Presentation #5 Kyle Peters - Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture
Transcription
Presentation #5 Kyle Peters - Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture
Kyle Peters University of Chicago Producing the Self-Itself 本発表では西田幾多郎の哲学を通じて芸術創作の理論を検討する。「個人作者」 と「作者の死」の言説に代わるものとして、芸術創作のオルタナティブな理論を提 出する。「作者」を歴史的、唯物的に形成されたものとする構造主義とポスト構造 主義の展開に伴い、多くのフェミニズムやポストコロニアリズムの研究者は主観的 主体(エージェンシー)の欠如や(ポスト)構造主義における芸術創作理論の客観 的条件の優先を問題視している。とりわけ、主体の存在を否定し客観性を優先する 言説において女性の主観や植民化された主観が軽視されるとして批判した。しかし、 この批判は近代の自主的、非歴史的、不変な「個人作者」という概念への回帰を求 めているわけではなく、主観と客観の相対的な関係によって形成された理論、すな わち、均衡のとれた芸術創作理論を求めている。 これらの妥当性を踏まえた上で、本発表では、まず、西田の 1925 年の「表現作用」 の主客対立に内在する根本的な作用としての「自己自身」という概念を用いる。芸 術創作において自己自身の不定型的構造は主観と客観という区分を超え、多方面に 溶解し、拡大すると主張する。次に、西田の「行為的直感の立場」をはじめとして、 「論理と生命」や「歴史的形成作用としての芸術創作」などのプロセスの枠組みを 参照した上で、芸術作品とその創作過程における主体の多元的様相を結びつける。 歴史的世界による限定の中にありながらも、芸術品の創造を通して自己自身が新た に創出される。なぜかというと、作品自体が自己限定を創造的に再構築し、再形成 し、再編成するからだ。 Reconceptualizing the Artist within an Ontology of Production This presentation uses the work of Nishida Kitarō 1 (1870-1945) to articulate an account of artistic agency that stands as an alternative to those discourses built around either the autonomy of the “Individual” or the “death of the author” [la mort de l'auteur]. 2 With the ascension and subsequent dominance of those structuralist and post-structuralist trends which situate the author as the product of historically and materially determined conditions, many feminist and post-colonial scholars have expressed concerns over the lack of subjective agency, and thus about the unchallenged primacy granted to objective conditions in these accounts of artistic production. In particular, they have questioned the incapacitation of both the female and the colonized subject in these discourses. But rather than slipping back into the modern conception of the author as 1 All Nishida citations refer to the 2002 – 2009 release of The Complete Works of Nishida Kitarō. Nishida, Kitarō. Shinpan Nishida Kitarō Zenshū, (New NKZ), Vol. 1-24, (Tokyo: Iwanami Bunko, 2002-2009). 2 Barthes, Roland. “La Mort de l'auteur,” In Œuvres completes (Complete Works), Vol. 2, (Paris: Seuil, 19661973), pp.491-495. English: Barthes, Roland, “The Death of the Author,” In Image-Music-Text, Trans. Stephen Heath, (New York: Hill and Wang, 1978). Written in 1967, but not published until 1968. Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 1 Individual, a notion which positions authorial output according to an autonomous, stable, and historically invariant essence, these scholars have called for a more balanced account of artistic production that is sensitive to the interrelationship between subjective and objective processes. Recognizing the legitimacy of these concerns, this presentation uses the notion of the “self-itself” [jiko jishin], as an act underlying the subject-object duality articulated in Nishida’s middle period essay “Expressive Activity” [Hyōgen sayō], to argue that the fluidity of the self-itself melts into manifold positions in artistic production, thereby decentering artistic agency across a multitude of positions and diffusing artistic production across the continuum of subjectivity and objectivity. 3 Next, using the processual framework articulated in his late-middle period essays “The Standpoint of Active-Intuition” [Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba], “Logic and Life” [Ronri to seimei], and “Artistic Production as a Historically Forming Activity” [Rekishiteki keiseisayō toshiteno geijutsuteki sōsaku], it links the work of art to the manifold positions of the processual subject, claiming that the unfolding of the self-itself is creatively produced through the novelty of the work of art as it reallocates, reorganizes, and redeploys the present within the horizons delimited by the historical body. Primacy of the Objective Following the emergence of structural linguistics in the mid-1950s, the status of the subject vis-àvis knowledge was radically altered, and the new goal of the human sciences was “not to constitute man, but to dissolve him.” 4 Accompanying notions came under increased scrutiny, and by the late 1960s the author had been pronounced dead and their regulative role in circulating discourses of power had been made clear. While Roland Barthes first made such a pronouncement in 1968 with “The Death of the Author” [La Mort de l'auteur], two works published soon after by Michel Foucault, “What is an Author?” [Qu'est-ce qu'un auteur?] and “The Discourse on Language” [L 'Ordre du discours], provide a more nuanced interpretation of the relationship between language, discourse, and thought. Although the first of these two essays restricts itself to the singular relationship between author and text, the second deals more numerously with those internal and external constraints which function to restrict the horizons structuring discourse. In both works, Foucault replies to criticisms that The Order of Things [Les Mots et les choses] sublated complex authorial differences between Buffon, Linnaeus, Darwin, and Ricardo into an uncritically broad èpistême. He responds by functionalizing the figure of the author. Foucault claims that the author works alongside commentary and discipline as an internal constraint, governing the circulation of discourse, and thereby functioning as a disciplinary power which serves to delimit and define the organization of knowledge therein. Foucault cites 18th century copyright-law as a central moment in the figuration of the author, in the process articulating the way in which the modern author is radically different from their operation as an “index of truthfulness” in earlier times. 5 Owing to such a process, the modern author is imbued with juridical powers, standing as the unified principle at the origin of the text, and thus as the ultimate and final index. Through their juridical status, the figure of the author ideologically functions to shape, limit, prohibit, and constitute the horizon of signification, thus impeding free(r) circulation of discourse and 3 Hall, Stuart. “Who Needs Identity?,” in Questions Concerning Cultural Identity, (Londong: Sage, 1996), p.4. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. The Savage Mind, (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1966). 5 Krauss, Rosalind. “Who Comes After the Subject?” In The Life & the Work: Art and Biography. (Los Angeles, 2007). 4 2 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself proliferation of meaning. 6 Foucault: “The author’s name manifests the appearance of a certain discursive set and indicates the status of this discourse within a society and a culture... it is located in the break that founds a certain discursive construct and its very particular mode of being.” 