Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body: Refiguring
Transcription
Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body: Refiguring
The Southern Journal of Philosophy (1996)Vol. XXxF! Supplement Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body: Refiguring the SedGender Distinction Nancy Tuana University of Oregon I’m going to make m e a man. Frank N. Furter Rocky Horror Picture Show The young man stands on stage his skin glistening. The flesh of his body offered up to the excited crowd is displayed with pride, all but that part hidden by a tight spandex bathing suit t h a t appears as if molded onto his body. As he begins his routine, offering pose after pose designed to highlight different parts of his body, huge veins on his neck and arms stand out creating a roadmap t h a t shifts and changes as he moves. He flexes his muscles t o expose the perfect washboard stomach, the huge throbbing pecs, the biceps and triceps he has braided into intricate patterns. The body on stage is a very carefully sculpted body. It is not enough to be big, muscles expanding neck, chest, and thigh size far beyond the parameters of storebought clothing. The body must be symmetrical and proportionate, which, given current competitive aesthetics, means a perfect V-shape. For the climax of his routine, he presents his most muscular pose. He turns to the audience, bends forward, and brings his arms half-way out from his body, bent at the elbow, hands clenched into fists, and pointing at one another. Taking a deep breath, he flexes his whole upper torso, and doubles the size of his shoulders, chest, and neck. The audience goes wild and t h e auditorium rings with the loud baritone cry “Beef! Beef! Beef!”’ ATTENDING TO BODIES The body has been made so problematic for women that it h a s often seemed easier to shrug it off and travel as a disembodied spirit. Adrienne Rich Of Woman Born 53 Nancy Tuana I want to call attention to bodies-fleshed, pulsating, volatile2 bodies. Over a decade ago I argued t h a t t h e distinction between sex a n d gender was pernicious a n d advocated t h a t .~ I continue t h i s argufeminists refuse its p ~ l a r i z a t i o n Here ment and do so by focusing on bodies. I believe t h at in embraci n g the distinction b e t w e e n se x a n d g en d er we h av e inadvertently contributed to a problematic neglect of bodies in feminist scholarship. I exaggerate. Feminists have not completely ignored bodies. In fact, much of t h e work on t h e topic San d ra Harding labels “the science question in f e m i n i ~ r n is ” ~devoted to exposing t h e ways i n which theories of biological determinism have been used to justify a range of sexist and racist practices. We have examined t h e ways science inscribed mark ers of inferiority onto woman’s body-her smaller brain size, her role in reproduction, h e r skeletal structure-and t h e ways in which these theories were intricately interwoven with theories of racial inf e r i ~ r i t y Indeed, .~ my own Less Noble Sex was designed to advance such studies by locating t h e points at which scientific theorizing about t h e structures of woman’s body was interwoven with religious and philosophical viewpoints.6 The goals of such studies are t o expose such theories as empirically false and to reveal t h e ways i n which scientific theorizing concerning sex and race differences both arose out of and in t u r n reinforced socially held biases about women a n d about people of oppressed races. I do not want to completely deny t h e value of such studies. They have contributed to our understanding of institutionalized racism a n d sexism, a n d t o t h e ways i n which science, even good science, emerges out of t h e values of t h e cultures in which it is practiced. However, as I will demonstrate, it is pernicious to simply critique theories of biological determinism on their own terms, for doing so leaves t h e metaphysic underpinning them in place. That is epistemically irresponsible.’ O u r ongoing reliance on t h e dichotomy between sex a n d gender is also epistemically irresponsible for we continue t o make t h e distinction in a way t h a t replicates t h e metaphysic t h a t provides t h e foundation for biological determinism. The problem I refer to is well illustrated i n Anne Minas’ introductory text Gender Basics: Feminist Perspectives on Women and Men. We have become increasingly aware of the possibility that some of the differences between men and women have social causes. We need some way of saying so, especially if we want to discuss how social structures may function in creating particular differences. Perhaps if we can change the structures, we may be able to change the differences they cause. (It hardly makes sense to direct social change at the genetic-the strictly biological-features.) 54 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body Thus the word “sex”is coming to be restricted to biological, or genetic male/female differences, leaving its official synonym, “gender,” free to drift toward meaning those differences that have social causes.” This quote frames a dichotomy, a n absolute separation, between those traits of women and men t h a t have social causes and those t h a t are rooted in biology. But the distinction does not stop there; added to this basic division is the belief t h a t features due to biology a r e not malleable. “It hardly makes sense to direct social change at the genetic-the strictly biological-features.” Feminism here repeats a key tenet of biological determinism: t h a t nature places marks upon women and men, Anglos and Latinos, and these marks are indelible. Having championed this distinction, many feminists then felt compelled to minimize t h e body. Indeed t h e t e n e t t h a t there are no significant biological differences between women and men is a hallmark of certain versions of liberal feminism, with t h e t e r m “significant” h e r e often defined i n t e r m s of wage-earning labor. As one example, I t u r n to Bonnie Spanier’s delineation of the premises of her recent study of molecular biology entitled Irn /partial Science. “I also start from the belief, based on accumulated evidence, that the only jobs men a r e constitutionally incapable of performing a r e childbearing and wet-nursing, while the only job a woman cannot perform is sperm d ~ n a t i o n . Although ”~ some feminists seem to resent even modifying the