What Is Good Care, and What Is Bad?

Transcription

What Is Good Care, and What Is Bad?
48
What Is Good Care, and What Is Bad?
David M. Cutler
Introduction: The Story of Sal
I would like to tell you about a fellow named Sal. Don’t worry; I made
him up.1 But imagine he is real.
Sal is a 60-year-old white male. He is slightly overweight, is borderline
diabetic, and smokes half a pack per day. But otherwise Sal is in good
health. Aside from minor ailments, Sal has never been very sick. Sal’s
doctor periodically advises him to lose weight, take medication for his
diabetes, and stop smoking, but Sal has always felt fine.
Increasingly, however, Sal feels chest pain when walking up stairs or
running to catch the subway. After some nagging, Sal visits his primary
care physician. The doctor suspects angina and refers Sal to a cardiologist, who does a variety of tests. The results are not great. Sal has probable heart disease.
Cardiac catheterization, a procedure to measure how well blood flows
to the heart, is performed. Significant narrowing is detected in one of the
arteries supplying blood to Sal’s heart. A heart attack won’t happen next
week, but will in the next few years. The cardiologist recommends angioplasty, a procedure to open the clogged artery and insert a mesh tube to
keep it open. The procedure is successful, and the artery is reopened.
Fortunately, insurance pays the $20,000 bill.
The cardiologist sends Sal back to the primary care physician, along
with some recommendations: nitrate pills for periods of intensive pain;
aspirin and beta blockers as well; more regular use of diabetes medication; absolutely no smoking; switch to non-fat milk instead of whole
milk; use salt only in moderation; and exercise regularly.
Defining the Health Care Challenge
Sal has the best of intentions. He starts taking the medications more
regularly, and switches to a salt substitute. After years of his wife’s entreaties, he finally gives up cigarettes. He walks 30 minutes a day, three times
a week, for two weeks. But life soon catches up. The medication needs
refilling, and there is no time. Sal’s weight, which fell at first, increases
again. It is hard to exercise in winter, Sal tells himself; when the weather
is nicer, he’ll begin the exercise program.
Come time for his annual physical, Sal feels ashamed of his lack of
progress. He grudgingly goes to the doctor a half-year later than he
should. The doctor repeats the unfollowed advice. Sal again tries to comply. Walking is resumed and red meat consumption is lowered, at least for
a time. Medications are back in use. But old habits are hard to break. In
just a few months, most of the progress is gone. This cycle continues for
a few years: recommendations are given, acted on for a while, and then
discarded. Sal’s visits to his doctor become progressively less regular.
Five years later, Sal pays the price. He has a massive heart attack. Sal
is rushed to the hospital and stabilized. Bypass surgery is performed two
days later, at a cost of $50,000 (thank God for insurance!). The surgery
keeps Sal alive, but there are complications. Sal’s heart doesn’t pump that
well anymore, and fluid builds up in his lungs. Over the next three years,
Sal is in and out of hospitals with pneumonia, heart, and respiratory
complications. At age 68, Sal dies.
Did Sal Receive Good Care?
Considering everything, how do we evaluate this story? Did Sal receive
good or bad medical care? Could things have gone better? If so, how?
Since this is a participatory conference, I want to take a survey. How
many of you believe that Sal received good medical care? How many
believe that Sal received bad medical care? I would say about three-quarters believe that he received good medical care, and one-quarter say that
he received bad medical care.
Sal is interesting because he shows how the medical system works—the
good and the bad. I want to use this case as an example of the kinds of
things that go right and wrong to illustrate the challenges that Cathy
Minnehan correctly raised.
David M. Cutler 49
The correct answer is that Sal received both good and bad medical
care. All the medical procedures that Sal received, if I understand correctly what my physician friends have told me, were appropriate. They
either alleviated the immediate symptoms or they saved his life. Angioplasty alleviated his immediate symptoms, bypass surgery saved his life,
and the medication and lifestyle recommendations he was given were
appropriate. This is state-of-the-art medical care.
But was it worth it? Did the benefits exceed the costs? The golden rule
of economics is that you do something if the benefits are greater than the
costs. In this case, if you consider the time when Sal had his heart attack,
the costs are the up-front treatment, including all those spiffy things that
he got in the hospital, plus the downstream costs of caring for him after
he survived. The primary benefit is the expectation of longer and higher
quality of life. There is also a personal dimension: whether people were
satisfied with the care they received. Finally, there are some financial
implications that may be either positive or negative. In this case, they are
mostly negative. For example, keeping Sal alive means that he collects
Social Security and other benefits. So these costs represent a reduction for
everybody else in the amount of money (resources) they have for goods
and services, and these costs offset the benefits to him and to us of Sal’s
living a longer life.
Totaling up the benefits and the costs, the balance sheet looks as shown
in Table 3.1, below:
Table 3.1
Benefits and Costs of Sal’s Treatment
Benefits
Costs
• Expectation of longer and higher• quality of life
• Upfront treatment costs (tPA,
• aspirin, primary angioplasty, beta
• blockers, etc.)
• Patient/family satisfaction with care
• Financial implications for others of
• keeping a person alive and/or
• healthy
• Downstream treatment costs
• Financial implications for others of
• keeping a person alive and/or
• healthy
• Other downstream costs
50
Defining the Health Care Challenge
We can think about asking whether care is worth it or not in the case
of Sal—or in the case of the medical system as a whole—by trying to
take account of the costs and the benefits of care. Sal’s case is actually
emblematic of the medical system as a whole.
Weighing the Evidence: The Net Gain from Recent Medical Advances
The discussion below is based on a decade of research on changes in
treatment standards over the past half-century in three important areas:
cardiovascular disease, low-birth-weight babies, and care for the mentally ill. Many more details can be found in my recent book, Your Money
or Your Life (Cutler 2004).
Changes in Medical Care for Severe Heart Disease
If you go back a couple of decades, to, say, 1950—Sal’s therapy would
have been bed rest. The 1950 standard of care for severe heart disease
(myocardial infarction, or MI) was bed rest for six months or more. So
rather than getting all those fancy procedures in the hospital, they would
have put him in bed for at least six months. The direct cost of this care
was minimal (although the opportunity cost to the patient and his family
may have been high). One can think about other costs, like the fact that
the person is not working and that he is perhaps supported through some
other programs. Conceptually, I include the reduced value of transfer
payments on the benefit side. Here, I just want to think about the medical costs.
In contrast, the 2000 standard of care for MI involves technologies
such as thrombolytics and revascularization—procedures whose direct
cost is high. Just to give you a sense of the magnitude, the direct cost of
cardiovascular disease care per 45-year-old rose from about $0 to about
$30,000 in present value terms over the last half of the twentieth century.
The reason we spend more in caring for heart disease today than in the
1950s and 1960s is that we do more. And that is true across the board.
As Cathy Minnehan mentioned, medical spending currently represents
15 percent of the economy. It’s going to be 18 percent. And the reason for
this is that we can do more.
Net Gains
One cares not just about what is spent, but about the return on spending.
As I said, there are a number of components to this reform. The most
important is how long a person lives. In this case, Sal probably lived
about five years longer because he had the care, much of it of reasonably
good quality. Actually, there’s a whole industry of people who go out and
measure the length of life and quality of life. Let me tell you a little about
what they have found.
As Figure 3.1 shows, cardiovascular disease mortality has declined by
over 50 percent since 1950. Put in terms of years of life, the average 45year-old will live another four and one-half years because cardiovascular
900
800
700
600
Surgeon General’s
smoking report
500
Anti-hypertension
medications
400
Spread of invasive
technologies
300
200
100
90
80
00
20
19
19
19
70
60
19
50
19
40
19
30
19
20
19
19
10
0
00
Changes in Medical Care for People Suffering from Depression
The 1950 standard of care for people suffering from depression involved
institutionalization in a mental hospital for the very ill, with very little
care for those with milder symptoms. Procedures for treating the severely
ill in institutions included lobotomy, electroconvulsive therapy, and insulin therapy. Two of those, thankfully, have been laid to rest. The 2000
standard for treating depression includes selective serotonin reuptake
inhibitors (SSRIs), antidepressants, and advances in psychotherapy such
as cognitive behavior therapy and other techniques. The advances in
treatment options for depression over the past half-century enable more
people to be treated more effectively. However, as a price to be paid for
this progress, spending on depression has doubled in the past 20 years, as
many more people are diagnosed with depression than were in the past.