7 This means that the author function is neither uniform nor constant. 8 It follows that while certain discourses are endowed with the author function, other discourses are not constrained in this manner. Foucault makes it clear, however, that the author-figure is particularly authoritative in the secondary discourse surrounding the literary arts, where they operate as the final principle governing classification, interpretation, and commentary. 9 Establishing a cause and effect relationship between author and the text, literary commentators are forced to submit the text, and their interpretations thereof, to the life of the author, forcing the latter to serve as the legislator of the text’s significance and meaning. Such a view extends to the visual arts as well, where Foucault cites the radically different demands imposed on the artist in the commentaries of the Renaissance and those of modernity. While Giorgio Vasari and other art historians of the Renaissance demand that the artist in some respects assert their unicity from the larger population, commentaries of the modern era require the biography to authenticate the truthfulness of the artwork. 10 Dismissing the idea that discourse will be liberated from any system of constraint with the disappearance of the author figure, Foucault stresses that that this figure operates as a historically variable function, and thus that texts can be organized and arranged according to other modes of governance. In envisioning the disappearance (or death) of the Individuality of the authorial figure, Foucault, like Barthes, shifts the author to the fringes of discourse in the effort to minimize their textual occlusion. 11 With the author restricted to this liminal space, the writing essentially acts as a conduit by which discourse organizes and constitutes itself, largely free of any form of subjective intervention. 12 Here, textual interpretation focuses on the modes, uses, and circulation of discourse, as well as the subjects that it makes possible. 13 Following Foucault, the secondary discourses in philosophy, literary criticism, and to a lesser extent 14 art history have called into question the primacy of the author as either the origin of a text or the locus out of which an utterly original work emerged. As such, these discourses have worked to distance scholarship from the construction of the author, and its intimate correspondence with the unicity and individuality of their style. In doing so, they treat the text as an assemblage of significations from which they can elicit those disciplinary forms that govern the organization and circulation of discourse. It is this shift that has worried certain feminist and post-colonial scholars, expressing concerns over the lack of subjective agency, and thus about the unchallenged primacy 6 Foucalt, Michel. “Qu'est-ce qu'un auteur?,” Bulletin de la Sociètè Française de philosohie 63 (JulySeptember, 1969); English: “What is an Author?,” In Michel Foucault: Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology, ed. James Faubion, (New York: The New Press, 1998), p.221. It was originally delivered as a lecture to the Sociètè Française de philosohie in 1969, with a modified form given in the United States the following year. 7 Ibid. p.211 8 Ibid. 9 Ibid. p.212 10 Foucault, Michel. Le gouvernement de soi et des autres: le courage de la vèritè (1984), (Unpublished Transcript, prepared by Michael Behrent, Feb. 29), p.60. 11 Foucault. “What is an Author?,” p.207. 12 cf. Burke, Seán. The Death and Return of the Author: Criticism and Subjectivity in Barthes, Foucault, and Derrida, (Edinburgh University Press, 2010), p.9. 13 Foucault. “What is an Author?,” p.222. 14 Sousloff, Catherine. The Absolute Artist, (University of Minessota Press, 1997), p.142. Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 3 granted to objective conditions in these accounts of artistic production. In line with these concerns, we should investigate whether the absolute primacy of the objective is the necessary correlation of the author’s death. Beyond Primacy: Artistic Production and the Act But rather than simply ignoring the death of the author, this presentation recognizes the legitimacy of the Foucauldian concerns regarding the privileging of authorship. This means that, rather than returning to a concept of authorship based on the modern conception of an autonomous, ahistorical, and invariant conception of the Individual, it seeks a third approach, one which takes into account the concerns voiced on both sides of the debate. That is, insofar as the primacy of either subjectivity or objectivity provides less than suitable explanatory alternatives, this presentation works to develop a theory formed in the inter-relationship between subjective and objective. One effective way to do this is to challenge the bifurcation establishing the opposition between these two terms. In Nishida’s middle-period works, both the standpoint of the conscious self and that of the objective mind, as well as their attending divisions between knower and known, subjective and objective, are born out of a more primordial, holistic act which stands as the one true reality. On a theoretical level, Nishida presents this conception of the act in contradistinction to change, which he claims, following the Aristotelian notion of substance, requires that there is something self-identical that persists. On the definitional level, the act is differentiated from change insofar as it can change of itself [mizukara henka suru mono], with the act standing as a subset of change, distinct inasmuch as it has an intentional structure and an underlying connection between cause and effect. But going beyond theory, Nishida’s middle-period work provides a quasiphenomenological formulation of these notions of act and change, claiming that in order for a thing to act or change, there must be a more fundamental “knowing of knowing” [shiru koto o shiru] at its base. This is the first-step of an important shift away from, or rather beneath and beyond, the egocentricity of the Cartesian cogito and the Kantian transcendental subject. Inasmuch as it is tacitly aware of its first-order directedness, the content of this knowing of knowing noetically transcends the object of knowing, and thus goes to a more primordial dimension of experience that lies beneath judgmental knowledge. This knowing of knowing is therefore a second-order reflexive activity accompanying a first-order intentional act, and thus contains additional content excluded in the first-order directedness of the conscious self. Insofar as this primordial dimension of experience is more robust in terms of content, it lacks the delineated and defined