denial (signifzcant differences), critics simply call attention to the body. In many cases this attention is directed at the same features t h a t centuries of biological determinists had raised against the specter of women’s equality: ovaries and hormones, pregnancy and lactation. Faced with the body, feminists have embraced meaning rather than flesh.1° Feminist denials of “significant sex differences” too often are articles of faith, shored up by attention to social causes of perceived differences, namely, “gender.” To offer j u s t one example, we have investigated institutions of motherhood, looked to alternative gender practices concerning child rearing i n other cultures, and examined links between economic practices and cultural attitudes about motherhood. The few attempts to muddy the waters by including the body, such as Adrienne Rich’s Of Woman Born,” are often criticized as essentialist. Indeed, during the last two decades (and perhaps even now) it seemed almost impossible to speak of the fleshed particularities of women’s bodies without evoking the charge of essentialism. At a time when feminists felt that they had to confront socially dominant arguments for the biological basis of male superiority, “gender” was a useful tool to explain male privilege a s a result of complex structures of oppression and privilege 55 Nancy Tuana t h a t w e r e historically variable a n d cu l t u ral l y constituted. Along with Beauvoir we gloried in arguing t h a t women were made, not born. Given t h e long history of reducing women to our bodies, it is no surprise t h a t feminist accounts have often held t h e body at arm’s length. B u t i n doing so we have failed to properly theorize it or t o account for i t s materiality. This paper is a call for a return to t h e flesh. Not only do I e x a g g e ra t e , I a m n o t easily satisfied. My shelves a r e full of new books written by feminists with t h e te r m “body” in t h e title. I n all too many of t h es e I find only abstract, theoretical bodies rather t h a n fleshed, lived bodies. I intend to avoid this omission. TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE FLESH When you meet a h u m a n being, t h e first distinction you m a k e is “male or female?” a n d you a r e accustomed t o make the distinction with unhesitating certainty. Sigmund Freud ”Femininity” The s e d g e n d e r distinction is only one of a wider s et of dichotomies t h a t are metaphysically linked-naturelnurture, biologylculture, essentiallaccidental, innate/learned, genetic/ environmental, fixedlvariable. Traits due t o n at u re or biology a r e perceived as fixed a n d unchangeable. Those arising from n u r t u r e via our particular cultures are seen as variable and, to some extent, within human control. The phrase “human nature” is t ak e n t o refer t o essential properties t h a t constitute our fundamental n a t u re . These traits are, by definition, innate. And since their source is biology (what modern traditionalists refer to a s genetic), essential traits are defined a s fixed. And it h a s been, perhaps, no accident t h a t t h e religious systems of Judaism and Christianity have linked fact an d value by insisting t h a t natural properties are “good” and This is a n old story t h a t is well known, b u t t h a t seems not to diminish delight in retelling it. You will no doubt recollect the 20 J a n u a r y 1992 i ssu e of Time t h a t carri ed , inscribed across its cover, the message: “Why are men and women different? It isn’t j u s t upbringing. New studies show they are born t h a t way.” The Time issue, unwittingly, described t h e problem with feminist critiques of sex (or should I s ay gender?) differences. After reporting t h a t scientific research “proves” t h a t “gender differences have as much to do with t h e biology of t h e b r ain as with t h e way we a r e raised,” t h e article goes on t o discuss feminist attitudes. “During t h e feminist revolution of 56 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body the 1970s, talk of inborn differences in the behavior of men and women was distinctly unfashionable, even taboo.” Characterizing t h e feminist position as holding t h a t the “end of sexism” would bring the end to sex differences, t h e author concludes t h a t “biology has a funny way of confounding expectations ... perhaps nature is more important than nurture after all.”13 By keeping in place a fixed, biological given, feminist theorizing leaves itself open to the critique that this biological body is more significant t h a n we hoped, t h a t t h i s body is o u r unchanging destiny. Unfortunately, t h e l a s t t e n years h a s witnessed a dramatic increase in popular acceptance of t h e view t h a t sex differences and race differences a r e biologically caused and t h u s inevitable. I believe t h a t we feminists have been epistemically irresponsible in leaving in place a fixed, essential, material basis for human nature, a basis t h a t renders biological determinism meaningful. We have not attended sufficiently to the body, to the ways in which it is formed and transformed by social institutions. We must turn our attention to the sexing of the body and to fleshing gender to understand both how the body is socially constituted and how its materiality in t u r n informs the parameters of i t s configurations. Let me be clear. I do not advocate disproving biological determinism. I advocate rendering it nonsense. l4 Although Foucault a n d feminist theorists influenced by his work focus attention on t h e ways in which power is inscribed onto bodies, we also need to attend more carefully to the fact t h a t in talking about male bodies or female bodies we refer neither to a biological entity nor to meaning, nor even to a combination of t h e two. We refer to a material-semiotic matrix, an intra-activeprocess that will be mischaracterized as long as we a t t e m p t to understand i t through t h e false dichotomy of sex/gender or through t h e related binarisms of biology/culture, essential/constructed. I borrow t h e term “intra-active” here from Karen Barad who uses i t as a visual a n d auditory reminder t h a t t h e r e a r e no two things t h a t interact-a reminder to avoid reinscription of t h e contested dichotomy.15 This paper is a call for feminist attention to transformations of the flesh. Much of recent feminist theorizing about bodies has focused on semiotic aspects of particular material-semiotic matrixes. But we will never understand bodies fully without also attending to flesh, and doing so in ways that do not render it separate from the discursive. I here employ the term “flesh” as a reminder that bodies are not inanimate. They a r e not dead matter. I wish to present fleshed bodies as alive, as pulsating. I evoke its verb tense: to inflame the passions, to become more substantial, to incite to battle, to saturate. What is fleshly is carnal and sensual. The flesh presents a volatile reminder t h a t bodies a r e not inert. 