Defining the Health Care Challenge
19
Changes in Medical Care for Low-Birth-Weight Infants
The 1950 standard for treating low-birth-weight infants was to use the
first generation of incubators and to experiment with warming and other
intuitive actions. These treatments were available at a very low cost. But
again, they were not very effective. In 2000, low-birth-weight infants can
be treated in sophisticated neonatology units, employing ventilators and
artificial “surfactant.”2 These treatments are quite costly: the cost per
low-birth-weight infant rose from about $0 in 1950 to about $70,000
in 2000.
52
Deaths per 100,000
David M. Cutler 51
Figure 3.1
Mortality from Cardiovascular Disease
Source: Vital Statistics of the United States (2000).
disease mortality has declined. Several factors have been important in this
trend, among them the marked decline in mortality rates that followed
the release of the Surgeon General’s report on the dangers of smoking,
the wide adoption of anti-hypertension medications, and the spread of
invasive technologies to treat cardiovascular disease. My estimate is that
about two-thirds of the increase in longevity—or roughly three years
of increased life—results from medical intervention, with most of the
remainder due to smoking cessation.
Let me now combine the costs and benefits of medical care. Since 1950,
we have spent about $30,000 per 45-year-old and obtained in return
about three years of longer life. And so your second quiz question is,
is it worth it? The correct answer is, yes, it is worth it. In case you’re
wondering, the present value of the benefits calculated by a methodology
I won’t go through—it will be familiar to most of the economists here
and is based on valuing risks to life and using that information to infer
the value of traditional life years—is about $120,000, yielding a rate of
return of four to one. Let me know when banks start paying that return
on their deposits, and I will sign right up. Indeed, when you look at quite
David M. Cutler 53
a number of medical interventions, they have benefits that are substantially greater than the costs, as Figure 3.2 shows.
What is going on in Figure 3.2 is that people value their health highly;
two-thirds of Americans rank health care as a top item for an expanding
economy. Most Americans are willing to pay the equivalent of $100,000
to save a year of life. Most of us have enough money to provide for the
basics in life: food, clothing, shelter, and basic medical care. And so, as
we get richer, we want to extend the quantity and improve the quality of
our lives. Medical advance costs a lot, but is worth it. That is why the
“R” word (rationing) cannot be uttered in polite company in the United
States.
Let me come back to the big picture. Why do we spend more now on
medical care? In part because we are well insured, and in part because the
technology is worth it. Now, that does not mean we can afford to keep
doing it; but as an approximate matter, what is going on with medical
spending is that we spend a lot more because we get a lot more. At least
8
7
Benefits/Costs
6
5
54
Defining the Health Care Challenge
by my estimation, on the whole it is worth it. So, Sal, and we, as a whole,
are actually doing fairly well. Why shouldn’t we spend our money on
being healthier?
The Glass Is Half-Empty
Sal: The Sad Part of the Story
So, that’s the good side. The bad side is what was not done for Sal.
Although medical care bought Sal years of life, many things that should
have been done were not. No one followed up on his adherence over
time to the recommended lifestyle changes. This, too, is state-of-the-art
medicine. No one helped Sal with medications, side effects, or any other
complicated issue of managing disease.
Consider poor old Sal. He was told, “Change your life.” So, here he is,
a 60-year-old man who all his life has been obese and has not taken care
of himself. He goes to the doctor and the doctor says, “You know what,
Sal? You really ought to make these major lifestyle improvements. Why
don’t you go away and do that?” Well, of course, he’s going to have difficulty doing that. Every one of us has difficulty doing that. Next week,
I’m giving up cookies. I promise. So, the single biggest problem in Sal’s
story is that Sal’s chronic disease was not well controlled. We could have
saved a lot of money, at least in the short term, and extended his life by
many years, had we controlled it better.
4
3
2
1
0
Cardiovascular Heart
disease
attack
1950–90
1984–98
Low-birth- Depression
1991–96
weight
infants
1950–90
Figure 3.2
Benefit/Cost Ratio of Medical Care in America
Source: Author’s calculations.
Breast
cancer
1985–96
Medical
care
combined
1950–2000
We Know We Can Do Better
What would good prevention look like? I will give you just one example,
that of HealthPartners, an HMO in Minneapolis that decided a few years
ago that it was going to focus on improved care for diabetics like Sal. The
primary components of diabetes management programs are the dissemination of guidelines, provider education, member education, screening
programs, performance feedback to physicians, patient reminders, case
management, and at-risk lists. The HMO went to the doctors and said,
“We’re going to give you profiles of how well your diabetic patients are
doing compared with other doctors’ diabetic patients. Then we’re going
to contact the patients and make sure they come in, to see whether they
are taking their medications and, if they are not, why not.” This is not
David M. Cutler 55
very intensive stuff. Still, the HMO showed significant improvements in
the care for diabetics, all as a result of low-tech care. This is not inventing
a spiffy new way to treat people once they have kidney failure. This is
figuring out ways to get people to do what’s best for them. A study of the
outcomes of this program showed a dramatic decline in patients’ mean
HbA1c levels3 from 1994, when the program began, to 2000 (see Figure
3.3 below).
There are other similar examples—Kaiser Permanente in California,
for instance—where people have shown that it is, in fact, possible to do
much better in managing chronic disease.
The real question is, why is Sal’s case so typical? Why isn’t more
being done to control chronic disease? My answer is: money. The kinds
of information technology that you would need in order to work with
patients are not reimbursed at all. There’s no reimbursement for anything
other than a doctor seeing a patient. Take the simplest example: what
share of doctors communicate regularly by email with their patients? I
can email virtually everybody in my life with the exception of my doctor.
The share of doctors who communicate regularly with their patients by
8.8
Mean HbA1c levels for diabetic
patients, HealthPartners
8.6
8.4
8.2
8.0
7.8
7.6
7.4
7.2
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
Figure 3.3
Improvement in Diabetes Management from Low-Tech Care at HealthPartners,
Minneapolis
Source: Beaulieu et al. (2007).
56
Defining the Health Care Challenge
email is 3 percent, which is smaller than the share of priests who are on
email. I think it’s even smaller than the share of people who communicate
with the Lord by email.
And, by the way, if you ask any doctor why they don’t communicate
via email, the reason is because they are not paid for it. I once knew an
HMO that was trying to figure out whether it could set up email for only
those employers that agreed to pay for it, even though there was no additional cost to provide it to everybody.
One result is that we spend a lot more than we need to on people when
they get sick. We also substitute intensive care for lifestyle chronic disease
care. If you ask, “What is the single biggest difference between care in,
say, the United States and care in Canada?” the answer would probably be
that in the United States, Sal got his angioplasty when he was feeling chest
pain; while in Canada, they would have told him to take his statin drug,
exercise more, and try to lose weight. The net results are that our health
care system is much more expensive than Canada’s. Both could be effective.
Indeed, if you look at Jack Wennberg’s work at Dartmouth (Wennberg,
Fisher, and Skinner, 2002), areas of the country that spend more don’t
have sicker patients going in, and probably don’t have healthier patients
coming out—although I must admit, I’m a bit less convinced of that—and,
on the whole, don’t have more satisfied patients. What happens when you
spend more is that doctors do more. Sometimes, it is needless stuff, that
is, testing that doesn’t need to happen; at other times, it is substituting
intensive testing for lifestyle changes that people could make.
The net impact is mixed. Figure 3.4 shows the division of medical care
along two axes: should the care be provided—a statement about whether
the care has benefits greater than costs—and whether the care is provided. The happy situations are where appropriate care is provided and
inappropriate care is not provided.
Unfortunately, what we get is too much of the other boxes. In Figure
3.4, those other boxes represent the two kinds of mistakes that are made.
The box on the top right represents things that are done that should not
be done. This includes intensive procedures that are used when simpler
interventions would do, and unnecessary testing that happens because
doctors are paid for it. There are different guesses as to how much money
that represents. Twenty percent seems like a lot. Actually, Jack Wennberg
David M. Cutler 57
Should Be Done
No
Yes
J
Overused care
(20% of health)
No
Underused care
(10% of health)
J
Is Done
Yes
Figure 3.4
Overall Assessment of the Level of Care Being Provided
Source: Author’s calculations.
at Dartmouth says it is 30 percent. My colleague Michael Porter at Harvard Business School thinks it is even higher (Porter and Teisberg 2006).
There’s a fair amount of money in there. And, this does not even include
administrative expenses. This is just medical care that is provided, but is
probably not doing much good beyond what we could accomplish otherwise. So, you could save that 20 percent, at least.
