ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS
Transcription
ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS
ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Peter Ireland Boston College March 17, 2015 These lecture notes by Peter Ireland are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommerical-ShareAlike 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0) License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/. 4 Measuring Risk and Risk Aversion A B C D E F Measuring Risk Aversion Interpreting the Measures of Risk Aversion Risk Premium and Certainty Equivalence Assessing the Level of Risk Aversion The Concept of Stochastic Dominance Mean Preserving Spreads Next: 5 Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions The Concept of Stochastic Dominance The concept of stochastic dominance allows us to make “preference-free” comparisons across risky cash flows, in the sense that if one asset exhibits stochastic dominance over another, it will be preferred by any investor no matter what his or her level of risk aversion. The Concept of Stochastic Dominance Consider two assets, with random payoffs Z1 and Z2 : Payoffs Probabilities for Z1 Probabilities for Z2 10 100 1000 0.40 0.60 0.00 0.40 0.40 0.20 There may be no state-by-state dominance, if the payoffs Z1 = 10 and Z2 = 100 can occur together and the payoffs Z1 = 100 and Z2 = 10 can occur together. The Concept of Stochastic Dominance Payoffs Probabilities for Z1 Probabilities for Z2 10 100 1000 0.40 0.60 0.00 0.40 0.40 0.20 Because E (Z1 ) = 64, σ(Z1 ) = 44, E (Z2 ) = 244, and σ(Z2 ) = 380, there is no mean-variance dominance either. The Concept of Stochastic Dominance Payoffs Probabilities for Z1 Probabilities for Z2 10 100 1000 0.40 0.60 0.00 0.40 0.40 0.20 But, intuitively, asset 2 “looks” better, because its distribution takes some of the probability of a payoff of 100 and “moves” that probability to the even higher payoff of 1000. Probability theory formalizes this notion, by saying that asset 2 exhibits first-order stochastic dominance over asset 1. The Concept of Stochastic Dominance Theorem Consider two assets with random payoffs Z1 and Z2 . Asset 2 displays first-order stochastic dominance over asset 1 if and only if E [u(Z2 )] ≥ E [u(Z1 )] for any nondecreasing Bernoulli utility function u. Note that this theorem only requires that investors have vN-M utility and that “more is preferred to less.” They do not even have to be risk-averse. The Concept of Stochastic Dominance First-order stochastic dominance is a weaker condition than state-by-state dominance, in that state-by-state dominance implies first-order stochastic dominance but first-order stochastic dominance does not necessarily imply state-by-state dominance. But first-order stochastic dominance remains quite a strong condition. Since an asset that displays first-order stochastic dominance over all others will be preferred by any investor with vN-M utility who prefers higher payoffs to lower payoffs, the price of such an asset is likely to be bid up until the dominance goes away. Mean Preserving Spreads Graphically, a mean preserving spread takes probability from the center of a distribution and shifts it to the tails. Mean Preserving Spreads Mathematically, one way of producing a mean preserving spread is to take one random variable X1 and define a second, X2 , by adding “noise” in the form of a third, zero-mean random variable Z : X2 = X1 + Z , where E (Z ) = 0. Mean Preserving Spreads As an example, suppose that 5 with probability 1/2 X1 = 2 with probability 1/2 +1 with probability 1/2 Z= −1 with probability 1/2 then 6 4 X2 = X1 + Z = 3 1 with with with with probability probability probability probability 1/4 1/4 1/4 1/4 E (X1 ) = E (X2 ) = 3.5, but if these are random payoffs, asset 2 seems riskier. Mean Preserving Spreads The following theorem relates the concept of a mean preserving spread to a weaker concept of second-order stochastic dominance. Theorem Let X1 and X2 , with E (X1 ) = E (X2 ), be random payoffs on two assets. Then the following two statements are equivalent: (i) X2 = X1 + Z for some random variable Z with E (Z ) = 0 and (ii) asset 1 displays second-order stochastic dominance over asset 2. Mean Preserving Spreads Theorem Consider two assets with random payoffs Z1 and Z2 . Asset 2 displays second-order stochastic dominance over asset 1 if and only if E [u(Z2 )] ≥ E [u(Z1 )] for any nondecreasing and concave Bernoulli utility function u. This theorem imply that any risk-averse investor