ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS
Transcription
ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS
ECON 337901 FINANCIAL ECONOMICS Peter Ireland Boston College March 24, 2015 These lecture notes by Peter Ireland are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommerical-ShareAlike 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0) License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/. 6 Modern Portfolio Theory A B C D E F Generalizing the Portfolio Problem Justifying Mean-Variance Utility The Gains From Diversification The Efficient Frontier A Separation Theorem Strengths and Shortcomings of MPT Generalizing the Portfolio Problem We can elaborate on our previous portfolio problem max Eu[Y0 (1 + rf ) + a(˜r − rf )] a by considering N > 1 risky assets with returns (˜r1 , ˜r2 , . . . , ˜rN ): " # N X max Eu Y0 (1 + rf ) + ai (˜ri − rf ) a1 ,a2 ,...,aN i=1 Generalizing the Portfolio Problem It turns out to be convenient to re-express this problem in terms of the shares wi = ai /Y0 of initial wealth allocated to each asset. Since ai = wi Y0 : " # N X max Eu Y0 (1 + rf ) + ai (˜ri − rf ) a1 ,a2 ,...,aN i=1 is equivalent to " max w1 ,w2 ,...,wN Eu Y0 (1 + rf ) + N X i=1 # wi Y0 (˜ri − rf ) Generalizing the Portfolio Problem Modern Portfolio Theory examines the solution to this extended problem assuming that investors have mean-variance utility, that is, assuming that investors’ preferences can be represented by a trade-off between the mean (expected value) and variance of the N asset returns. MPT was developed by Harry Markowitz (US, b.1927, Nobel Prize 1990) in the early 1950s, the classic paper being his article “Portfolio Selection,” Journal of Finance Vol.7 (March 1952): pp.77-91. Generalizing the Portfolio Problem The mean-variance utility hypothesis seemed natural at the time the MPT first appeared, and it retains some intuitive appeal today. But viewed in the context of more recent developments in financial economics, particularly the development of vN-M expected utility theory, it now looks a bit peculiar. A first question for us, therefore, is: Under what conditions will investors have preferences over the means and variances of asset returns? Justifying Mean-Variance Utility If we start, as we did previously, by assuming an investor has preferences over terminal wealth Y˜ , potentially random because of randomness in the asset returns, described by a vN-M expected utility function E [u(Y˜ )] we can write Y˜ = E (Y˜ ) + [Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] and interpret the portfolio problem as a trade-off between the expected payoff E (Y˜ ) and the size of the “bet” [Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] Justifying Mean-Variance Utility With this interpretation in mind, consider a second-order Taylor approximation of the Bernoulli utility function u once the outcome [Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] of the bet is known: u(Y˜ ) ≈ u[E (Y˜ )] + u 0 [E (Y˜ )][Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] 1 + u 00 [E (Y˜ )][Y˜ − E (Y˜ )]2 2 Justifying Mean-Variance Utility u(Y˜ ) ≈ u[E (Y˜ )] + u 0 [E (Y˜ )][Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] 1 + u 00 [E (Y˜ )][Y˜ − E (Y˜ )]2 2 Now go back to the beginning of the period, before the outcome of the bet is known, and take expectations to obtain 1 E [u(Y˜ )] ≈ u[E (Y˜ )] + u 00 [E (Y˜ )]σ 2 (Y˜ ) 2 since E [Y˜ − E (Y˜ )] = 0 and E {[Y˜ − E (Y˜ )]2 } = σ 2 (Y˜ ) Justifying Mean-Variance Utility 1 E [u(Y˜ )] ≈ u[E (Y˜ )] + u 00 [E (Y˜ )]σ 2 (Y˜ ) 2 The right-hand side of this expression is in the desired form: if u is increasing, it rewards higher mean returns and if u is concave, it penalizes higher variance in returns. So one possible justification for mean-variance utility is to assume that the size of the portfolio bet Y˜ − E (Y˜ ) is small enough to make this Taylor approximation a good one. But is it safe to assume that portfolio bets are small? Justifying Mean-Variance Utility A second possibility is to assume that the Bernoulli utility function is quadratic, with u(Y ) = a + bY + cY 2 , with b > 0 and c < 0. Then u 0 (Y ) = b + 2cY and u 00 (Y ) = 2c so that u 000 (Y ) = 0 and all higher-order derivatives are zero as well. In this case, the second-order Taylor approximation holds exactly. Justifying Mean-Variance Utility Note, however, that for a quadratic utility function RA (Y ) = − u 00 (Y ) 2c = − u 0 (Y ) b + 2cY which is increasing in Y . Hence, quadratic utility has the undesirable implication that the amount of wealth allocated to risky investments declines when wealth increases. Justifying Mean-Variance Utility Fortunately, there is a result from probability theory: if Y˜ is normally distributed with mean µY = E (Y˜ ) and standard deviation σY = {E [Y˜ − E (Y˜ )]2 }1/2 then the expectation of any function of Y˜ can be written as a function of µY and σY . Hence, in particular, there exists a function v such that Eu(Y˜ ) = v (µY , σY ) Justifying Mean-Variance Utility The result follows from a more basic property of the normal distribution: its location and shape is described completely by its mean and variance. Justifying Mean-Variance Utility If Y˜ is normally distributed, there exists a function v such that Eu(Y˜ ) = v (µY , σY ). Moreover, if Y˜ is normally distributed and 1. u is increasing, then v is increasing in µY 2. u is concave, then v is decreasing in σY 3. u is concave, then indifference curves defined over µY and σY are convex Justifying Mean-Variance Utility Since µY is a “good” and σY is a “bad,” indifference curves slope up. But if u is concave, these indifference curves will still be convex. Justifying Mean-Variance Utility Problems with the normality assumption: 1. Returns on assets like options are highly non-normal. 2. Departures from normality, including skewness (asymmetry) and excess kurtosis (“fat tails”) can be detected in returns for both individual stocks and stock indices. Justifying Mean-Variance Utility The mean-variance utility hypothesis is intuitively appealing and can be justified with reference to vN-M expected utility theory under various additional assumptions. Still, it’s important to recognize its limitations: you probably wouldn’t want to use it to design sophisticated investment strategies that involve very large risks or make use of options and you probably wouldn’t want to use it to study how portfolio strategies or risk-taking behavior changes with wealth. The Gains From Diversification One of the most important lessons that we can take from modern portfolio theory involves the gains from diversification. To see where these gains come from, consider forming a portfolio from two risky assets: ˜r1 , ˜r2 = random returns µ1 , µ2 = expected returns σ1 , σ2 = standard deviations Assume µ1 > µ2 and σ1 > σ2 to create a trade-off between expected return and risk. The Gains From Diversification If w is the fraction of initial wealth allocated to asset 1 and 1 − w is the fraction of initial wealth allocated to asset 2, the random return ˜rP on the portfolio is ˜rP = w˜r1 + (1 − w )˜r2 and the expected return µP on the portfolio is µP = E [w˜r1 + (1 − w )˜r2 ] = wE (˜r1 ) + (1 − w )E (˜r2 ) = w µ1 + (1 − w )µ2 The Gains From Diversification µP = w µ1 + (1 − w )µ2 The expected return on the portfolio is a weighted average of the expected returns on the individual assets. Since µ1 > µ2 , µP can range from µ2 up to µ1 as w increases from zero to one. Even higher (or lower) expected returns are possible if short selling is allowed.