On the other hand, there is the bottom-left quadrant, where things that
should be done are not being done. Nobody has a great guess as to what
it would cost to do these things. My own personal guess is that we could
spend about 10 percent more on medicine by, for example, dealing better
with Sal and his chronic disease. What would that involve? Having him
come to the doctor, get tests, and take medication. Similarly, uninsured
people should get more care. After all, if we didn’t want them to get
more care, why would we want them to have insurance? My rough guess
is that if we waved a magic wand and started doing all the right things,
and stopped doing all the needless ones, we might save about 10 percent
of our medical care spending on a net basis, but we would actually have
remarkably improved health.
Getting to the Promised Land: Three Strategies
So, how do we get there? The Holy Grail of health care reform is cost,
access, and quality. People want costs to be lower, access to be higher, and
quality to be better. And so, how does one deal with this analysis that suggests that while we are doing pretty well on the whole, there are some very
58
Defining the Health Care Challenge
gross errors? There are three strategies that are out there. I will try to give
you a very brief overview of them and tell you a bit about how I lean.
The first strategy is consumer-directed health care, which entails making health care more of a market. This strategy includes greater cost sharing, more information provision, and related interventions. This solution
comes out of the literature that worries a lot about the overuse of medical care. And, indeed, everything that we know from the RAND Health
Insurance experiment (Newhouse et al. 1993) suggests that increasing
cost sharing by people will lead to less use of care, and that would be
good on the overuse dimension. What people worry about is whether
this will exacerbate the problem of underused care. When people give up
care, who is to say that the care that is saved is only the low-valued care?
Some evidence suggests that it is not (Huskamp et al. 2003).
The second strategy is the single-payer system: lower fees, restrictions
on what is done, and lower administrative expense. This approach is
also, to a great extent, designed to address the issue of care overuse, since
the United States spends more on health care than other countries do.
But will the single-payer approach do anything on the prevention side?
Most of the evidence we have from other countries—some of them single-payer—is that they actually don’t do much better on prevention than
the United States does. All medical systems are geared towards high-tech
treatment. Some just do more of it, while others do less of it. So, I worry
that health would not improve in a single-payer system.
The third broad direction is payment reform—paying for performance,
not quantity. This strategy is primarily designed to address underused
care, by paying doctors to do things that they ought to do. The primary
concern that people have with respect to this strategy is: will it actually
save money or will it just lead to more care, and will providers game this
system in some way? There is enormous debate about this, which other
speakers will address. My personal belief is that this is the best way to go,
since both underuse and overuse are significant problems.
I cannot resist ending on a cautionary note. In the past few decades,
there have been any number of “magic cures” for health care. The prospective payment system was going to be great. Managed care was going
to be great. Provider integration was going to be great. Provider disintegration was going to be great. Having insurers provide medical care was
David M. Cutler 59
going to save the world. Having providers and insurers be separate was
going to solve our problems. We have gone through various fads, and we
need to be cautious about all of these ideas. In fact, this is where I want to
leave things: in the religious world, they have been searching for the Holy
Grail for 2,000 years. In health care, we have only been searching for 100
years, so we have quite a way to go. That is not to say we shouldn’t try
these approaches, but just to say that we should be a bit skeptical about
our ability to work wonders.
Notes
1. For the curious, Salus is the Roman god of health.
2. “Surfactant” is a fluid secreted by the cells of the alveoli (the tiny air sacs in
the lungs) that serves to reduce the surface tension of pulmonary fluids and thus
keep the lung from collapsing.
3. The test measures the amount of glycosylated hemoglobin (hemoglobin molecules that have become chemically linked to glucose) in the blood. The test gives
a good estimate of how well diabetes is being managed over time.
References
Beaulieu, N., D. M. Cutler, K. Ho, G. Isham, T. Lindquist, A. Nelson, and
P. O’Connor. 2007. The business case for disease management for managed care
organizations. Forum for Health Economics and Policy 9 (Frontiers in Health
Policy Research), Article 1.
Cutler, D. M., 2004. Your Money or Your Life: Strong Medicine for America’s
Health Care. New York: Oxford University Press.
Huskamp, H. A., P. A. Deverka, A. M. Epstein, R. S. Epstein, R. G. Frank, and
K. A. McGuigan. 2003. The effect of incentive-based formularies on prescription-drug utilization and spending. New England Journal of Medicine 349:
2224–32.
Newhouse, J. P. and the Insurance Experiment Group. 1993. Free For All: Lessons from the Rand Health Insurance Experiment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Porter, M. E. and E. O. Teisberg. 1996. Redefining Health Care: Creating Positive
Sum Competition to Deliver Value. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School
Press.
Wennberg, J. E., E. S. Fisher, and J. S. Skinner. 2002. Geography and the debate
of Medicare reform. Health Affairs, Web Exclusive. http://content.healthaffairs.
org/cgi/content/full/ hlthaff.w2.96v1/DC1.
62
The Health Care Challenge: Some Perspectives
from Behavioral Economics
Richard G. Frank
Introduction
Health economists, led by David Cutler, have brought into question the
long-held proposition that most of the increases in health care spending
consist of waste and inefficiency. Cutler makes a strong case that, on
average, the growth in spending has been used to purchase care whose
value exceeds the value of the outlays. Advances in medical technology
and knowledge have produced these gains. At the same time, it is widely
acknowledged that the U.S. health care system operates some distance
from its efficiency frontier. The point of departure for economists seeking
to address such issues is to consider the traditional incentive problems
in health insurance markets that stem from adverse selection and moral
hazard, which are clearly important.
However, rapid increases in medical spending and dissatisfaction with
quality of care appear to be nearly universal in Western nations that
operate under vastly different health care rationing arrangements. David
Cutler’s analysis of health care delivery in the United States consists of
two main parts. The first assesses empirically whether, on average, the
gains in health over time are comparable in value to the rise in spending
on medical care that has produced them. The second part begins with an
acknowledgment that we are unlikely to be on the efficiency frontier and
argues for a “pay-for-performance” approach to improving health care
delivery in the United States. In this essay, I focus on a few behaviors
related to medical decision-making that may help to explain why the
health care system operates at some distance from the efficiency frontier.
I also concentrate on aspects of the psychology of decision-making that
Defining the Health Care Challenge
may be important to the design of pay-for-performance schemes. My aim
is not to provide a comprehensive review of issues, but rather to highlight
a few fundamental ideas from behavioral economics that may offer some
insights beyond those provided by the traditional mode of health economics analysis regarding why the health care delivery system performs
the way it does.1
My remarks are organized into three additional sections. First, I offer
a cursory review of the performance of the U.S. health care delivery system. Second, I identify two behavioral economics concepts that may have
particularly strong power to explain some of the observed patterns of
performance: “status quo bias” and “unrealistic optimism.” I then apply
a third idea from behavioral economics that is related to some proposed
supply-side remedies to the cost and quality problem: the “psychological response to complex pricing schemes.” The final section of the paper
offers some concluding observations.
Health Care Spending and Value
The United States spent roughly $1.99 trillion or 16 percent of gross
domestic product (GDP) on health care in 2005.2 Health care spending is also growing at an annual rate of 7.8 percent, a rate that is 2.7
percentage points higher than the rate of growth in GDP for that period
(5.1 percent). These trends are a return to historical patterns that were
interrupted briefly during the late 1990s (1996 to 1999), the era of managed care. The popular press and many policy analysts view the growth
in health care spending as unsustainable. Students of the federal budget
note that the share of the federal budget accounted for by health expenditures, currently about 16 percent, is expected to rise to 21 percent in
2017, and will equal the size of all current federal outlays by the year
2070 (CBO 2007, Table 3-1).
David Cutler and others have noted that deciding whether health spending is too low or too high requires considering the value of what health
expenditures purchase (Cutler 2004). Dramatic advances in medical science have produced cures where none previously existed—treatments
that allow people to function effectively in society where previously they
Richard G. Frank 63
would have been disabled and dependent, as well as procedures that can
be administered in a physician’s office that would have required many
days in a hospital just a few years ago. Thus, the technical frontier of
medicine has expanded enormously over the past 20 years. Cutler’s analysis uses changes over time in medical spending and health outcomes
to assess whether the gains in health have been worth the extra outlays
on health services. Using case studies on infant health, cardiovascular
disease, and depression, he offers persuasive evidence that average productivity of spending on medical care has been rising. This is very important because it has shifted the debate from the idea that most additional
medical care spending in the United States stems from price increases and
produces little in the way of increased health.