57 Nancy Tuana They are pulsating, sensual, fluid. Feminists must return bodies to philosophy in the flesh. Bodies are material-semiotic spaces.“j Representation does not supersede materiality ( t h e common misreading of social constructivism) nor does materiality supersede representation. It is t h e either/or of t h i s choice I protest. The relationship is rather one of a complex intra-action t h a t is not adequately described by making distinctions in kind between “the effects of socially inscribed meanings” and “the impact of matter.” The case for this position is made by attending to bodies. If we flesh out the story of the bodybuilder, we discover t h a t bodies can be fabricated through deliberate alterations. Here’s the kind of NEW MAN I build. Charles Atlas Building bodies is no easy task. Although deliberate, cons t r u c t i n g bodies resembling those made famous by Arnold and Rambo is no mean feat. Bodybuilders view their bodies as a form of highly r e s i s t a n t plastic t h a t m u s t be severely disciplined into shape. J o e Weider, named by Arnold Schwarzenegger as “the greatest trainer bodybuilding h a s ever seen,” advises would be champions to “ ... show no mercy to the pitiful wretches [those resistant little musclesl. Bomb t h e m harder. Blitz them more often. Bury them under tons of weights. H i t them with less rest between sets. P u t more mental effort into it. In short, hound t h e lagging areas a s h a r d as you can until they give u p and grow.”17Cartilage must be stretched to enlarge rib cages a n d “improve overall body structure.” Most importantly one must gain muscle mass, increasing muscular body weight by four to six pounds per year. Every year. H a r d work is not enough to fashion t h e perfect body, a n d many serious bodybuilders use steriods as a m a t t e r of course. Steroids increase strength and enable the body to “bulk up” by accelerating the rate at which the body can metabolize nitrogen into muscle. According to Joe Weider, “most bodybuilders t a k e s t e r o i d s , a n d a few t a k e p u r e androgenics ( s u c h as testosterone), for six weeks before competing.”ls Thyroid stimulants are used to speed up the metabolism and help the body to get “cut up.” And t h e current fashion for “vascularity,” the road map of veins criss-crossing t h e pumped body, requires minimal body fat which is often obtained by use of special drugs. PHILOSOPHIES OF THE BODY Elizabeth Grosz identifies two broad kinds of philosophical approaches to t h e body, w h a t s h e labels inscriptive a n d lived 58 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body body. Foucault is currently t h e best known advocate for inscriptive philosophies of t h e body. Inscriptions a r e seen as “mark[ing] the surface of the body, dividing it into zones of intensified or de-intensified sensation, spreading a libidinal concentration unevenly over the written-and-erotic surface.”lgAs we see from the combination of “punishing” workout routines and routine use of steroids, these are not surface inscriptions. Muscles are not simply marked, they are “grown.” The body is transformed from outside/in and inside/out. Bodybuilders like Schwarzenegger have not only transformed their own bodies, they have participated in a transformation of cultural attitudes towards male bodies. When I was young, bodybuilders were regarded with suspicion. Men who admired the bodies of muscle-bound men were seen as narcissistic a t best, deviant at worst. Bodybuilding, we were warned, would lead boys t o “compare their bodies with those of other boys” which could eventually “take the form of being sexually aroused by the others, and out of this comes the desire to have sex with the body of another person.”20Thanks to over a dozen Schwarzenegger films, backed up by a pumped Sylvester Stallone in the Rocky and Rambo series, the bodybuilder has been converted from social deviant to warriodpatriot. This occurred a t t h e same time t h a t presentations of male bodies changed dramatically. The last ten years has witnessed an explosion of partially nude male bodies in advertising. And these bodies are buffed. We no longer worry if our sons plaster their bedroom walls with posters of these pumped male bodies, for all of us, men and women alike, a r e learning to see the male body (well, a properly muscled one) as an object of desire. This cultural transformation has an impact on lived experience. A young boy’s bodily, fleshed presence has been changed by this transformation. Think of what it takes i n the days of Conan a n d Rambo for a boy to feel manly. I t is no longer enough to be powerful, one must look the role by presenting a body t h a t is hard, muscular, and athletic. The change in culture perhaps parallels, in reverse, the phenomena of anorexia in women. How many pumped men, pros and amateurs alike, look in the mirror and see themselves as lacking in muscled manliness? This newly eroticized body is paradoxical, for at the same time that bodybuilders have, thanks in large part to Arnold’s antics, come out of t h e closet a n d invaded mainstream US.culture, the new butch-shift in gay culture rears the fearful head of homoerotic desire while at the same time reinforcing gender stereotypes of manliness. Yet we all know, don’t we, t h a t real men, manly men, those musclebound bodies, are heterosexual! Aren’t they?!? Unpacking all this would require another paper. But lest you begin to think that my focus here is limited to discursive practices, let me remind you once again of the need 59 Nancy Tuana t o see bodies as material-semiotic intra-actions. Changes in t h e culture of bodybuilding not only shift and shape t h e meanings of masculinity, they are incorporated into bodies, which in t u r n shift and shape. When bodybuilders at t emp t to inscribe th eir bodies with t h e (currently) perfect form of masculinity, the body has a say. The prolonged use of steriods causes a condition known a s gynecomastia, or “bitch tits,” the growth of a bulbous swelling under one or both nipples a s a result of the body’s oestrogen level rising to counteract the massive dose of what i t takes to be testosterone ... with prolonged steriod use testicles atrophy, penises s h r i n k a n d erections become infrequent or cease altogether. In other words, the bodybuilder using steroids i s effecting his own castration. This is the unavoidable logic of the bodybuilder’s long term scourging of his masculine body. After years of abuse with drugs and “intensitylinsanity” routines, “Mr. Universe” [Ray] Michalik found his body finally taking the hint and effecting the final transformation: “His testosterone level plummeted, h i s sperm count went to zero a n d all t h e oestrogen i n his body, which had been accruing for years, turned his pecs to soft, doughy breasts. Such friends a s he still had pointed out t h a t his ass was plumping like a woman’s and tweaked him for his sexy, new hip-switching walk.7721 Masculinities-femininities are performed-and-embodied. To say t h a t th e body is “always already” culture is not to deny t h a t it is “always already” material; j u s t do not make a dichotomy out of it. A METAPHYSICAL INTERLUDE Traditional theories of n a t u r e h u r t u r e employ a notion of genetic fixity. Unfortunately, even recent attempts to acknowledge a n interaction between n a t u r e a n d environment replicates th is notion of genetic fixity. As I argued in “Re-Fusing Naturernurture,” typical interpretations of t h e biological concept of epigenesis (t h e concept t h a t a n organism develops by the new appearance of structures a n d functions through t h e interaction of gene and surrounding conditions) retain a n additive model t h a t does not undercut t h e division between nat u r e h u r t u r e . Although theorists who adopt such a n account insist t h a t traits a r e t h e result of a n interweaving of genetic and environmental factors, and t h u s deny t h a t any particular trait is static a n d unchanging, they persist in positing a n ontological divide between t h e two. Such a move simply changes t h e question from “Which t ra i t s are due to innate factors and which ar e due to environmental factors?” to “To what extent is 60 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body the trait in question due to innate factors and to what extent is it due to environmental factors?” The genetic factors remain static and unchanging in the sense of delimiting a fixed set of possibilities, although the trait, now seen as a combination of the manifestation of genetic factors within a particular (and perhaps changing) environment, need not be static. Nature and nurture continue to be seen as separate, though perhaps not separable, mechanisms. Correlated to this additive model is an equally mechanical design for a trait’s ability to change. Crudely put, a trait that is the result of 80 percent nature and 20 percent environment is seen as far less variable than one in which the percentages are reversed. Contemporary philosophies of t h e body must be supplemented with a new metaphysic that treats the relationship between bodies a n d culture as a dynamic intra-action, t h a t refuses to treat nature and nurture as dichotomous, and t h a t rejects a mechanistic, additive model. Feminists must replace the traditional physical object metaphysic, wherein each object h a s essential and accidental characteristics, with a process metaphysics t h a t emphasizes phenomena. Karen Barad’s Bohrean-inspired theory of “agential realism” offers a contemporary version of this much needed metaphysic. On Barad’s account, “phenomena are constitutive of reality.” Reality is not composed of things-in-themselves or things-behind-phenomena, but things-in-phenomena.22 Phenomena a r e simultaneously material-semiotic. On a process account, observable features of a n individual (phenotype) result from the genetic makeup of the individual (genotype) i n intra-action with t h e environment i n which t h e genotype develops. This intra-action must be seen as dynamic and nonlinear. On such a model, rather than determining a set of characteristics or potentials, the fixity woven into the above two models, genotype specifies patterns of reaction of a developing organism t o the environment i t encounters. The notion of certain outcomes being “natural” and others “unnatural,” or more or less so, makes no sense here. The process is the development of new structures and patterns from the results of the intra-action of previously existing structures and p a t t e r n s both within the organism and its internal environment and between the organism and its external environment. Since new patterns and structures emerge from such intra-actions, the organism is different at each stage of its development. It is not enough to say nature cannot be separated from nurture. We must also provide models adequate to the cumulative dynamic of organism-environment intra-actions. A process metaphysics replaces the notion of unchanging substances affecting one another by external contacts (molecules colliding) with activity (force, energy) intra-acting with other activity. Entities are not fixed, but emergent. Complex 61 Nancy Tuana intra-actions between entities transform t h e previous struct u r e of each activity. Notions of essential characteristics or fixed natures (Kantian noumena) make no sense. Nor would a dichotomy between n a t u r e h u r t u r e or s ep arat e genetic a n d environmental mechanisms be a d e q u at e t o a n intra-active model of t h e dynamic relation between gene, environment, an d organism. A process metaphysic of phenomena does not preclude making distinctions, even distinctions between nature and nurture. But doing so must always be richly situated an d acknowledge t h e complexity of t h e developmental intraaction. What is rejected is t h e claim t h a t these distinctions (nature-nurture) signify n a t u ra l boundaries. Bu t do not t ri p over t h a t refusal into t h i n k i n g t h a t t h es e distinctions are then arbitrary divisions of a prior oneness. Revealing distinctions, constructing boundaries between n a t u r e a n d n u r t u r e are im p o r ta n t , b u t t h e y will be time, s i t u at i o n , a n d value relative, and