structure that marks judgmental acts of knowledge. That is, in contrast to the unadulterated, rich unity of this fundamental dimension of experience, higher-order judgments are more refined, and thus marked by a clearer noetic-noematic structure. Nishida uses several different terms to refer to this more primordial dimension of experience, with the self-itself and the “supraconscious self” [chōishikitekijiko] standing as two notable examples used to elucidate and differentiate this more fundamental realm from other conceptions of self. Regardless of which lexicon he employs, Nishida’s middle-period work claims that this more basic dimension is presented through “intuition” [chokkan]. Intuition “negates the self” [jiki hitei] such that the details of the world are vividly presented to the self-itself, without it being demarcated into the conscious self [ishiki jiko], something like an isolated cogito. As such, he posits a supraconscious realm beneath the subject-object bifurcation structuring the conscious self, articulating this primordial level as an experiential base out of which the ego of the conscious self, judgment, and 4 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself other higher-order thinking develops. It is not that judgmental knowledge of objects merely drops out of experience in this lower level, but rather that this dimension is proto-judgmental, thus lacking the subject-object duality marking higher-order thinking. In this more fundamental order of experience the self has both proto-judgmental knowledge of objects and intuitive knowledge of itself as intentional, as directed toward objects. Neither the conscious self nor the object completely drops from experience in this more basic level; instead the co-constitution of self and object comes to the fore. Our intuition of this more fundamental dimension of experience where there is no division between knower and known, perceiver and perceived, is deemed “self-awareness” [jikaku] by Nishida. It follows that in self-awareness there is no distinction between subjective and the objective, and there is thus a supraconscious unified act at the base of our self-awareness upon which the conscious self is established. Nishida connects these more primordial dimensions of experience to artistic production, claiming that creativity is born out of the act, as the latter is neither created nor creates. In other words, the act is the substrate out of which creative activity emerges. 15Artistic creation, it follows, cannot be a subjective function by which ideas, emotions, and sentiments are manifested from the standpoint of the conscious self. 16 Nishida challenges the everyday assumption that there exists a causal relation between the intention of the artist, the meaning of the work of art, and the emotion that it incites in the spectator. Neither can artistic creation be an objective function by which one creatively operates from the standpoint of the unchanging objective mind [kyakkanteki seishin], an idea that he associates with certain German idealist thinkers. 17 For Nishida, both the standpoints of the conscious self and the objective mind are born out of a more fundamental act which stands as the one true reality. This one true reality is the source of creativity, and thus it is the source of artistic production. In creating a work of art, the artist transcends both the subjective position of our conscious self and the objective position of the objective mind thereby operating from the more primordial standpoint of the supraconscious act. Nishida: In expressive activity, the center of consciousness transitions from the conscious self to the supraconscious self, and so-called conscious activity, on the other hand, becomes a shadowy image reflected onto the body. If we are able to think of language in the above manner, then we should probably say that art is an expression in its most complete sense…the artist does not create insofar as he possesses eyes and hands, but rather they create because they take part in the concept. Inasmuch as the artist submerges the subjectivity of the self within objectivity, they intentionally act. 18 From the standpoint of this supraconscious unified act, Nishida claims that the subject does not bear the content of the work of art, but rather the objective presences itself, and thus subjectivity is submerged into objectivity in artistic production. This is not an endorsement of the objective mind discussed above, but rather it is the recognition that when subjectivity is born, the objective is objectified as objective for that subjectivity. Nishida often refers to the “objective qua subjective” [kyakkan soku shukan] and the “subjective qua objective” [shukan soku kyakkan], arguing that without the subjective there is no objective. His point is that when one submerges the subjective self 15 Nishida. “Hyōgen sayō,” New NKZ, Vol.3, pp.371-372. Originally published in 1925. Ibid. p.377. 17 Ibid. p.378. 18 Ibid. p.377. 16 Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 5 into the objective, both subjectivity and objectivity drop and they create from the supraconscious self, the one true reality as action. But a concern presents itself: has Nishida really rejected the primacy of objective conditions? And this concern is followed by another one: has Nishida simply substituted the notion of the act for objectivity? Combining the two concerns: has Nishida merely replaced one hegemonic determining force with another, once again thwarting artistic agency and individual expression? If so, the artist does not create in Nishida, but rather the act creates through the artist, reducing the artist to a tool without volition, a mere means for expression. To properly consider this point, however, it becomes necessary to clarify our conception of artistic agency. For, as mentioned above, we should not equate our conception of agency with that of Individuality, and thus we should not require Nishida to provide us with an ahistorical, invariant, and utterly autonomous conception of agency. To do so would be to dismiss the Foucauldian concerns discussed above and, moreover, to place an unfair burden upon Nishida. In the above textual excerpt, Nishida clarifies that the “so-called self” [iwayuru jiko] becomes a shadowy image cast upon the body in artistic expression, and thus stresses that the self-itself is not to be identified with the self as it appears in higher-order, intentionally directed experience. For Nishida, it is a mistake to equate higher-order judgment with the self because, in fact, this is not our primordial mode of functioning in the world. The so-called self is a highly abstract dimension of experience, which, insofar as it is highly structured, lacks the