Cutler’s insights have encouraged other analyses that point in similar
directions. For example, Thorpe and colleagues decompose the source of
expenditure growth for the 15 medical conditions that account for the
highest rates of nominal growth in health care spending (Thorpe, Florence, and Joski 2004). They decompose changes in spending into changes
in the cost per treated case, number of cases treated, and population
(growth and composition). For 7 of the top 15 conditions, they show that
changes in treated disease prevalence account for 40 percent or more of
the increase in spending, an indication that more people are getting some
treatment for important illnesses. In addition, for several of the disease
categories for which spending growth is being driven by the cost per case,
there is evidence of important gains in health outcomes; this is the case
with heart disease, as discussed by Cutler.
Cutler’s analysis recognizes features of health care delivery that suggest inefficiency. He notes a variety of troubling reports that suggest that
the health care system does not operate on the technical frontier and
that there is, in fact, a great deal of poor quality in American health
care (Institute of Medicine 2001; McGlynn et al. 2003). Research has
also established that there is vast variation in the costs of providing
health care to various patient populations located in different regions of
the country. For example, in 1999, it cost 103 percent more to provide
health care to Medicare beneficiaries living in Miami than to those in
Minneapolis. The difference cannot be accounted for by demographic
64
Defining the Health Care Challenge
differences, health care prices, or health status (Wennberg and Cooper
1997). Together, these reports suggest that the health sector does not
produce on the production frontier and often does not minimize the cost
of producing health or health improvements.
What Cutler’s analysis does not say is either (1) how health care is
not efficient, or (2) whether efficiency is improving over time. This then
leaves open questions of how one might want to change the organization and financing of health care. Cutler’s prescription for improving the
value of health care spending or efficiency is based on his observation
that health care payment systems in the United States do not typically
reward the outcomes that we want. Hence, he sees pay-for-performance
(P4P) schemes as a step towards paying for the kinds of outcomes that
efficiency dictates and Americans want. Cutler is not alone in his enthusiasm for P4P. There has been a recent rush by payers to implement such
policies (Rosenthal et al. 2004; Institute of Medicine 2007). I believe
that it is worth stepping back to consider how doctors make decisions
and whether the “rationality” that is behind P4P is present to a sufficient degree to warrant the current enthusiasm. This raises two specific
questions:
(1) If physicians are rational and money oriented, how do they respond
to P4P schemes?
(2) If physicians are not entirely rational and money oriented, how do
they respond to P4P schemes?
Below, I focus mainly on the second question and leave most of the first
question for another time.
Inertia, Optimism, and Complexity
In this section, I concentrate on the inertia of professionals, or what has
been termed status quo bias in decision-making and unrealistic optimism by professionals, in the context of a highly complex and uncertain decision-making environment. I will also examine the psychology
of responses to complex payment environments. These concepts will be
applied to help explain the inefficiency in health care delivery and the
possible difficulties with P4P as a remedy.
Richard G. Frank 65
Inertia or Status Quo Bias
Thaler has identified a general tendency of people to exaggerate the value
of an item they possess (selling price) relative to how they would value
the same item if they did not own it (buying price) (Thaler 1980). This
has been termed the “endowment effect.” Samuelson and Zeckhauser
make some related observations regarding the tendency of people to
exaggerate their preference for the current state of affairs (Samuelson
and Zeckhauser 1988). This occurs in the context of more complex circumstances (choices over multiple goods or complicated attributes) and
has been termed status quo bias. These apparent anomalies in decisionmaking have been linked to reference points and strong loss aversion. A
number of experimental studies have provided evidence that status quo
bias occurs under a variety of circumstances in which decisions are made
under uncertainty.
For example, a test of status quo bias was conducted among electric
power consumers in California. Consumers were asked to indicate their
preferences over different combinations of service reliability and rates.
The respondents came from one of two groups, one with much more reliable services than the other. Each group was asked to indicate preferences
over six service-rate combinations, where one was the status quo. The
results showed that 60.2 percent of the high-reliability group chose the
status quo, and 5.7 percent chose the low-reliability option, which came
with a 30 percent decline in rates. In the low-reliability group, 58 percent
chose the status quo, and 5.8 percent selected the high-reliability option,
which came with a 30 percent increase in rates (Hartman, Doane, and
Woo 1991). The results suggest that people are reluctant to adopt a new
service or to even-handedly evaluate new choices.
The departure of everyday medical practice from recommended evidence-based medical practice has been widely documented. A recent
study examined the quality of care for 30 chronic and acute conditions
as well as for some preventive practices (McGlynn et al. 2003, Note 3).
They found that, overall, people seeking care received about 55 percent
of recommended care. Many of these practices have been recognized for
some time in published research and by professional medical societies
as forming the basis of high-quality treatment. A recent example of offfrontier production was examined by Skinner and Staiger who found
66
Defining the Health Care Challenge
that economic incentives and budgets did not explain departures from
frontier production (Skinner and Staiger 2005). Thus, the advances in
medical treatment techniques that Cutler and others identify as driving
the health system to deliver more health care also require physicians and
other providers of medical care (hospitals and nurses) to modify treatment approaches that in numerous cases appear to have met with success
for many years. In other words, these advances require providers to alter
the status quo. The puzzle for economists is that the “costs” of adopting
these new practices are generally quite low for physicians, while the prospects for improving health outcomes are quite high. Why, then, would
professionals focused on treating the ailments of those who are most
often well-insured people not adopt these new practices?
In the context of medical decision-making and studies of diffusion of
medical knowledge and practice, status quo bias may offer a foundation
for developing a new model that explains the tendency of medical practice to cling to older methods of treatment. Prescription drug decisions
furnish an important choice to study this issue. Since physicians generally
do not gain financially based on the drugs they choose, one would expect
them to behave as “perfect agents.” For example, physicians have been
shown to favor pharmaceutical products that they were introduced to in
medical training even if newer products have been shown to be superior
(Scherer 2000). One recent study conducted in Germany examined the
characteristics of psychiatrists most likely to adopt the new generation of
anti-psychotic medications. The analysis found that the age of the psychiatrist (as a marker of how long he or she had been in practice) was the
most important variable explaining the adoption of the new drugs. Patient
characteristics had no significant effect on prescribing patterns (Haman
et al. 2004). Hellerstein (1998) studied a very simple decision, whether to
prescribe a generic drug, using U.S. data from 1989. She found that most
of the variation in the prescribing of generics was unexplained by patient,
price (insurance), and regulatory factors. As in other research, she found
that older physicians were less likely to prescribe generic products than
were younger physicians. These studies offer evidence on patterns of prescribing that are consistent with status quo bias.
The implication of status quo bias in medical decision-making is that,
while innovation in medical care will result in improved health outcomes
over time, even at levels where the benefits exceed the incremental expen-
Richard G. Frank 67
ditures, the distance between average practice and the efficiency frontier
can be substantial and will grow ever larger during times of accelerating
innovation. In terms of consequences for P4P, status quo bias will likely
attenuate any response relative to what one might expect from a “purely”
rational, money-oriented doctor. It also implies that the rewards needed
to “move practice” may be larger than expected.
Unrealistic Optimism
People tend to be overconfident. Studies of drivers and entering students
all suggest that large majorities of people believe that they are better than
average. That is, they believe they are more accomplished drivers than
the average or that they will achieve a higher grade in a course than the
average student. For listeners to National Public Radio, this is the “Lake
Woebegone” phenomenon, where all children in the community are
above average. Holding these beliefs does not mean only that one moves
through life with a more positive outlook, but rather that decision-making is potentially distorted. Such distortion in decision-making under
uncertainty has been termed unrealistic optimism (Weinstein 1980).
In the business context, overconfidence by top management (CEOs)
has been associated with the wave of mergers that took place between
1998 and 2001. During that period, about $2 trillion was spent on acquisitions. Yet, shareholders of the acquiring companies lost about $250
million as a result of those deals. This raises the question of why there
was so much enthusiasm for mergers if the deals were unfavorable for the
acquiring companies (Moeller, Schlingemann, and Stulz 2003).
In the context of a model of physician decision-making in which the
physician is treated as a Bayesian information processor, the establishment of priors and the updating of priors with new information may be
subject to distortions by unrealistic optimism.
Experimental research on optimism reveals that key among the characteristics that explain the degree of unrealistic optimism are the desirability
of the anticipated event, its perceived controllability, experience with the
event, and the perceived probability of the event (Weinstein 1980). Research
also shows that having detailed information on experiences of comparison
groups attenuates, but does not eliminate, unrealistic optimism.