must re-fuse dichotomization. What is needed is a metaphysic adequate to a critical understanding of t h e complexities of the material-semiotic matrix of phenomena. Although recent feminist accounts seem to be veering towards such a view, they often miss t h e mark due, I would argue, to t h e unhnder-theorized impact of a traditional realist metaphysic and t h e either/or of realism/social constructivism it engenders. As j u s t one example, consider Dorothy Nelkin and Susan Lindee’s claim in “The Media-ted Gene” t h a t Genes seem to cause the bodily differences that matter most in this cultural debate [namely over the meanings of gender and race]. But bodily difference i s historically specific, written not in the body but in the culture that defines what aspects of the body are most important when one begins to sort people into groups ... Scientific claims [about nature1 ... are, in effect, a way to construct the body in ways that will legitimate existing social c a t e g o r i e ~ . ~ ~ I n continuing to make a dichotomy between n a t u r e h u r t u r e , genelenvironment, mattedlanguage, feminist theorists fail to realize t h e radical potential of their position. We reify the dichotomy that will be used against us. Given a process metaphysic, we undermine t h e eitherjor of biological determinismhadical social constructivism by rendering meaningless t h e poles of t h i s dichotomy. Bodies a r e theorized ( an d lived) as a material-semiotic matrix. B u t we must be careful i n such rendering to give full voice to all aspects of t h i s matrix. Take t h e case of J u d i t h Butler as j u s t one example of a feminist theorist who clearly supports t h e spirit if not t h e particulars of such a metaphysic. In h er first book Gender Double, she rejects t h e presumption of a binary gender system on t h e grounds t h a t it “implicitly retains t h e Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body belief i n a mimetic relation of gender to sex whereby gender mirrors sex or is otherwise restricted by it.”24Although Butler clearly rejects a metaphysical division of nature from nurture, her attention is overly focused on discursive elements, which too often leads her to ignore or obscure the materiality of the intra-action. Bodybuilders perform sex by transforming flesh. Culture intra-acts with biology. Biology is a well-spring for performativity, but i t i s neither fixed nor static. Nor is i t a completely plastic background that the social forms into particular structures. I t is active, productive, acted upon, and produced. There is a materiality t h a t must always be taken into account but not separated from the discursive. Indeed, the discursive is itself marked by the body.25 Do we truly need a true sex? Michel Foucault Herculine Barbin But I have over-simplified. The sex/gender dichotomy is linked to the nexus of dichotomies listed above, but the full connection requires a n additional belief, the belief t h a t there are two and only two sexes. An early rendition of this linkage can be found in Ann Oakley’s 1972 book, Sex, Gender, and Society. ‘Sex’ is a word t h a t refers to the biological differences between male and female: the visible difference in genitalia, the related difference in procreative function. ‘Gender’ however is a matter of culture: it refers to t h e social classification into ‘masculine’ and ‘feminine.’26 Although feminists have done a n excellent job of delineating the ways in which understandings and practices of femininity and masculinity have been fluid and situational, we have been far less successful in conceptualizing being a woman and being a man as fluid and situational. We continue to posit a fixed, essential binarism. Why do we hold so tenaciously to this dichotomy? What holds it in place? Man is always defined in opposition to woman: “1.an adult male person, as distinguished from a boy or a woman. MAN, MALE, GENTLEMAN refer to adult humans of the sex t h a t produces sperm for procreation. MALE n.1. a person bearing a n X and Y chromosome pair in the cell nuclei and normally having a penis, scrotum, and testicles, and developing hair on the face at adolescence. MALE classifies individuals on the basis of their genetic makeup or their ability t o fertilize an ovum in bisexual reproduction. It contrasts with FEMALE i n all its uses. FEMALE n.1. a person of the sex whose cell nuclei con63 Nancy Tuana tain two X chromosomes and who is normally able to conceive and bear young.”27 T h e sex/gender distinction imports t h e n a t u r e h u r t u r e dichotomy, b u t adds to it t h e tenet t h a t there are two, an d only two, tr u e sexes, woman a n d m a n , a n d t h a t t h e i r n a t u r e is grounded i n evolution and innate psychological and biological dispositions. MAN/WOMAN a r e natural, unmediated categories. They ar e real and “out there.” Femininities/masculinities a r e “made,” not so sex. Herein lies another concern for femin i s t u s e of t h e sex/gender distinction. Should we n o t a s k , along with Foucault, “DOwe truly need a true sex?”28A version of t h i s q u es t i o n h a s been posed, a n d an s wered , by An n e Fausto-Sterling who a rg u e s t h a t two sexes a r e not enough. “For biologically speaking, there are many gradations running from female t o m a l e ; a n d d e p e n d i n g on how o n e calls t h e shots, one can argue t h a t along t h a t spectrum lie a t least five sexes-and perhaps even more.”29 Calling u s back to t h e “facts” of biology, Fausto-Sterling reminds us of intersexuality. S h e calls attention to t h e fact t h a t intersexuals may constitute as many a s 4 percent of births, yet their existence h a s been incredibly well erased by current medical practices and completely denied by Western legal systems. As annoying as we might find t h e cu rren t d eb at es i n Congress concerning same-sex marriage, we seldom notice t h a t opponents and proponents alike presume “bi-sexuality.” The biological fact of intersexuality, confounds t h e markers used to define sex. “MAN, MALE, GENTLEMAN refer to adult h u m a n s of t h e sex t h a t produces sperm for procreation.” The intersexual is a combination of female a n d male anatomical structures, such t h a t t h e individual cannot be clearly defined as male or female. The so-called “true hermaphrodite” is a person who has one testis and one ovary; “pseudohermaphrodites” are individuals who have