unadulterated bounty of original experience. To limit agency to higher-order judgment would be to make the reification fallacy, and thus to mistake those abstract dimensions of experience as the most concrete and primordial. In the lexicon of Nishida’s earlier work, it would be to ignore the fundamentality of “pure experience” [jun’sui keiken] and posit those higher-order dimensions of experience as more basic. Insofar as the self-itself exists at the more primordial level of the act, and thus prior to the subject-object split, we should locate agency prior to the emergence of the subject, in the supraconscious level of the selfitself. In this more primordial state, the notions of autonomous subjectivity and hegemonic objectivity are deconstructed, articulating both a less autonomous and less determined conception of artistic agency. This allows for a more dynamic conception of the artist, free from both hegemonic objectivity and autonomous subjectivity. Here, the fluidity of this supraconscious realm allows the self-itself to create art from manifold positions beyond that which is entailed in the subjectivity of Individuality. As such, artistic agency is decentered across a multitude of practices and positions, and artistic production is always diffused across the continuum of subjectivity and objectivity. But at this point our creeping concern once again arises: has Nishida’s account of the self-itself really taken into account the objective dimensions structuring artistic production? And further: has the Foucauldian notion of discursive events dropped in our discussion, leading to a largely ahistorical account of objective forces? Synthesizing in the question: is Nishida’s account of artistic agency ahistorical? Beyond Primacy: Artistic Production and Active-Intuition In order to adequately deal with these concerns, we must refer to Nishida’s late-period works, those essays published after the second volume of Fundamental Problems of Philosophy: The Dialectical World [Tetsugaku no konpon mondai (Benshōhōteki sekai)] in late 1934. In these works, Nishida employs an explicitly historical framework in his discussions of creativity, working to strike a balance between subjectivity, agency, the historical world, and what is now called discourse through 6 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself his concept of “negation” [hitei], or rather, through “negation qua affirmation” [hitei soku kōtei] and “affirmation qua negation” [kōtei soku hitei]. This deeply historical yet creative account structures his formulation of aesthetics, and thus he emphasizes the fundamentality of the historical ground in his discussions of the artistic subject at the same time that he emphasizes the importance of the creative subject in his discussions of art historical trends. The investigation into the nature of subjectivity, as seen above in “Expressive Activity,” functioned prominently in nearly all of Nishida’s work since an Inquiry into the Good [Zen no kenkyū]. Nishida’s later works continue this investigation from a historical standpoint, and as Itabashi Yujin notes, work to analyze the creative nature of the self through its basis in historical reality. 19 This is not to say, however, that Nishida simply embraces a rectilinear conception of time, which conceives of the historical past as a stream which determines the present into the future. Instead, Nishida emphasizes the dynamic “self-determination” [jiko gentei] of the present from the “historical world” [rekishiteki sekai]. The historical world functions not merely as the storehouse of past experience, but is also integrated into the present in its movement of self-formation. He articulates this movement as an irreversible, sequential transition of moments moving “from the made to the making” [tsukuraretamono kara tsukurumono e], in which the present self-determines itself, affirming itself through its negation of the historical past. Taking seriously the Marxist critiques of his students Miki Kiyoshi (1897-1945) and Tosaka Jun (1900-1945), Nishida claims that the selfdetermination of the present is only possible as a historically and materially determined phenomenon, and thus only insofar as it is concretized in the “historical body” [rekishiteki shintai]. It follows that the notions of history and body are inextricably linked such that whenever Nishida refers to the body in his later works, he is always referring to the historical body, which is such when it is inscribed by the historical world. 20 This notion of the self-determination of the present in its negation of the historical body functions as both “temporal-spatial and spatial-temporal” [jikanteki-kūkanteki, kūkantekijikanteki]. 21 The body functions as a useful starting point in articulating the spatial dimensions of Nishida’s analysis insofar as it operates as a common space that articulates itself across both subject and object, making clear the inter-connection between these two poles and functioning beyond the active-passive division, and thus the subject-world dichotomy. In his writings on the body, Nishida employs the notion of “active-intuition” [kōiteki chokkan] using this term to expand on his middle period analysis of the supraconscious self as the locus of self-world, subject-object relationality. Active-intuition operates, to use James Heisig’s expressions, as a fundamental inter-active, interintuitive relationality, 22 functioning as the condition of the possibility for the binary between active and passive, and thereby further making possible both an active subject grasping and molding objects in the world and an intuited object in which the subject becomes passive in the face of objects in the world. But against the traditional dichotomous conception, in which passivity is articulated as belonging to and manipulable for activity, in active-intuition my activity necessarily entails the activity of the thing, and the activity of the thing necessarily entails my activity. Active19 Itabashi, Yujin. Rekishiteki genjitsu to nishida kitarō tetsugaku, (Hōsei University Press, 2008), p.17. Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” New NKZ, Vol.7, p.134. Originally published in 1935. 21 Nishida. “Jissen to taishō ninshiki: Rekishteki sekai ni oite no ninshiki no tachiba,” New NKZ, Vol. 8, p.129. Originally published in 1937. 22 Heisig, James. Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School, (University of Hawaii Press, 2001), p.55. 