Physicians are trained and function in environments that are consistent with the conditions that breed unrealistic optimism. Because they
68
Defining the Health Care Challenge
are trained to take control, physicians frequently believe that they have
considerable ability to stave off the consequences of illness. Physicians
are also charged with taking a central role in making decisions about life
itself and about the ability of individuals to function and engage in basic
human activity. Thus, the outcomes they aim to influence are highly emotionally charged and valued by their patients. A physician has frequently
dealt with particular cases on a number of occasions, in many cases with
a positive outcome. Finally, it is seldom the case that physicians have
detailed information on comparison groups to help them judge the likely
incremental outcomes of their efforts.
The consequences of unrealistic optimism in physician decision-making may be several. First, physicians may have gained confidence in
their choices as they have received additional information about a case,
even when their accuracy in, for example, making a diagnosis has been
unchanged by the information (Oskamp 1965). Thus, optimism in the
presence of clinical information will generate more testing and diagnostic
procedures. Second, unrealistic optimism may make physicians overestimate the expected benefits from administering additional treatment—possibly because they overestimate both their own abilities and the potential
impact of their preferred technologies. This can result in the provision of
excessive levels of care. Finally, the physician may imbue patients with an
overestimate of the benefits of receiving more treatment.
Data on the experience of caring for people at the end of life illustrate
these possibilities and direct us towards hypotheses about optimism in
medical care. The experience of patients at the end of life offers a disturbing reflection of medical decision-making and resource allocation that
reflects larger issues in health care delivery. Specifically, the majority of
terminally ill patients state a preference to die at home, but frequently
do not actually do so (Buntin and Huskamp 2002). Spending for care
at the end of life accounts for a large share of Medicare expenditures,
estimated at about 25 percent over the past two decades. There is considerable disagreement regarding how much this level of spending can
be reduced. However, Skinner and colleagues compare regions with the
highest and lowest deciles of physician utilization during the last six
months of life. They report utilization of diagnostic tests that differ by
factors of between 2 and 3.5. In addition, they note differences in high-
Richard G. Frank 69
intensity treatments (feeding tubes, dialysis, and ventilators) that differ
by factors of 3 to 8 (Skinner, Fisher, and Wennberg 2001). These figures
suggest potential for savings even if there are some differences in patient
preferences across regions. Strikingly, patterns of end-of-life care do not
vary substantially according to insurance arrangements (Experton et al.
1997). Thus, spending levels and the ability to deliver care consonant
with people’s preferences do not appear to be driven primarily by payment incentives.
Unrealistic optimism appears to play a central role in clinical decisionmaking at the end of life, as physicians tend to overestimate the duration
of survival. Lamont and Christakis studied the prognostication abilities
of physicians treating cancer patients in hospices (Lamont and Christakis
2001). The median physician estimate of survival time was 75 days after
admission to hospice, while the median actual survival time was 26 days.
In addition, physicians then communicate more optimistic prognoses to
patients than they actually believe. In the Lamont and Christakis study
of cancer patients, for instance, physicians reported optimistic outlooks
for patients to their colleagues about 12 percent of the time, whereas the
same physicians reported optimistic outlooks to the same patients 41
percent of the time (Christakis 1999). The true prognosis was communicated to only 37 percent of the cancer patients. The unrealistic optimism
potentially affects both the physician’s decisions about the therapies to
pursue and the patient’s demand for care. Optimism has been posited to
lead physicians to overprescribe intensive interventions aimed at cure,
while under-referring to hospice (Lamont and Christakis 2001). Some
research has observed that terminally ill patients who overestimate their
expected survival time are far more likely to demand intensive “curative” care relative to palliative treatment (Weeks et al. 1998). Optimism
therefore drives care towards high-intensity treatment that is unlikely to
generate many clinical benefits, and away from the use of hospice, an
arrangement that may better serve the desires of well-informed patients.
Unrealistic optimism is likely to be important in medical decisionmaking in a range of other areas as well. It probably contributes to the
emphasis on high-intensity medical care in the United States and for offfrontier performance of the health care system. Clearly, other economic
and professional influences are also at work in this case, but it is likely
70
Defining the Health Care Challenge
that unrealistic optimism about technology and the ability to apply it
have played a key role. Unrealistic optimism may result in a diminished
response to P4P schemes, since physicians may be hard to convince that
they are not currently doing “the right thing.” In addition, physicians
may be resistant to schemes that “undervalue” their efforts. Corporate
CEOs have responded in an analogous fashion when capital markets
have tended to undervalue their investment and acquisition decisions.
Complexity and the Limits to Supply-Side Fixes
Policymakers in the health sector have moved quickly in recent years to
adopt measures that aim to address quality and cost problems by the
implementation of P4P schemes (Rosenthal et al. 2004). Under these
arrangements, health plans implement various types of payments that
reward achieving levels of performance on quality indicators (in some
cases, performance is relative—for example, top 20 percent—in others, it
is absolute). One health plan, for instance, used data on physicians with
respect to whether they screened for breast, cervical, and prostate cancer
as well as for high cholesterol, and whether they managed diabetes and
instituted other prevention programs. The plan paid $20 per patient to
those doctors in the top quartile of performance, and $10 per patient
to those between the 50th and 75th percentiles. Hundreds of such payment arrangements are being adopted around the country. The appeal
is clear. Demand does appear to be very sensitive to quality or performance differences. Prices of health care are generally administered so that
higher-quality providers cannot charge more than others, and so there are
incentives to underprovide quality if improvement is costly. Such schemes
tend to assume that market participants (doctors and hospitals) exhibit a
high level of economic rationality.
Even standard economic models that assume rationality raise cautions
regarding the enthusiasm for P4P schemes. Principal-agent models, for
example, lead to concerns with multi-tasking or “teaching to the test,”
whereby the outcomes upon which one pays will improve, while other
outcomes that are valued but not well measured or not rewarded will
be neglected and may decline. Recent research on P4P offers some evidence to suggest that multitasking behavior takes place among physicians
(Mullen, Frank, and Rosenthal 2007). Other institutional features and
Richard G. Frank 71
behavioral phenomena may also be important in determining the impact
of P4P.
The health care delivery system is very complex, with each provider
typically serving 10 to 15 different public and private payers. Thus,
payment methods, quality guidelines, level of care criteria, formularies,
and coverage arrangements for patients will differ from payer to payer.
Within each plan, payment arrangements are complicated, and the benefit
designs facing individual patients are typically highly nonlinear and frequently dependent on prior treatment choices. This complexity requires
that physicians be able to process large amounts of information in the
context of strict time constraints to make optimizing choices. Recent theoretical and empirical analyses suggest, however, that the ability to do so
may be quite limited.
If we consider layering P4P schemes on top of existing payment systems—which for most physicians consist of mixes of capitation, fee for
service, and case rates, and also frequently include productivity bonuses,
pharmacy performance bonuses (sometimes related to generic prescribing), and some straight hourly payments for a set of 10 to 15 payers—the
typical physician faces a very complicated price schedule. Liebman and
Zeckhauser (2004) argue that complex price schedules have the potential
to confuse physicians and patients and to increase the market power of
the organizations establishing the pricing schemes. They postulate that
people respond to the complexity in pricing schemes by adopting simple
rules to govern behavior. The design of the pricing schemes in anticipation of the psychological response to the complexity is key to determining
whether the pricing schemes enhance or harm social welfare.
The health care system has had a variety of experiences with complex
payment methods. A recent paper by Glied and Zivin (2002) examines
physician behavior in the face of multiple incentive systems. They find
that observed physician behavior does not respond to the incentives associated with the marginal patient in the way that simple profit maximization would predict. Instead, their empirical results show that the response
to one category of incentives depends on the composition of payment
schemes for other patients in their practice. This suggests an alternate
rule to profit maximization that governs response to supply behavior,
such as a response to the modal incentives. During the 1980s, Medi-
72
Defining the Health Care Challenge
care and some state Medicaid programs instituted a hospital prospective payment system. That payment system had two parts: a prospective
part that paid for an admission as stratified by diagnostic category and
a part where supply-side cost sharing obtained after a specified level of
spending was reached. Frank and Lave studied the effect of changing the
payment system from cost-based reimbursement to per-case prospective
payment for psychiatric care (Frank and Lave 1989). They showed that
the response was a reduction in both long-stay and short-stay cases. The
expected pattern was for a reduction in long-stay cases and an increased
density of short-stay cases. Interviews with physicians suggested that they
treated the prospective payment based on an average hospital stay for a
case as if it were a target, and so the density of cases increased around
the mean stay.