testes a n d some female genitals, b u t no ovaries, or have ovaries a n d some male genitals b u t no testis. Nor will chromosomes provide such markers. “MALE n.1. a person bearing a n X a n d Y chromosome pair i n t h e cell n u clei.” Some so-called “sex-reversed” individuals combine XX chromosomes a n d male genitalia or XY chromosomes a n d female genitalia. (Let me not erase here t h a t Western medical science r e f e rs t o s u c h i n d i v i d u a l s as XY femal es a n d XX males. Note t h e bias of bipolar sex.) Some intersexuals a r e XXY, others a r e genetic mosaics where some cells are XX o r XO and others are XY. B u t F a u s t o -S t e rl i n g does n o t a d d r e s s t h e e n t i r e t y of Foucault’s question. We could, I think fairly, render h er question “Must we render (true) sex as binary.” Though displacing t h e division between woman a n d m a n , it is accomplished by addition (man + woman + 31, a n d t h e questioning of “true” sex (“Do we truly need a true sex?”) does not arise. Sex becomes 64 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body f a r more diverse, b u t its biological fixity remains unquestioned. Fausto-Sterling clearly recognizes the cultural role in how such sexual difference is both understood and managed. “Why should we care if t h e r e a r e people whose biological equipment enables them to have sex “naturally” with both men and women? The answers seem to lie in a cultural need to maintain clear distinctions between the sexes ... [and] the specter of homosexuality.”30But she maintains the eitherlor of naturelnurture. We have moved from two true sexes to at least five. But once again, addition will not help. THE BODY PLASTIC We live in a world of two biological genders. But that may not be the only world. Suzanne J. Kessler and Wendy McKenna Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach Do we really? Which “we”? To begin to flesh out the reason why a process metaphysic with its inherent intra-active model of nature-culture is so important, I will give two examples t h a t illustrate t h e ways in which the volatility of flesh renders the question of true sex problematic. .~~ As a first example, consider the Brazilian t r a ~ e s t i sMany of the sex workers in Salvador Brazil are individuals who have carefully sculpted their bodies to exaggerate the curves identified with the female body. In many ways they a r e the mirror opposite of bodybuilders. One sculpts a manly form; the other the full breasts, buttocks, and thighs of a womanly form. They are scantily clad in ways t h a t will both augment their voluptuous curves and accentuate the size of their penises. “They do not self-identify as homens (men) or mulheres (women), but as t r a u e s t i ~ . ”Like ~ ~ bodybuilders they shape their bodies both mechanically and through use of hormones. Like bodybuilders, trauestis are the result of an intra-action of flesh and environment. And like t h e bodybuilder, though perhaps more obviously, they not only explode t h e conception of two and only two sexes, but present a n argument against simply “adding to” t h e currently accepted numbers of sexes “third sex,” (or perhaps “sixth sex”). To add to the number of sexes reinforces the view that there is some sort of biological t r u t h to sex, t h a t there is behind the confusion truly a t r u e sex. But such a position also eradicates the complex intra-action involved here. To understand the extent of this intra-action, I would like to compare Brazilian trauestis with the history of transsexuals 65 Nancy Tuana in the United States and Understanding the transsexual experience in t h e U.S. and Europe i n the twentieth century involves telling a variety of stories including the development of plastic surgery techniques and a t t i t u d e s towards their use, the notion of gender identity that arose out of scientific theorizing about intrasexuals, t h e efforts of transsexuals to create their subjectivity, but most of all understanding the tenacity of the hold of binarism on Western scientific thinking about sedgender. Story One: Plastic surgery has been a recognized medical speciality for less than 80 years. Although i t was originally developed to render whole those bodies t h a t had been deformed by war, accident, mistake of birth, or illness, the industry of “cosmetic surgery” quickly created a place for itself in Western medical practices. The latter transformed notions of “normal appearance” within the Western world and linked such an appearance with psychological health. A 1952 article in Better Homes and Gardens began with a discussion of “Henry,” who became a young hoodlum as a result of protruding ears. The judge in his case sentenced him to plastic surgery, after which a social worker reported: “He appears to have lost entirely the old feeling of inferiority about his ears which drove him into seeking out acquaintances of dubious character, because he felt they were the only persons who would associate with him on an equal plane.”34 Stories T h o a n d Four: Physicians managing intersexuality began to shift away from the notion of a true sex hidden in the flesh of such individuals. A deepening understanding of the naturally occurring gradation of normal sexual variance carried with it a notion of a continuum of psychological and anatomical sex differences. Still t h e absolutism of bipolar sexuality died hard, and medical science in the twentieth century insisted on “managing” the bodies of intersexed individuals by enforcing binary sex, something t h a t was impossible prior to the advances in plastic surgery. But if science was to enforce binary sex, while a t t h e same time denying t h a t in the case of intersexuals there was one single indicator (chromosomes, genitals, etc.) t h a t could infallibly be invoked as the arbiter of sex identity, there had to be a new measure. This measure was provided by the concept of “gender identity” developed in the work of scientists such as John Money and Robert Stoller. Gender identity was defined as a person’s inner experience of gender, a person’s feelings of maleness or femaleness. Money argued t h a t gender identity, although a psychosocial phenomena and thus not innate, is indelibly imprinted by early childhood rearing within the first 4 ‘/z years of age. While advocating sex assignment based on presenta- Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body tion of external