20 Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 7 intuition prioritizes neither subject nor object, and therefore refuses the fundamentality of any form of unidirectionality. Instead, the world flows against the subject and the subject flows against the world. This means that action is always being acted upon, a bidirectional activity in which we form and determine objects as we are formed and determined by objects. As such, Nishida emphasizes mutual mediation, the fact that it is only in and through their connection with the other that each expresses itself as itself. Our primordial mode of being in the world lies in mutual mediation, in the locus of action-acted, forming-formed. Insofar as the self-expression of both the subject and world are active qua passive, passive qua active, they stand together as a whole prior to any division, with the primordial connectedness of active-intuition functioning as the transcendental condition for any possible subject-object, self-world relation. Thus, on the most primordial level there is an activeintuitive relationality structuring the “dialectical self-identity” [jiko dōitsu] of the many and the one. But this topos of connectivity is not restricted to “actual existing space” [jistsuzaiteki kūkan], and we must keep in mind that the body is always concretized as the historical body in these later works. It follows that dialectical self-identity also functions on the temporal plane, and therefore that in active-intuition “actual existing space envelopes the temporal.” 23 On the spatial-temporal [kūkanteki jikan] level, active-intuition unifies each object into a collective movement of self-determination of the present in the sequential transition from the made to the making. In Nishida’s philosophy, at the same time that subject and object are spatially situated as fundamentally both unified and independent, they are also temporally singular yet connected into a dynamic whole. As the many instantly determine themselves in the move to the making, the whole simultaneously determines itself, uniting the singular into a new totality. As stated above, this is not a reduction of the singular into the collective, but rather the simultaneous recognition of singularity and unity, of many and one. This temporal movement takes place within actual space, which functions as “the intermediary which mutually correlates independent objects.” Thus on the spatial-temporal level, we have the “contradictory identification of the many and the one” [ta to ichi to ga mujunteki jikodōitsu]. But Nishida’s analysis is not merely spatial, nor merely spatial-temporal, and thus he does not prioritize spatiality. Rather, his analysis also proceeds from the other direction, with active-intuition being articulated from the temporal-spatial [jikanteki kūkan] standpoint. As discussed above, Nishida articulates history as a sequential transition of successive moments in the movement from the made to the making. Despite history operating as the hallmark of his later work, the radicality of this view, and thus its difference from the rectilinear conception of time, comes to the fore through its emphasis on the present. Privileging the “absolute present” [zettai no genzai] in his analysis, Nishida claims that the present moment creatively unfolds as self-determination, a diffusion [kakusan] and dispersion [sanran] of novelty in the present moment. This is possible inasmuch as active-intuition is the “affirmation of absolute negation” [zettai hitei no kōtei], and thus insofar as the absolute present unfolds and determines itself by negating and transcending the past, thereby affirming itself into the present moment. This movement is termed absolute insofar as this creative diffusion is conditioned by the negation of the past, and thus of the rectilinear conception of time. This movements is termed a diffusion insofar as it is an unfolding of the one into the many within the framework of the contradictory identity of opposites. The disconnected, singular moment arranges the scattered many into a unified movement of self-determination in the transition from the made to the making, while simultaneously negating this unity, dispersing this unity into the many, thereby crystallizing the 23 Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.162. 8 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself contradictory identity of the many and the one as the “perishing and becoming of each moment.” 24 Finally, this is termed creative insofar as this negation of the present moment into the future allows for a novel unfolding of the present moment. 25 Despite perishing and becoming in each moment, the present moment is not completely isolated from past and future. In fact, it is quite the opposite, as Nishida interprets historical formation as a “continuity of discontinuity” [hirenzonku no renzoku] and thus stresses the “simultaneous existence” [dōji sonzai] of past and future in the present moment. 26 But Nishida does not merely collapse past and future into the present, a concern of his colleague Tanabe Hajime (1889-1962); rather, he preserves the distinct temporal modalities of past, present, and future, yet articulates them into the present moment through the notion of the “eternal now” [eien no ima]. Nishida: “when I say that things are historically formed as the self-determination of the eternal now, in other words to say that things are actively seen, it is not to say that things appear by chance.” 27 Each moment is enveloped by the eternal now. This means that, if we formulate the determination of the instant according to a two-dimensional coordinate system, and conceive of it as a horizontal movement from the made to the making, then the eternal now stands vertical, making robust what would otherwise be a flat, linear unfolding. 28 This vertical expansion allows for two movements. First, in this upward expansion of the horizontal present moment, the eternal now undercuts any universal standpoint for temporality, dispersing the present moment into the many, and thus into a multitude of present moments, of temporal movements. This entails that, as Ishida Masato notes, “no perspective fathoms the ‘absolute depth’ of the past—there is no universal method to determine whether a past occasion belongs to a relatively ‘immediate’ past or a ‘remote’ past.” 29 Second, past and future are integrated into the determinative-forming of the many present moments through this vertical axis. This means that the historical body, which as mentioned above functions as the storehouse of the past, is integrated into the present through the eternal now. In being integrated into the present, the historical body functions alongside future possibilities to constrain the horizons structuring the self-determination of the instant. As Jacynthe Tremblay remarks, “the present thus appears as the center in which the past has already passed and simultaneously has not yet passed, and in which the future has not yet arrived, although it appears there already.” 