995. "Human Wrongs and International Relations." International Affairs (Royal Institute of International Affairs 1944-) 71: 103-26. ———. 1999. "Three Tyrannies " In Human Rights in Global Politics, eds. Tim Dunne and Nicholas Wheeler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 31-70. Bray, Daniel. 2013. "Pragmatic Ethics and the Will to Believe in Cosmopolitanism." International Theory 5: 446-76. Bukovansky, Mlada, Ian Clark, Richard Price, Christian Reus-Smit, and Nicholas Wheeler. 2012. Special Responsibilities. Global Problems and American Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cochran, Molly. 1999. Normative Theory in International Relations. A Pragmatic Approach. Edited by Steve Smith. Vol. 68, Cambridge Studies in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Contarino, Michael, Melinda Negron-Gonzales, and Kevin T. Mason. 2012. "The International Criminal Court and Consolidation of the Responsibility to Protect as an International Norm." Global Responsibility to Protect 4: 275-308. Deitelhoff, Nicole, and Harald Müller. 2005. "Theoretical Paradise – Empirically Lost? Arguing with Habermas." Review of International Studies 31: 167-79. Doty, Roxanne Lynn. 1997. "Aporia: A Critical Exploration of the Agent-Structure Problematique in International Relations Theory." European Journal of International Relations 3: 365-92. Epstein, C. 2012. "Stop Telling Us How to Behave: Socialization or Infantilization?". International Studies Perspectives 13: 135-45. Epstein, Charlotte. 2013. "Constructivism or the Eternal Return of Universals in International Relations. Why Returning to Language Is Vital to Prolonging the Owl's Flight." European Journal of International Relations 19: 499-519. Erskine, Toni. 2002. "'Citizen of Nowhere' or 'the Point Where Circles Intersect'? Impartialist and Embedded Cosmopolitanisms." Review of International Studies 28: 457-78. ———. 2008. Embedded Cosmopolitanism. Duties to Strangers and Enemies in a World of 'Dislocated Communities'. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 2012. "Whose Progress, Which Morals? Constructivism, Normative Ir Theory and the Limits and Possibilities of Studying Ethics in World Politics." International Theory 4: 449-68. Fierke, K.M. 2013. "Constructivism." In International Relations Theories. Discipline and Diversity, eds. Tim Dunne, Milja Kurki and Steve Smith, 3rd ed: Oxford University Press. 187-204. Finnemore, Martha , and Kathryn Sikkink. 1998. "International Norm Dynamics and Political Change." International Organization 52: 887-917. Gearan, Anne. 2014. "U.S. Rules out Coordinating with Assad on Airstrikes against Islamists in Syria." Washington Post, 26 August. Gurowitz, Amy. 2008. "Policy Hypocrisy or Political Compromise? Assessing the Morality of Us Policy Towards Undocumented Migrants." In Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics, ed. Richard Price. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hoffmann, Matthew J. 2009. "Is Constructivist Ethics an Oxymoron?". International Studies Review 11: 231-52. Hopf, Ted. 1998. "The Promise of Constructivism in International Relations Theory." International Security 23: 171-200. Hurd, Ian. 2008. "Constructivism." In The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, eds. Christian ReusSmit and Duncan Snidal. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Keck, Margaret, and Kathryn Sikkink. 1998. Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press. Knight, W. Andy. 2011. "The Development of the Responsibility to Protect – from Evolving Norm to Practice." Global Responsibility to Protect 3: 3-36. Liese, Andrea 2009. "Exceptional Necessity - How Liberal Democracies Contest the Prohibition of Torture and Ill-Treatment When Countering Terrorism ". Journal of International Law and International Relations 5: 17-48. Linklater, Andrew. 2001. "Citizenship, Humanity, and Cosmopolitan Harm Conventions." International Political Science Review 22: 261-77. Linklater, Andrew. 2011. The Problem of Harm in World Politics: Cambridge University Press. Lynch, Marc. 2008. "Lie to Me: Sanctions on Iraq, Moral Argument and the International Politics of Hypocrisy." In Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics, ed. Richard Price. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 165-96. Morris, Justin. 2013. "Libya and Syria: R2p and the Spectre of the Swinging Pendulum." International Affairs 89: 1265-83. Müller, Harald. 