genitalia for infants, Money insisted t h a t the sex of older children and adults is determined by their gender identity, and argued t h a t i t was impossible to then physically impose a change of sex t h a t would go contrary to t h a t gender identity. Here a psychosocial process, not a physiological marker, was held to determine appropriate surgical and hormonal interventions. In this way, the physician was seen as once again insuring psychological health through modifying bodily “deformities,” but always in line with the binarism of womanlman. Story Three: The stage is now set for trannsexuals to argue t h a t t h e i r core gender identity, which Stoller defines as a “person’s unquestioned certainty t h a t he [sic] belongs to one of only two sexes,”35was i n tension with their physical sex. This, in t u r n , provides t h e foundation for “the transsexual experience’’ i n t h e U.S.and Europe.36Transsexuals, unlike intersexuals, had no physiological justification for surgical and hormonal sex change. But t h e development of the notion of gender identity and the use of plastic surgery to manage psychological health provided transsexuals with a rationale to gain t h e support of t h e medical establishment. As Bernice H a u s m a n i n Changing Sex explains, “by demanding sex change, transsexuals distinguished themselves from transvestite and homosexual subjects-the other designations available in the sexological discourses of the period to identify cross-sex proclivities-and t h u s engaged actively i n producing themselves as Transsexuals not only believed themselves to be the other sex; they demanded to be made into the other sex. They wished to be transformed. Comparison: The transsexual who turns to the medical establishment to obtain hormones and plastic surgery t h a t will make her or him into the opposite sex is quite different from the Brazilian trauestis who denies being either man or woman, though the trauestis, like the transsexual, turns t o hormones and plastic surgery to craft t h e appropriately gendered (or should I say sexed?) bodily manifestations. Despite certain important similarities, these are different intra-actions. A transsexual identity turns on a notion of true, original sex to which one really belongs.38The identity of trauestis exposes another possibility. Most trauestis do not think they are really women or really men, nor a r e they identified as such by others. Neither the performativity of transvestites who desire to perform the other sex, nor the transformativity of transsexuals who desire to be the other sex fits the material-discursive intra-action of trauestis. The point is that neither sex nor gender is a static entity. As Andrea Cornwall phrases it, “people gender others and actively create, perform, and modify their own gendered identities in different settings. Bodies are not mere biological material providing a canvas for the bold strokes of gender to 67 Nancy Tuana be painted. They can be reshaped and modified to embody discourses about sexuality or gender liter all^."^^ Although I reject t h e notion of biological fixity, seeing bodies as simply cultural constructs is equally problematic. Consider this example from Dislocating Masculinity: The pervasive use of paired oppositions within the anthropology of women of the 1970s derived in large part from the influence of structuralism. Such usage privileged idealized versions of gendered difference and implied t h a t “men” and “women” a r e natural objects rather t h a n cultural constructions. Even more fundamentally, i t begged awkward questions about t h e presumed dichotomy “male” and “female.” An alternative perspective seems far more appropriate: that biology itself is a cultural construction a n d t h a t t h e link between a sexed body a n d a gendered individual is not necessary but on tin gent.^^ Such a view overlooks t h e materiality of bodies. The bodies I have here called attention to, these fleshed, pulsating, volatile bodies, are neither biologically given nor cultural constructions. They are simultaneously material-cultural. It is t h e either/or we must transform. EMBRACING DIFFERENCE I believe i n t h e difference between men a n d women. I n fact, I embrace the difference. Elizabeth Taylor Elizabeth Takes Off Orlando h a d become a woman-there is no denying it. But in every other respect, Orlando remained precisely as he had been. Virginia Woolf Orlando: A Biography I want you all to know t h a t there are only three real men on this stage-me and my two backup girls! Madonna I have r u n out of space and muddied t h e waters sufficiently for one talk, b u t indulge me in one more gesture. In t h i s case simply a set of questions. If I a m right about t h e need for a n alternative metaphysic, though I a m su re t h e re will be questions about t h e specificities of th e one I propose, how do we embody-perform it? What types of institutions and practices hold t h e axis of bipolar sex/ gender in place in our society and how can we dislodge them? 68 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body How do we destabilize both “sex” and “gender” as a normalizing narrative not only in feminist theory but in twentieth century U.S. culture? Does the current transgender movement provide an opportunity to refigure sedgender? Will these attempts to embrace differences-the performativity of drag or the constitution of transgendered individuals-succeed in destabilizing the normativity of being “normally sexed?” In what ways does heterosexism keep the axis of sex binarism in play? And what of the category of woman and the roles it plays in feminist theory and women’s studies? How do we avoid the eitherlor and embrace difference? NOTES * My use of the example of the bodybuilder in this paper was stimulated by Mark Simpson’s provocative article “Big Tits!: Masochism and Transformation in Bodybuilding,” a chapter from his Male Zmpersonators: Men Performing Masculinity (New York: Routledge, 1994). Although he puts the example to a very different use, examining t h e paradox of homoerotic desire and bodybuilding, I like to think that our approaches are complementary. I use the term intentionally here to invoke Elizabeth Grosz’s Volatile Bodies: Towards a Corporeal Feminism (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), which is one of the most exciting attempts to return feminist theorizing to the body. Nancy Tuana, “Re-Fusing