30 Thus as the present moment becomes, affirming itself into and then negating itself out of existence, it perishes into the past. As it sinks into the past through the movement of negation, the modified historical body upon which the past is inscribed conditions the simultaneous selfdetermination of the present, thereby structuring the new formation of the present. This selfdetermination of the present is the production of subjectivity qua objectivity, and this means that 24 Nishida. Tetsugaku no konpon mondai (Benshōhōteki sekai), New NKZ, Vol. 6, p.250. Originally published in 1934. 25 There are degrees of novelty, however, and this will be discussed through the notions of active and passive habits below. 26 Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.162. 27 Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.201. 28 Nishida himself puts it in terms of such a two-dimensional coordinate system. cf. Nishida, “Jikaku ni tsuite,” New NKZ, Vol.9, p.483. Originally published in 1943. 29 Ishida, Masato. “The Sense of Symmetry: Comparative Reflections on Whitehead, Nishida, and Dōgen,” In Process Studies, Vol.43, No.1, p.11. 30 Tremblay, Jacynthe. “Hidden Aspects of Temporality from Nishida to Watsuji,” In Essays in Japanese Philosophy, (Nagano: Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture, 2008), p.168. Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 9 the historical body, in its integration into the present, operates as a discursive constraint. As such, this movement forms a network of pre-discursive, conceptual and practical associations which determine the formation of subjectivity, and thus its horizons for perception, thought and action. This schema is made evident in the way in which Nishida situates artistic production in the “style theories” [yōshiki] 31 of Alois Riegl and Willhelm Worringer, as well as in Jane Harrison’s work on Greek mythology and ritual. 32 Artistic style is formulated as part of the historical body which, as discussed above, is integrated into, and thus conditions, artistic expression in the present. Nishida’s concrete articulation of historical style heavily draws upon his colleague Watsuji Tetsurō (1889-1960). In particular, Nishida draws on Watsuji’s 1927 work, “Concerning the ‘Style Theories’ of Eastern Art” [Tōyō bijutsu no ‘yōshiki’ ni tsuite] and his 1928 article, “Characteristics of the Arts Based on Differences in ‘Location’” [‘Tokoro’ ni yotte kotonaru geijutsu no tokushusei], claiming that Egyptian, Greek, and Japanese people [minzoku] form an artistic style within their own distinct environment or climate [fūdo]. 33 This association becomes extremely problematic as Nishida undertakes an unsubstantiated East-West comparative analysis, privileging the expression of spirit [kokoro] as the artistic style structuring Eastern, particularly Japanese, art. 34 Regardless, for present purposes it is important to see that artistic style, as part of the historical body, functions alongside the future to articulate the horizon of affordances for artistic expression. 35 As such, it acts as a paradigm, carving channels and suggesting a course for artistic behavior. 36 But it is important to further recognize that Nishida does not believe that the formation of subjectivity is merely determined by the historical body nor by what is now called discourse. He thus does not believe that artistic expression is determined by artistic styles. This is because he does not claim that history moves from the made to the made, or the making to the made, and thus does not endorse any form of strict historical determinism. For Nishida, the movement of self-determination of the present, as made, is conditioned by the past and also, as making, stands in direct relation to the future. Insofar as past and future are integrated into the unfolding of the present, they delimit the horizon of affordances open to the present, thereby conditioning the expressive possibilities in the self-determination of the present. Since this movement is active-intuitive it constitutes subjectivity qua objectivity; that is, subjectivity qua the historical, material world. Here, the historical body, as the paradigmatic horizon constraining expressive activity, constitutes subjectivity as a suggestion for interpreting the historical world into the future. It follows that the emergence of subjectivity through active-intuition, through the integration of the past in the movement of self-determination in the present moment, follows the path impressed by the historical body. Subjectivity is subjected, produced and located in its integration of the material historical body. As such, Nishida privileges the subject as shutai, decentering the Aristotelian Homo Faber, the Cartesian cogito, and Kantian transcendental subjectivity by emphasizing the subject’s fundamental relationality with the promulgation and propagation of the 31 Riegl, Alois, Die spätrömische Kunstindustrie nach den Funden in Österreich-Ungarn (Late Roman Art Industry), Trans. R. Winkes, (Bretschneider: Rome, 1985). 32 Nishida. “Rekishiteki keisei sayō toshite no geijutstuteki sōsaku,” New NKZ, Vol.9, pp.236-237. Originally published in 1941. 33 Ibid. p.280. 34 Ibid. p.282. 35 Ibid. p.280. 36 cf. “The idea is the basic paradigm of our actions.” Ibid, p.277. Idea is here understood as the historical, actual world. Nishida. “Kōiteki chokan no tachiba,” pp.135, 160-161. 10 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself historical body. That is, the subjectivity [shukan] of Aristotle, Descartes, and Kant is merely an abstraction from the becoming of subjectivity [shutai] in and alongside the historical world. Thus its connection to the historical material world does not entail the eradication of subjectivity but rather its dispersion. Put more strongly: the historical body does not erase individual subjectivity but rather the composition of subjectivity functions as the transcendental condition for the propagation and future articulation of discourse. It is through its crystallization into the many distinct subjectivities that discourse propagates. The singular subjectivity is here understood in its fundamental relationality with objectivity. Through its integration of past movements, the constitution of subjectivity functions to reproduce discursive formations. This suggestion for interpretation is the most basic level at which expressive activity functions. In other words, expressive activity largely functions as a prompting to repeat what has been given in antecedent experience, thereby recapitulating the historical body through the constitution of subjectivity. But this interpretive proposal cannot entirely stand as recapitulation, and it follows that on the most primordial level expressive activity is a first order minimal expression and minimal interpretation through which the made is transformed into the making. This ontological schema comes forth explicitly in Nishida’s discussion of habit (shūkan). Nishida cites habit formation as the most basic example of the historical body influencing, conditioning, and thereby suggesting a form for the present. 