The implication of these ideas and the experience with complex payment schemes is that, in a fragmented delivery system, P4P will not automatically elicit the expected behavioral responses. Very little is known
regarding the most effective design for such policies.
Conclusions
David Cutler’s work has stimulated health economists to think in different ways about the performance of the health care delivery system. He
emphasizes that assessing the performance of the health care delivery
system is an empirical matter that requires careful and detailed analysis
of spending and outcomes. The next step in that research program is to
understand more about where we are relative to the efficiency frontier,
and why. I have offered some examples of ideas that might be useful in
putting behavioral economics to work on that task. This is a big job, but
it is one that Cutler’s work clearly points to as unfinished business.
Cutler’s call for P4P is well reasoned and sensible. However, whether
one begins with the rational, money-oriented doctor or the optimistic person with limited ability to respond effectively to complex economic environments, theory will probably be of limited use in predicting responses
to P4P schemes. Thus, Cutler suggests that some of these schemes be tried
and that we begin to learn from these experiences. While I agree completely with that proposal, I also believe it is quite likely that the rational,
Richard G. Frank 73
money-oriented physician may not be the best starting place. If this is
correct, then there are some useful implications from behavioral economics for how to design P4P schemes. I will conclude by mentioning three.
First, use relatively simple payment schemes so that attention is easily
focused on the key outcomes that will be rewarded. Second, implement
these schemes on a large scale to diminish the complexity (number of
payment schemes) and to increase the share of business affected, so that
it pays to change. Finally, make the rewards large enough to overcome
inertia, reluctance, and intrinsic motivational concerns.
■ Richard G. Frank is grateful to David Cutler, Tom McGuire, and
Jon Skinner for helpful discussion. Financial support from the AHRQ
and the John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation is gratefully
acknowledged.
74
Defining the Health Care Challenge
Glied, S. and J. G. Zivin. 2002. How do doctors behave when some (but not
all) of their patients are in managed care. Journal of Health Economics 21 (2):
337–353.
Haman, J., B. Langer, S. Leucht, R. Busch, and W. Kissling. 2004. Medical decision making in antipsychotic drug choice for schizophrenia. American Journal of
Psychiatry 161 (7): 1301–1304.
Hartman, R. S., M. J. Doane, and C. K. Woo. 1991. Consumer rationality and
the status quo. Quarterly Journal of Economics 106 (1): 141–162.
Hellerstein, J. K. 1998. The importance of the physician in the generic
versus trade-name prescription decision. RAND Journal of Economics 29 (1):
108–136.
Institute of Medicine. 2001. Crossing the Quality Chasm. Washington, DC:
National Academy Press.
Institute of Medicine. 2007. Rewarding Provider Performance: Aligning Incentives in Medicare. Washington, D.C.: NAS Press.
Lamont, E. B. and N. A. Christakis. 2001. Prognostic disclosure to patients with
cancer near the end of life. Annals of Internal Medicine 134 (12): 1096–1105.
Notes
Liebman, J. B. and R. J. Zeckhauser. 2004. Schmeduling. Working Paper, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University.
1. For a complete review of such issues, see Frank (2004).
McGlynn, E. A., S. M. Asch, J. Adams, J. Keesey, J. Hicks, A. DeCristofaro, E.
Kerr. 2003. The quality of health care delivered to adults in the United States.
New England Journal of Medicine 348 (26): 2635–2645.
2. See National Expenditures at www.cms.hhs.gov/statistics/nhe/default.asp
(Accessed May, 2005).
References
Moeller, S., F. Schlingemann, and R. Stulz. 2003. Do shareholders of acquiring
firms gain from acquisitions? Research Technology Management 46 (6): 62–66.
Buntin, M. B. and H. Huskamp. 2002. What is known about the economics of
end of life care for Medicare beneficiaries. The Gerontologist 42 (3): 40–48.
Mullen, K. J., R. G. Frank, and M. B. Rosenthal. 2007. Can you get what you
pay for? Pay for performance and the quality of health care providers. Working
Paper, Harvard University.
Christakis, N. A. 1999. Death Foretold: Prophecy and Prognosis in Medical
Care. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Oskamp, S. 1965. Overconfidence in case study judgments. Journal of Consulting Psychology 29 (3): 261–265.
Congressional Budget Office. 2007. The Budget and Economic Outlook, Fiscal
Years 2008 to 2017. Washington, DC: U.S. Congressional Budget Office.
Rosenthal, M. B., R. Fernandopulle, H. R. Song, and B. Landon. 2004. Paying
for quality: Providers’ incentives for quality improvement. Health Affairs 23 (2):
127–141.
Cutler, D. M. 2004. Your Money or Your Life: Strong Medicine for America’s
Health Care System. New York: Oxford University Press.
Samuelson, W. and R. Zeckhauser. 1988. Status quo bias in decision making.
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 1 (1): 7–59.
Experton, B., Z. Li, L. G. Branch, R. J. Ozminkowski, and D. M. Mellon-Lacey.
1997. The impact of payor/provider type on the cost of dying among frail older
adults. American Journal of Public Health 87 (2): 210–216.
Scherer, F. M. 2000. Pharmaceuticals. In Handbook of Health Economics, edited
by Newhouse, J. P. and A. Culyer. Amsterdam: North Holland.
Frank, R. G. 2004. Behavioral economics and health economics. NBER Working
Paper No. 10881.
Skinner, J., E. S. Fisher, and J. E. Wennberg. 2001. The efficiency of Medicare.
NBER Working Paper No. 8395.
Frank, R. G. and J. R. Lave. 1989. A comparison of hospital responses to reimbursement for Medicaid psychiatric patients. RAND Journal of Economics 20
(4): 588–600.
Skinner, J. and D. O. Staiger. 2005. Technology adoption from hybrid corn to
beta blockers. NBER Working Paper No. 11251.
Richard G. Frank 75
Thaler, R. 1980. Towards a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organizations 39: 36–90.
Thorpe, K. E., C. S. Florence, and P. Joski. 2004. What medical conditions account
for the rise in health care spending. Health Affairs, Web Exclusive. http://content.
healthaffairs.org/cgi/ reprint/hlthaff.w4.437v1.pdf. Accessed April 18, 2007.
Weeks, J. C., E. F. Cook, S. J. O’Day, L. M. Peterson, N. Wenger, D. Reding,
F. E. Harrell, P. Kussin, N. V. Dawson, A. F. Connors, J. Lynn, and R. S. Phillips.
1998. Relationship between cancer patients’ predictions of prognosis and their
treatment preferences. Journal of the American Medical Association 279 (21):
1709–1714.
Weinstein, N. D. 1980. Unrealistic optimism about future life events. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 39 (5): 806–820.
Wennberg, J. E. and M. M. Cooper. 1997. Dartmouth Atlas of Health Care.
Chicago: American Hospital Publishing.
78
Costs, Benefits, and Rationing of Health
Care: Comments on Cutler’s “What Is Good
Care, and What Is Bad?”
William D. Nordhaus
Defining the Health Care Challenge
they, particularly the elderly, see health care as a basic right. Reducing
benefits or entitlements among powerful groups will not be easy. Third,
medical care is seen as a special kind of good and not as a normal economic good. The idea that medical care should be “rationed” the way we
ration food, shelter, and automobiles is unacceptable not only to patients
but also to many physicians. Clearly, some kind of rationing must occur,
and the major questions are how it will be done, who are the losers and
winners, and whether it will be efficient or inefficient.
The Costs of Health Care
A Very Hard Problem
To put health care in perspective, it is useful to consider some of the
major economic problems facing the United States today. These include:
(1) the budget deficit, (2) global warming, (3) the current account deficit,
(4) Social Security, (5) dependence on imported oil, and (6) health care.
After some study, I believe that we could fashion a reasonable solution
that would resolve the first five problems, at low cost and with relatively
little inequity and economic dislocation.
For the sixth one, health care, I do not believe that an obvious solution
exists. Henry Aaron called health care “the problem that won’t go away.”
I wonder whether it is the problem that cannot be solved, or that cannot
be solved in a simple and efficient way. This is perhaps the message of
the papers prepared for this conference by David Cutler, Alain Enthoven,
and Henry Aaron; it is the message from the dozens of presentations and
papers I have read over the years. Most experts believe that they have a
solution to the American health care problem—whether this-or-that kind
of competition or this-or-that kind of payer—but it is not obvious to me
that any of these plans will actually resolve the problems of the American
health care system today.