2004. "Arguing, Bargaining and All That: Communicative Action, Rationalist Theory and the Logic of Appropriateness in International Relations." European Journal of International Relations 10: 395-435. Price, Megan, Anita Gohdes, and Patrick Ball. 2014. "Updated Statistical Analysis of Documentation of Killings in the Syrian Arab Republic Commissioned by the Office of the Un High Commissioner for Human Rights." In Secondary Updated Statistical Analysis of Documentation of Killings in the Syrian Arab Republic Commissioned by the Office of the Un High Commissioner for Human Rights, ed Secondary ———. Reprint, Reprint. Price, Richard. 2008a. "The Ethics of Constructivism." In The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, eds. Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 2008b. "Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics." International Organization 62: 191-220. ———. 2008c. "Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics." In Moral Limit and Possibiltiy in World Politics, ed. Richard Price. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1-52. ———. 2008d. "Progress with a Price." In Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics, ed. Richard Price. Vol. 107, Cambridge Studies in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Proess. 281-304. Price, Richard M. 2012a. "Introduction." International Theory 4: 430-34. ———, ed. 2008e. Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics. Edited by Christian Reus-Smit and Nicholas Wheeler, Cambridge Studies in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ———. 2012b. "On Pragmatic and Principled Limits and Possibilities of Dialogue." International Theory 4: 477-92. Price, Richard, and Christian Reus-Smit. 1998. "Dangerous Liaisons? Critical International Theory and Constructivism." European Journal of International Relations 4: 259-94. Ralph, Jason. 2011. "After Chilcot: The ‘Doctrine of International Community’ and the Uk Decision to Invade Iraq." The British Journal of Politics & International Relations 13: 304-25. ———. 2014. "The Liberal State in International Society: Interpreting Recent British Foreign Policy." International Relations 28: 3-24. Ralph, Jason, and Adrian Gallagher. 2014. "Legitimacy Faultlines in International Society. The Responsibility to Protect and Prosecute after Libya.". Review of International Studies. Reus-Smit, Christian. 2008. "Constructivism and the Structure of Ethical Reasoning." In Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics, ed. Richard M. Price, Cambridge Studies in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 53-82. Rights, United Nations Office of the High Commissioner for Human. 2014. "7th Report of Commission of Inquiry on Syria." 12 February (published on 5 March) ed. Risse, Thomas. 2000. ""Let's Argue!": Communicative Action in World Politics." International Organization 54: 1-39. Shawki, Noha. 2011. "Responsibility to Protect: The Evolution of an International Norm." Global Responsibility to Protect 3: 172-96. Venzke, Ingo. 2009. "Legal Contestation About Enemy Combatants - on the Exercise of Power in Legal Interpretation,." Journal of International Law and International Relations 5: 155-84. Weber, Martin. 2014. "Between ‘Isses’ and ‘Oughts’: Ir Constructivism, Critical Theory, and the Challenge of Political Philosophy." European Journal of International Relations 20: 516-43. Welsh, Jennifer. 2014. "Implementing the Responsibility to Protect: Catalyzing Debate and Building Capacity'." In Implementation and World Politics. How International Norms Change Practice, eds. Alexander Betts and Phil Orchard. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Welsh, Jennifer M. 2013. "Norm Contestation and the Responsibility to Protect." Global Responsibility to Protect 5: 365-96. Wendt, Alexander 1995. "Constructing International Politics." International Security 20. Wiener, Antje. 2004. "Contested Compliance: Interventions on the Normative Structure of World Politics." European Journal of International Relations 10: 189-234. ———. 2009. "Enacting Meaning-in-Use: Qualitative Research on Norms and International Relations." Review of International Studies 35: 175-93. ———. 2014. A Theory of Contestation: Springer Berlin Heidelberg. Wiener, Antje 2008. The Invisible Constitution of World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wiener, Antje, and Uwe Puetter. 2009. "Quality of Norms Is What Actors Make of It Critical Constructivist Research on Norms." Journal of International Law and International Relations 5: 1-16. Zehfuss, Maja. 2001. "Constructivism and Identity: A Dangerous Liaison." European Journal of International Relations 7: 315-48.