with vN-M preferences will avoid “pure gambles,” in the form of assets with payoffs that simply add more randomness to the payoff of another asset. Mean Preserving Spreads Second-order stochastic dominance is a weaker condition than first-order stochastic dominance, in that first-order stochastic dominance implies second-order stochastic dominance but second-order stochastic dominance does not necessarily imply first-order stochastic dominance. But second-order stochastic dominance remains a strong condition. Since an asset that displays second-order stochastic dominance over all others will be preferred by any risk-averse investor with vN-M utility, the price of such an asset is likely to be bid up until the dominance goes away. 5 Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions A Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation B Portfolios, Risk Aversion, and Wealth Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation Let’s now put our framework of decision-making under uncertainty to use. Consider a risk-averse investor with vN-M expected utility who divides his or her initial wealth Y0 into an amount a allocated to a risky asset – say, the stock market – and an amount Y0 − a allocated to a safe asset – say, a bank account or a government bond. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation Y0 = initial wealth a = amount allocated to stocks ˜r = random return on stocks rf = risk-free return Y˜1 = terminal wealth Y˜1 = (1 + rf )(Y0 − a) + a(1 + ˜r ) = Y0 (1 + rf ) + a(˜r − rf ) Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation The investor chooses a to maximize expected utility: max E [u(Y˜1 )] = max E {u[Y0 (1 + rf ) + a(˜r − rf )]} a a If the investor is risk-averse, u is concave and the first-order condition for this unconstrained optimization problem, found by differentiating the objective function by the choice variable and equating to zero, is both a necessary and sufficient condition for the value a∗ of a that solves the problem. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation The investor’s problem is max E {u[Y0 (1 + rf ) + a(˜r − rf )]} a The first-order condition is E {u 0 [Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (˜r − rf )](˜r − rf )} = 0. Note: we are allowing the investor to sell stocks short (a∗ < 0) or to buy stocks on margin (a∗ > Y0 ) if he or she desires. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation Theorem If the Bernoulli utility function u is increasing and concave, then a∗ > 0 if and only if E (˜r ) > rf a∗ = 0 if and only if E (˜r ) = rf a∗ < 0 if and only if E (˜r ) < rf Thus, a risk-averse investor will always allocate at least some funds to the stock market if the expected return on stocks exceeds the risk-free rate. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation As an example, suppose u(Y ) = ln(Y ), as suggested by Daniel Bernoulli. Recall that for this utility function, u 0 (Y ) = 1/Y . Then assume that stock returns can either be good or bad: rG with probability π ˜r = rB with probability 1 − π where rG > rf > rB defines the “good” and “bad” states and πrG + (1 − π)rB > rf , so that E (˜r ) > rf and the investor will choose a∗ > 0. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation The first-order condition E {u 0 [Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (˜r − rf )](˜r − rf )} = 0 specializes to π(rG − rf ) (1 − π)(rB − rf ) + = 0. ∗ Y0 (1 + rf ) + a (rG − rf ) Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (rB − rf ) Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation (1 − π)(rB − rf ) π(rG − rf ) + =0 ∗ Y0 (1 + rf ) + a (rG − rf ) Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (rB − rf ) π(rG − rf )[Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (rB − rf )] = −(1 − π)(rB − rf )[Y0 (1 + rf ) + a∗ (rG − rf )] a∗ (rG − rf )(rB − rf ) = −Y0 (1 + rf )[π(rG − rf ) + (1 − π)(rB − rf )] Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation a∗ (rG − rf )(rB − rf ) = −Y0 (1 + rf )[π(rG − rf ) + (1 − π)(rB − rf )] implies a∗ (1 + rf )[π(rG − rf ) + (1 − π)(rB − rf )] =− , Y0 (rG − rf )(rB − rf ) which is positive, since rG > rf > rB and E (˜r ) − rf = π(rG − rf ) + (1 − π)(rB − rf ) > 0. Risk Aversion and Portfolio Allocation a∗ (1 + rf )[π(rG − rf ) + (1 − π)(rB − rf )] =− , Y0 (rG − rf )(rB − rf ) In this case, a∗ : Rises proportionally with Y0 . Increases as E (˜r ) − rf rises. Falls as rG and rB move father away from rf , holding E (˜r ) constant; that is, in response to a mean preserving spread.