What are the barriers to fixing health care? There are many, but some
that seem particularly important to me are the following. First, the economic stakes are huge in terms of the incomes of the providers (doctors,
insurance companies, lobbyists, and the rest).1 Health care is too large to
tuck into an omnibus bill. Second, the welfare stakes are enormous for
patients. People have benefited greatly from improved medical care, and
Our economy has a very large stake in both the costs and the benefits of
our health care system. I will begin with the familiar terrain of the share
of health spending in the economy. There are clearly some ambiguities in
estimates of spending on health care, such as whether to include spending on research and development, the environment, automobile and mine
safety, and even health economists’ salaries. Standard estimates from the
U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) indicate that the
share of health expenditures rose from 8.8 percent of gross domestic
product (GDP) in 1980 to 15.3 percent in 2003.
Figure 3.5 shows the share of medical care in personal consumption
expenditures (PCE), with a share under 4 percent up to around 1950,
then rising sharply to 17 percent of PCE in 2004. The share of health in
government direct purchases (which exclude transfer payments), shown
in Figure 3.6, has been stable at between 4 and 6 percent of the total. Figure 3.7 shows the estimated relative inflation rate of health care, according to the U.S. Bureau of Economic Analysis (BEA), compared with all
personal consumption expenditures. Health care prices have been rising
more rapidly than all prices by about 1 percent per year, although it is
quite likely that medical care inflation has been overestimated because of
measurement issues.
The Benefits of Improved Health
On the benefit side, there is evidence that the improvements in health
status over the last century have caused substantial improvements to eco-
80
Defining the Health Care Challenge
5
16
4
14
3
12
2
10
1
Government consumption and gross investment in health/
Total government consumption and investment
(Percent)
7
6
5
4
3
2
1
1964
1969
1974
1979
1984
1989
1994
99
04
20
94
89
84
19
19
19
79
19
74
19
19
64
69
19
59
19
54
44
19
19
19
64
19
69
19
74
19
79
19
84
19
89
19
94
19
99
20
04
19
19
19
19
19
19
Figure 3.7
Relative Inflation of Medical Care to All Personal Consumption Expenditures
(Three-Year Moving Average)
Source: U.S. Bureau of Economic Analysis.
Figure 3.5
Medical Care as a Share of Personal Consumption Expenditures
Source: U.S. Bureau of Economic Analysis.
0
1959
49
–4
19
–3
0
34
2
54
–2
59
4
44
19
49
–1
34
6
39
0
19
8
19
Percent
18
39
Percent
William D. Nordhaus 79
1999
Figure 3.6
Health as a Share of Government Consumption and Gross Investment
Source: U.S. Bureau of Economic Analysis.
nomic welfare. This result emerges from several studies that value health
improvements at conventional values of life extension. Studies by David
Cutler and Elizabeth Richardson, as well as by Kevin Murphy, Robert
Topel, and myself, have examined the economic equivalent of the extensions to life saving.2
My own conclusion from this exercise, based only on changes in life
expectancy, was that the value of improvements in life expectancy is
about as large as the value of improvements in all other consumption
goods and services put together. Figure 3.8 shows an illustrative calculation from my study on “The Health of Nations” (Nordhaus 2003).
This demonstrates that the growth of income from health improvements
(shown as the first three bars in each group) is about as large as the
growth in conventionally measured incomes.
Over the period from 1975 to 2000, for example, conventionally measured per capita income grew at an average rate of 2.0 percent per year.
Over this same period, the annual average improvements in life expectancy
had an economic value of between 1.0 and 2.1 percent of income (depending upon the discount rate and other assumptions).3 Over the entire period
William D. Nordhaus 81
4
Discount rate = 0.000
Discount rate = 0.010
Discount rate = 0.025
Per capita income
Percent
3
2
1
0
1900–25
1925–50
1950–75
1975–2000
Figure 3.8
Growth in Health Income and Conventional Income, 1900–2000
Growth in health income is equal to the change in the value of improved health
status divided by income and is shown for three different annual discount rates.
The fourth bar shows the growth in per capita income. All figures are annual
average percent per year.
Source: Nordhaus (2003).
from 1900 to 2000, the value of improved health or health income grew
at between 1.2 and 2.5 percent of consumption (again depending upon
the exact assumptions), whereas income grew at a rate of about 2.0 percent of consumption. Looking at the entire twentieth century, the contribution of the increase in life expectancy was between 59 percent and 126
percent of the contribution of income from all sources combined.
Specific Egalitarianism and the Need for Rationing
Among the public and many health care practitioners, it is widely accepted
that everyone has a right to basic medical care. In a recent survey, 84
percent of respondents agreed that, “Health care should be provided
equally to everyone, just as public education is” (Kaiser Family Foundation 2004). This strong sentiment is usually tempered by concerns about
costs and restrictions to access. However, with respect to health care, it is
striking how many people believe in “specific egalitarianism,” meaning
82
Defining the Health Care Challenge
that specific programs or services should be distributed “equally” among
all people. Some examples of this include the vote for citizens, the draft
in time of major wars, as well as primary and secondary public schooling
among children.
While there is general agreement that basic health care should be universally provided, this poses serious economic issues. First, as James
Tobin pointed out, specific egalitarianism can be used most efficiently
when goods are inelastic in supply.4 We do not worry (with the obvious exceptions) about inefficiencies in the “production” of votes in proclaiming “one person, one vote.” Similarly, there has generally been but
a small response in the supply of citizens to the presence of a universal
military service in most countries. By contrast, because much of health
care is elastic in supply, particularly in the long run, mandating equal
provision is likely to lead to major inefficiencies.
Two polar examples can serve to illustrate this point about elasticity.
First, there is little in the health care sector that is truly fixed in supply in
the long run (in the sense of being completely price inelastic). Perhaps the
supply of organs for transplantation comes close to fixed supply. If these
organs are allocated purely based on medical need, then the absence of
a market signal will not reduce the number available and will not keep
transplants from those who need them. If we desire specific egalitarianism, a parallel market in this case would be harmful. If a market in
organs is allowed, those with higher incomes can bid some of the fixed
supply away from those who need them most. This is one example where
the Canadian model of prohibiting a private market to run in parallel to
the comprehensive public system can be justified.
The opposite, however, would hold for medical drugs, the second polar
example. Suppose that the government system includes payments for an
expensive drug like Taxol for treatment of cancer. Like the majority of
manufactured products, most drugs are close to perfectly elastic in supply
(and may even have some positive learning effects). In this case, it would
not be sensible to prohibit a parallel private market, because there is no
crowding out of the public supply by increased private demand.
A second difficulty with specific egalitarianism in health is the definition of the bundle of goods to which equality should apply. Many people
would agree that access to medical care for a life-threatening illness, such
as a ruptured spleen or tuberculosis, should not be denied to anyone.
William D. Nordhaus 83
However, it is not clear that people would agree that everyone should
have free and immediate treatment for removal of corns and calluses.
Where to “draw the line” is a vexing problem—one that will not go away
and indeed is likely to worsen as more conditions are classified and more
treatments are discovered.
One of the results of poorly designed specific egalitarianism is the general view among health care experts that the allocation of health care in
the United States is highly inefficient. The general view, expressed differently in the papers by Cutler, Enthoven, and Aaron, is that many critical conditions are untreated, while others with high costs and close to
zero medical benefits are receiving substantial resources. Although this is
self-evident to specialists, it is also a very difficult research issue. David
Cutler’s presentation showed a number of illnesses for which the benefitcost ratios for some treatments are quite high (cardiovascular disease,
heart attack, low-birth-weight infants, and depression), with some suggestions of areas where the benefit-cost ratio may be low (such as Sal’s
angioplasty). More than one-third of Medicaid spending goes to longterm care, and it is not clear that this qualifies as a high-benefit activity.
It would be interesting to see whether a more comprehensive approach
could be taken, using a nationally representative sample that matches
treatments and conditions, to flesh out the larger picture.
Whether or not a country provides equal health care for all its residents, there must be rationing of health care. While rationing might be a
jarring word, it reflects the reality that, in a world of scarcity, every need
and desire cannot be fully satisfied. Until we get to the point where every
symptom of every hypochondriac can be extensively examined, probed,
tested, and treated, it will be necessary to leave some perceived medical
need unsatisfied. Rationing is not an option. However, it is not obvious
how we are to ration.