NatureRVurture,” Women’sStudies Znternational Forum 6, no. 6 (1983):621-632. Sandra Harding, The Science Question in Feminism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1986). See, e.g., Anne Fausto-Sterling, Myths of Gender (New York: Basic Books, 1985); Londa Schiebinger, The Mind Has No Sex? Women in the Origins of Modern Science (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989); Nancy Leys Stephan, “Race and Gender: The Role of Analogy in Science,” Zsis 77 (1986):261-277. Nancy Tuana, The Less Noble Sex: Scientific, Religious, and Philosophical Conceptions of Woman’s Nature (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993). I borrow the notion of epistemic responsibility from Lorraine Code. She introduces t h e practice i n her book, Epistemic Responsibility (Hanover, N.H.: University Press of New England, 1987) and develops it further in What Can She Know? Feminist Theory and the Construction of Knowledge (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991) and Rhetorical Spaces: Essays on Gendered Locations (New York: Routledge, 1995). Anne Minas, Gender Basics: Feminist Perspectives on Women and Men (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth, 1993), 4. I do not intend to pick on Minas; her text is representative of a widely held perspective. Bonnie B. Spanier, Zm /partial Science: Gender Ideology in Molecular Biology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 19951, 12. lo Not only has the bulk of feminist attention been directed at gender, even when feminists attend to the body, their accounts are more likely to be what Elizabeth Grosz in “Bodies and Knowledges: Feminism and the Crisis of Reason,” Feminist Epistemologies, Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter, eds. (New York: Routledge, 1993), 187-216, has de- 69 Nancy Tuana scribed a s “inscriptive” rather t h a n “lived experience,” a phenomena I interpret as indicating a feminist discomfort in dealing with t h e flesh, compared to our dexterity in dealing with meaning. l1 Adrienne Rich, Of Woman Born: Motherhood as Experience and Institution (New York W. W. Norton, 1976). l2 I discuss this point further in “Re-Fusing NatureDJurture.” l 3 Christine Gorman, “Sizing Up the Sexes,” Time, 20 January 1992, 42-45. l4 For an account of the Wittgensteinean concept of “rendering nonsense” put to radical feminist use, see Sarah Lucia Hoagland’s “Making Mistakes, Rendering Nonsense, and Moving Toward Uncertainty,” Fetninist Interpretations of Wittgenstein, ed. Naomi Scheman (University Park: Pennsylvania State Press, forthcoming). l5 Karen Barad, “Meeting t h e Universe Half-Way: Ambiguities, Discontinuities, Quantum Subjects, and Multiple Positionings in Feminism and Plysics,” Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, Lynn Hankinson Nelson and Jack Nelson, eds. (Great Britain: Kluwer, 1996). l6 I borrow the phrase “material-semiotic” from Donna Haraway, “Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism a s a Site of Discourse on the Privilege of Partial Perspective,” Feminist Studies 14, no. 3 (1988): 575-599. Joe Weider, Bodybuilding: The Weider Approach (Chicago: Contemporary Books, 19811, 115. la Weider, Bodybuilding, 163. l9 Elizabeth Grosz, “Feminism and the Crisis of Reason” in Feminist Epistemologies, Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter, eds. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994), 197. See also her Volatile Bodies, 2o Wardell B. Pomeroy, Boys and Sex (London: Pelican, 1968), 59. 21 Mark Simpson, Male Itpersonators: Men Performing Masculinity (New York: Routledge, 19941, 41-42. z2 Barad, “Meeting the Universe Half-Way,” 22. 23 Dorothy Nelkin and M. Susan Lindee, “The Media-ted Gene: Ston e s of Race and Gender,” in Deviant Bodies: Critical Perspectives on Difference in Science and Popular Culture, Jennifer Terry and Jacqueline Urla, eds. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995), 399-400, my emphasis. 24 Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion o f Identity (New York: Routledge, 1990), 6. 25 For a n example of the ways in which language is informed by the materiality of the body see Mark Johnson’s, The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987). 26 Ann Oakley, Sex, Gender and Society (London: Temple Smith, 19721, 16. 27 Entries cited are from Random House Webster’s College Dictionary, electronic version. ** Michael Foucault, “Introduction,” in Herculine Barbin, Herculine Barbin: Being the Recently Discovered Memoirs of a Nineteenth-century French Hermaphrodite, translated by Richard McDougall (Brighton, England: Harvester Press, 1980), vii. 29 Anne Fausto-Sterling, “The Five Sexes: Why Male and Female Are Not Enough,” The Sciences (MarcWApril 1993): 20. 30 Fausto-Sterling, “The Five Sexes,” 23. 70 Fleshing Gender, Sexing the Body 31 My analysis here is based on Andrea Cornwall’s excellent article “Gendered Identities and Gender Ambiguity among navestis in Salvador Brazil,” in Dislocating Masculinity: Comparative Ethnographies, Andrea Cornwall and Nancy Lindisfarne, eds. (London and New York: Routledge, 1994), 111-132. 32 Cornwall, “Gendered Identities and Gender Ambiguity,” 111. 33 I am beholding here to Bernice Hausman’s complex rendition of the history of transsexualism in the U.S.and Europe in her Changing Sex: Transsexualism, Technology, and the Idea of Gender (Durham: Duke University Press, 1995). 34 Hausman, Changing Sex, 53-54. 35 Robert Stoller, Sex and Gender: On the Development of Masculinity and Feminity (New York: Science House, 19681, 39. 36 I a m not convinced t h a t “the transsexual experience” is quite as uniform and universal as Hausman makes it out to be. 37 Hausman, Changing Sex, 111. 38 Although this insistence on an experienced true sex contrary to the sex of their body may have been opportunistic in some cases since transsexuals are dependent upon the medical establishment, autobiographical accounts belie such opportunism being a common practice. 39 Cornwall, “Gendered Identities and Gender Ambiguity,” 114-115. 40 Andrea Cornwall and Nancy Lindisfarne, eds. Dislocating Masculinity: Comparative Ethnographies (London and New York: Routledge, 1994), 34, my emphasis. It is important here to note that Cornwall and Lindisfarne are not embracing this view but offering it as a widely held tenet of constructionist theories. Cornwall, in her article and this introduction, embraces a position similar to my own. 71