37 We should note that our habits are not born out of the passive reception of the world; rather, even the most ingrained of habits develops in the progression of history, usually in relation to changes in one’s surrounding environment. As the environment changes our habits adjust, remaining similar to what they once were but also regulating themselves in accordance with such fluctuations. Nishida: What composes our habit is not simply consciousness. Something like biological instinct is established as the self-determination of the dialectical world. And something like second nature [daini shizen] is established within our biological bodies, and moreover, it is established as expressive activity. 38 Through his discussion of habits, Nishida provides an ontology of reproduction and, insofar as this reproduction is minimally influenced by expressive activity and thus not a mere recapitulation of the past, production. In this ontology of becoming, the passive habit is always minimally creative. It is here, I argue, that Nishida makes his first step towards rearticulating subjectivity beyond the merely subjected. It is indeed true that, through its vertical integration, subjectivity is, to use Stephen Heath’s vocabulary, “interpellated” in discourse, largely functioning to reproduce and recapitulate the historical world. 39 But this cannot merely function as a recapitulation of discursive constraints. Despite being subjected to the historical body, subjectivity is structured by expressive activity, and is thus always simultaneously forming-formed and formed-forming. This means that in its expressive, intuitive self-determination, subjectivity entails novelty. But the novelty entailed in habits, particularly of those linked to second nature, is extremely constrained. If Nishida stopped here he would have an exceedingly restricted conception of novelty, one which largely privileged the recapitulation and rearticulation of the objective, discursive, 37 Nishida. “Ronri to seimei,” New NKZ, Vol.8, pp.13-14. Originally published in 1936. Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.201. 39 Heath, Stephen. Questions of Cinema (Macmillan Press, 1981), p.106. 38 Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 11 historical body. But Nishida proceeds, drawing upon the modern French philosopher Maine de Biran in order to distinguish active habits [nōdōteki shūkan] and passive habits [judoteki shūkan]. Expressive activity largely functions as a passive habit, which is formulated as the inheritance of past-impulses [shōdō] with a minimally creative interpretation. Against expressive activity as a passive habit, Nishida formulates active-intuition as an active habit. Nishida: “If we speak from the standpoint of the self-determination of the historical world, what is called an active habit should be thought of as active-intuition.” 40 Active habit is therefore, Nishida continues, the “development of historical life,” and should be understood as a creative reconfiguration and restructuring of past patterns. This means that subjectivity is not merely subjected, and thus is not simply interpellated into discourse through the present moment’s integration of the historical body. Rather, as activeintuition, subjectivity emerges from the ground of its fundamental connectivity with objectivity, and thus emerges both as active and forming as it is acted and formed. As William Haver puts it, “perception, apperception, and cognition are not for Nishida merely inscriptions on an essentially passive epistemological or phenomenological subject but modes of an active, aggressive, appropriation, driven by a daemonic potential, the power to be.” In the self-determination of subjectivity through absolute negation, the present moment allows for the constitution of a novel potentiality beyond the paradigms carved by the historical body. That is, the self-determinative production of subjectivity allows for the reorientation and reconfiguration of discursive power relations. This means that subjectivity is produced with agency, as agency; that agency is guaranteed in the co-production of subject and object, and is thus secured inasmuch as subjectivity is always situated within and alongside the limitations of the historical body. Nishida claims that “artistic intuition [geijutsuteki chokkan] is established as a certain case of active-intuition,” 41 thus employing enhanced novelty as the grounds for a distinction between instinctual and artistic production. This is, of course, a matter of degree. While instinctual subjectivity is production, it is minimally novel and is thus largely dominated by the passive inheritance of past impulses. On the other hand, while the agency that is born out of artistic production integrates the historical past, it is differentiated in its active reconfiguration of past impulses. 42 But the agency born in the self-determinative formative movements of the present, either active or passive, is not necessarily equitable in terms of its subject-object relation, and Nishida claims that determinations of agency are situated on a continuum between the immanent [naizai] and the transcendental [chōetsu] poles. Keeping in mind these antipodes, Nishida articulates two active movements of agency, distinguishing artistic intuition from “thought” [shii]. While both function as forms of agency, constituted as the co-production of subjectivity and objectivity in the self-determination of the present, thought functions in the transcendental direction, as an active movement on the side of objectivity, and artistic intuition functions in the immanent direction, as an active movement on the side of subjectivity. This means that the agency constituted in the latter emphasizes the direction of the self in its expressive formation. Insofar as agency is constituted in the direction of the self in artistic expression, the historical “world reflects the image of the self- 40 Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.201. Nishida, “Ronri to seimei,” p.340. 42 Nishida. “Rekishiteki keisei sayō toshite no geijutstuteki sōsaku,” p.264. 41 12 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself itself.” 43 This is not a collapsing of the historical dimensions into subjectivity, and Nishida emphasizes that “what is called artistic creative activity is not the activity of subjective consciousness. This must come into being from the self-determination of the historical world.” 