Most goods and services are rationed by the purse. Prices ration out
the limited supply of fancy cars and mansions, as well as not-so-fancy
gasoline and land, to those whose incomes and tastes lead them to want
them most. In many areas of health care, we do not allow prices to ration
out services to the highest bidders. The results are sometimes longer waits
for care as a surrogate price (as is the complaint in many HMOs and in
Canada), rising expenditures as the demand for services rises sharply (as
for Medicaid and Medicare), or lack of coverage (for the rising number
84
Defining the Health Care Challenge
of uninsured). One way of interpreting the fiscal crisis facing the United
States is that the country is unwilling to ration health resources by price
or by trimming the benefit package.
So long as we continue to seek some form of specific egalitarianism
in health care, there will be no easy solutions to the rationing problem.
For my tastes, I would prefer some type of explicit selection of covered
benefits along the lines of the Oregon prioritized list of covered services. The philosophy of the Oregon plan is that all citizens should have
access to care, and that there should be an open and reasoned process
for determining the list of covered treatments. One initial component of
the ranking of the prioritized list was a cost-benefit test, although that
appears to have generated such disagreement that it was either dropped
or demoted in favor of cost-effectiveness tests together with expert and
public views.5
While not without shortcomings, this approach has several attractive
features. First, it does allow a budget constraint to operate in the sense
that a “line” can be drawn to fit treatments into available resources. So,
for example, the funding line in 2004 just included simple and social
phobias and just excluded acute conjunctivitis.
Second, while we might complain about the priorities, there appears
to be little disagreement about the general rankings. Treatment of diabetes and appendicitis are covered, and few would probably disagree
here. Below the line are elective dental services and several conditions for
which there are either no effective treatments or no necessary treatments.
There are also some brave exclusions, such as the decision not to treat
cancers with five-year survival probabilities of less than 5 percent.6
It would be useful to have more study about the implicit valuations of
different conditions along with treatment costs for the prioritized list to
see whether, in fact, the cost-benefit calculations are reasonable. It would
also be interesting to compare the cost-benefit calculations in the health
care arena with those that have been done for environmental, health, and
safety regulations. As Table 3.2 shows, results in the regulatory area indicate extremely disparate cost-benefit ratios, depending upon the regulation
and agency. The regulations shown here range from highly cost-beneficial
with large benefits and negligible costs (for the tobacco regulations for
youths) to others where the costs per fatality prevented are in the billions
William D. Nordhaus 85
Table 3.2
Estimates of Cost of Life Saved by Major Federal Regulations
Rule (Agency)
Net cost per
discounted life
(millions of 1995 $)
Toxicity characteristics to determine hazardous wastes (EPA)
–8,300.0
Underground storage tanks: technical requirements (EPA)
Manufactured home construction standards on wind (HUD)
–350.0
–37.0
Process safety management of highly hazardous chemicals
(DOL)
–3.3
Regulations of cigarettes and smokeless tobacco for youths
(HHS)
–0.5
Medicare and Medicaid programs, miscellaneous (HHS)
0.2
Quality mammography standards (HHS)
0.3
Food labeling regulations (HHS)
0.4
Childproof lighters (CPSC)
Standard for occupational exposure to benzene (DOL)
Occupational exposure to methylene chloride (DOL)
0.
7.1
8.5
86
Defining the Health Care Challenge
of dollars (such as some drinking water regulations). Are cost-benefit
ratios also this disparate under current programs like Medicare and Medicaid, and in current HMO and insurance benefit packages?
Third, a prioritized list, in principle, allows adjustments of treatments
and coverages in response to changes in medical technology and clinical
studies. One of the major difficulties with most approaches to coverage
is “contractual stickiness,” whereby benefits are easy to add but difficult to remove.7 A prioritized list provides a mechanism for adding and
removing services that legitimizes the process rather than politicizing the
process from the very start. In this arena, the process of changing the list
cannot be an easy one, any more than weaning people from their SUVs
by high gasoline prices is painless in a market arena. Still, we clearly need
mechanisms to substitute for a market mechanism when we decide, as in
much of health care, not to allow the price mechanism to operate.
A prioritized list is not the only mechanism for selecting covered services, however. Every HMO and insurance contract must somehow make
similar choices all the time. One major advantage of the prioritized-list
approach is that, in principle, it uses a cost-benefit philosophy (ranking on the basis of the benefit-cost ratio) rather than a medical necessity
philosophy (whereby procedures are included if their proven benefits are
positive) or the results of litigation (whereby something is included to
prevent legal action). Perhaps the most important advantage is that by
excluding medical services that are low priority, particularly those that
receive public funding, we make room for extending high-priority services to those who currently do not qualify or who are crowded out by
market or bureaucratic forces.
Occupational exposure to 4,4a methylenedianiline (DOL)
18.0
Asbestos prohibitions, total (EPA)
19.0
National primary and secondary water regulations—
phase II (EPA)
25.0
Occupational exposure to asbestos (DOL)
27.0
Hazardous waste management system—wood preservatives
(EPA)
50.0
Sewage sludge use and disposal regulations, 40 CFR pt. 503
(EPA)
190.0
Land disposal restrictions for “third third” scheduled wastes
(EPA)
190.0
Hazardous waste management system, solvents (EPA)
200.0
Occupational exposure to formaldehyde (DOL)
390.0
Prohibit the land disposal of the first third of scheduled wastes
(EPA)
400.0
1. This point was amply shown in an insightful set of essays in Aaron and
Armacost (1995).
Land disposal restrictions—phase II (EPA)
910.0
2. See particularly Cutler and Richardson (1997), and the chapters by William
D. Nordhaus, Kevin M. Murphy, and Robert H. Topel, and David M. Cutler and
Srikanth Kadiyala in Murphy and Topel (2003).
Drinking water regulations, synthetic organic chemicals—
phase V (EPA)
Solid waste disposal facility criteria (EPA)
Source: Hahn, Lutter, and Viscusi (2000, pp. 16–17).
9,600.0
36,000.0
Notes
3. The single most important assumption in these studies is the value of extending the lifespan by a year. Most studies, including my own, value a life-year at
around $100,000 per year, or $12 per hour, at income levels of the 1990s.
William D. Nordhaus 87
4. Tobin (1970). Tobin discusses several policies that are good targets for specific
egalitarianism.
5. A description and the list are available at http://egov.oregon.gov/DAS/OHPPR/
HSC/current_prior.shtml. A particularly useful discussion is by Bodenheimer
(1997a, 1997b).
6. This is an interesting calculation for those in health economics. Assuming that
the value of one year of life extension is $100,000, then the value of such procedures would be less than .05 × 5 × $100,000 = $25,000. The cost of a course
of treatment is probably in the same order of magnitude as the upper limit of
benefit, so this seems reasonably well grounded in the underlying cost-benefit
calculation.
7. Contractual stickiness is the health care analog to downward wage rigidity that macroeconomists analyze in such detail. The two syndromes arise
from the same underlying source, the costs of negotiating changes to existing
understandings.
References
Aaron, H. J. and M. H. Armacost (eds.). 1995. The Problem That Won’t Go
Away: Reforming U.S. Health Care Financing. Washington, DC: Brookings
Institution.
Bodenheimer, T. 1997a. The Oregon health plan—lessons for the nation. New
England Journal of Medicine. 337 (9): 651–655.
Bodenheimer, T. 1997b. The Oregon health plan—lessons for the nation. New
England Journal of Medicine. 337 (10): 720–723.
Cutler, D. and E. Richardson. 1997. Measuring the health of the U.S. population.
Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics. 217–271.
Hahn, R. W., R. W. Lutter, and W. K. Viscusi. 2000. Do Federal Regulations
Reduce Mortality? Washington, DC: AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory
Studies.
Kaiser Family Foundation. 2004. Kaiser health poll report. http://www.kff.org/
healthpollreport/ CurrentEdition/index.cfm. Accessed April 18, 2007.
Murphy, K. M. and R. H. Topel (eds.). 2003. Measuring the Gains from Medical
Research: An Economic Approach. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Nordhaus, W. D. 2003. The health of nations: The contribution of improved
health to living standards. In Measuring the Gains from Medical Research: An
Economic Approach, edited by Murphy, K. M. and R. H. Topel. Chicago: Chicago University Press. 9–40.
Tobin, J. 1970. On limiting the domain of inequality. Journal of Law and Economics 13 (2): 263–277.