44 This articulation of artistic intuition can be used to reconceptualize our understanding of artistic production, the work of art, the artist, as well as the relationship between these notions. First and foremost, the work of art is neither reducible to its historical conditions nor to the life of the artist. Concomitantly, the work of art is not the vestige of an expelled artistic agency, neither discharged onto the world through an intense focusing of subjectivity (as in the Individual conception of the artist) nor displaced and nullified in the larger unfolding of discourse (as in the artist’s death). Both views are mistaken inasmuch as they articulate the work of art as a secondary event, assuming that it is either the perceptions, thoughts, and actions of the already-existing artist-subject or the prearticulated discursive object that stands as the sole condition for the work of art. In the context of activity and passivity, the first view is mistaken inasmuch as it presupposes a pre-formed subjective agent which acts and molds a passive world, and the second view is mistaken inasmuch as it assumes an active world which acts and molds a passive subject. But to understand these artistic concepts, an interpretive shift from the unidirectionality of being to the bidirectionality of production is necessary. Such a move abandons the hermeneutical framework, which sees work or text as an impetus to uncover the subject behind it or the hidden discursive network of meaning structuring its appearance. In its place, it situates artistic production as a moment in the production of the subjectivity of the artist, neither as a mere reflection of the artist nor the discursive paradigm. This shift situates subjective agency not within the context of the Aristotelian, the Cartesian, nor the Kantian subjectivity (shukan), but rather within the context of a historically located conception of subjectivity (shutai). Here, subjective agency is secured in active intuition, with subjectivity standing as such only through its fundamental relationality with objectivity, in the interconnection of one and many. This secures a more flexible conception of artistic agency, rooted in mutual mediation, in the locus of action-acted, whereby we form and determine objects as we are formed and determined by objects. Thus on the one hand, the production of subjectivity is constructed in relation to objectivity in the integration of the historical past, and is therefore “chained” or “sutured” in the unfolding of discourse. 45 But, on the other hand, as artistic production, subjectivity projects the self onto the world thereby making the “world reflect the image of the self-itself.” 46 Here, objectivity is constructed in relation to subjectivity. This means that artistic production, as rooted in this bidirectional activity, is the production of a subjectivity which is placed and positioned in discursive webs as it moves beyond them, reconfiguring and reorienting these discursive ideological systems. The fact that such a conception is imbricated in a radically momentary conception of becoming is important in our formulation of these artistic concepts. As discussed above, the bidirectionality of active-intuition unfolds in the absolute present, with this production simultaneously negating subjectivity out of existence, thus securing the alterity of future determinative productions of self and world, and the independence of past determinations of self and world. As such, no Individual can be deduced from the work of art, and thus there is no stable subjectivity that stands behind, and 43 Nishida. “Rekishiteki keisei sayō toshite no geijutstuteki sōsaku,” p.283. Nishida. “Kōiteki chokkan no tachiba,” p.110. 45 Heath, Questions of Cinema, p.106. 46 Nishida. “Rekishiteki keisei sayō toshite no geijutstuteki sōsaku,” p.283. 44 Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself – 13 functions as an absolute link between, the disparate outputs of an artist’s oeuvre. Instead, there is a dynamic conception of processual subjectivity, produced and extinguished in the present moment. As such, our investigation privileges care for the disparate moments of production, investigating those contemporaneous personal and social factors structuring the emergence of the work of art, and thus of subjectivity. This requires an openness to radical diversity within an oeuvre, and thus challenges the narrative approach to biography and discourse that has structured much inquiry. Moreover, it also requires attention to distinct moments in the production of a single work, and thus stresses the recognition of diversity between manuscripts or drafts, working to articulate different subjective modes across one work. But this is not to negate the conceptions of artist or oeuvre, severing all ties between the different works created by an artist. In fact, Nishida’s conception of the simultaneous existence of past and future in the absolute present, where past and present are integrated into the selfdetermination of the present through the eternal now, demands that we pay attention to such a connection. Inasmuch as the work stands as the crystallization of a coming into being which integrates past and future, the commentator also has an obligation to search for threads – both subjective and objective – across a single work, several works of a single author, and different works across different authors. Moreover, inasmuch as the distinction between immediate and remote past is blurred in the formation of subjectivity, the commentator has to be especially aware of and open to discontinuities between the temporally close and continuities between the temporally distant. Conclusion This presentation has worked to articulate an alternative to those discourses built around either the autonomy of the Individual or the author’s death. Using Nishida’s middle period philosophy, it employed the notion of the self-itself, as an act underlying the subject-object duality, to argue that the fluidity of the self-itself melts into manifold positions in artistic production, thereby decentering artistic agency across a multitude of positions and diffusing artistic production across the continuum of subjectivity and objectivity. Next, using his late period philosophy, it connected the work of art to the manifold positions of the processual subject, claiming that the unfolding of the self-itself is creatively produced through the novelty of the work of art as it reallocates, reorganizes, and redeploys the present within the horizons delimited by the historical body. 14 – Kyle Peters: Producing the Self-Itself