Scienza della logica
Transcription
Scienza della logica
Hegel TEORIA XXXIII/2013/1 Hegel Scienza della logica Scritti di: Claudio Cesa, Walter Jaeschke, Klaus Düsing, Jean-Louis Vieillard-Baron, Giuseppe Cantillo, Félix Duque, Riccardo Dottori, Franco Chiereghin, Michela Bordignon, Marcello Monaldi, Bernard Mabille, Pasqualino Masciarelli, Rainer Schäfer, Massimo Adinolfi, Elena Ficara. ISSN 1122-1259 I l primo tomo della Wissenschaft der Logik fu pubblicato alla fine di aprile del 1812. Il secondo uscì dalla tipografia nel dicembre dello stesso anno, recando però come data il 1813. Entrambi erano dedicati alla “Logica oggettiva”. Il terzo volume sulla “Logica soggettiva”, che Hegel sperava di far seguire immediatamente, uscì invece alla fine del 1816. Siamo quindi a circa duecento anni dalla pubblicazione di quest’opera. Per tale occasione il presente volume di «Teoria», nelle sue varie parti, intende offrire una lettura approfondita di alcuni aspetti del testo hegeliano. Ciò viene compiuto, com’è ormai stile della rivista, avvalendosi dei maggiori esperti a livello internazionale e coinvolgendo nel progetto studiosi affermati di diverse generazioni. e azion co lut er va pia p ne tazio u l a v per Scienza della logica copia ione az valut r e p copia e azion zione copia aluta per v lut er va p a i cop TEORIA Rivista di filosofia fondata da Vittorio Sainati XXXIII/2013/1 (Terza serie VIII/1) e azion lut er va pia p co ne tazio valu a per copi ione az valut r e p ia cop e azion t r valu ia pe cop copia € 18,00 ne tazio u l a v per zione ISBN 978-884673663-5 9 788846 736635 Teoria_2013-1-cover.indd 1 ETS copia aluta per v Edizioni ETS 13/06/13 09.28 «Teoria» è indicizzata ISI e SCOPUS, e ha ottenuto la classificazione “A” per le riviste di filosofia morale. ne di questo numero La versione elettronica ne tazio u l a tazio v u l r a e v p è disponibile sul sito: www.rivistateoria.eu per copia copia Direzione e Redazione: Dipartimento di Filosofia dell’Università di Pisa, via P. Paoli 15, 56126 Pisa, tel. (050) 2215500 - www.fls.unipi.it Direttore: Adriano Fabris ione z a t u al per v Comitato Scientifico Internazionale: Antonio Autiero (Münster), Damir copia Barbarić (Zagabria), Vinicius Berlendis de Figueiredo (Curitiba), Bernhard Casper (Freiburg i.B.), Néstor Corona (Buenos Aires), Félix Duque (Madrid), Günter Figal (Freiburg i.B.), aDenis zione zioneGuénoun (Parigi), Dean Komel (Lubiana), aluta alut Lanceros (Bilbao), Regina Schwartz (Evanston, v v r r Klaus Müller (Münster), Patxi e e p p opia (Evanston, Illinois), Mariano E. Ure (Buenos copiaAires). Illinois), Ken cSeeskin Comitato di Redazione: Eva De Clerq, Annamaria Lossi, Carlo Marletti, Flavia Monceri, Antonia Pellegrino, Stefano Perfetti, Luisa Sassi. ne tazio Pisa, 56126 Amministrazione: EDIZIONI ETS, piazza Carrara 16-19, u l a v per www.edizioniets.com, info@edizioniets.com copia tel. (050) 29544-503868 ne Abbonamento 2012: Italia € 30,00, Iva inclusa; estero US $ 30,00, tazio u l a v r e da versare sul c.c.p. 14721567 intestato alle Edizioni ETS. p ne tazio copia u l a v Prezzo di un fascicolo: € 18,00, Iva inclusa.a per i copIva Prezzo di un fascicolo arretrato: € 20,00, inclusa. L’indice dei fascicoli di «Teoria» può essere consultato all’indirizzo: ione lutaz a v www.rivistateoria.eu. Qui è possibile acquistare un singolo articolo o l’intero r e pia p numero in formato PDF, e anche l’intero numero in versionecocartacea. zionedella stampa presso la Canc. del Trib. di Pisa aReg. t Iscritto al u l a per v copian° 10/81 del 23.5.1981. Direttore Responsabile: Adriano Fabris. Semestrale. Contiene meno del 70% di pubblicità. one utaziPisa. alETS, © Copyright 1981 by Edizioni v r e p copia I numeri della rivista sono monografici. Gli scritti proposti per la pubblicazione sono peer reviewed. I testi devono essere conformi alle norme editoriali indicate nel sito. TEORIA Rivista di filosofia fondata da Vittorio Sainati Ultimi fascicoli apparsi della Terza serie di «Teoria»: XXXI/2012/2 (Terza serie VII/2) «Spinoza nel XXI secolo» XXXI/2012/1 (Terza serie VII/1) «Conformity and Dissent - Conformità e dissenso» XXXI/2011/2 (Terza serie VI/2) «La formazione e la conoscenza ai tempi del web» XXXI/2011/1 (Terza serie VI/1) «Critica della ragione medica» XXX/2010/2 (Terza serie V/2) «La figura e il pensiero di Armando Carlini» XXX/2010/1 (Terza serie V/1) «Filosofie dell’immagine» XXIX/2009/2 (Terza serie IV/2) «Metamorphoses of Love - Metamorfosi dell’amore» XXIX/2009/1 (Terza serie IV/1) «Etica della comunicazione tra due continenti» XXVIII/2008/2 (Terza serie III/2) «Eurosofia. La filosofia e l’Europa» XXVIII/2008/1 (Terza serie III/1) «Il futuro del “nuovo pensiero”. In dialogo con Franz Rosenzweig» XXVII/2007/2 (Terza serie II/2) «Ethicbots - Etica e robotica» XXVII/2007/1 (Terza serie II/1) «Democrazie, appartenenza, valori - Democracies, belonging, values» XXVI/2006/2 (Terza serie I/2) «Levinas in Italia» XXVI/2006/1 (Terza serie I/1) «L’identità in questione» Teoria_2013-1-cover.indd 2 13/06/13 09.28 000a_frontespizio.qxd 12-06-2013 16:28 Pagina 1 TEORIA copia e azion alut per v opia c Rivista di filosofia fondata da Vittorio Sainati XXXIII/2013/1 (Terza serie VIII/1) e azion alut per v e copia zion aluta v r e p Hegel zione a valut a per Scienza della logica copi copia zione p e cop copia alut per v e azion cop e copia ne tazio luta er va azion t r valu ia pe cop r valu ia pe zion aluta v r e p copia alut per v e azion Edizioni ETS r valu ia pe ne tazio 000a_frontespizio.qxd copia 12-06-2013 16:28 Pagina 2 e azion alut per v copia e azion alut per v e copia zion aluta v r e p zione a valut a per copi cop copia zione p e cop copia alut per v e azion cop e copia ne tazio luta er va azion t r valu ia pe r valu ia pe zion aluta v r e p copia alut per v e azion r valu ia pe ne tazio 000b_indice_3.qxd 12-06-2013 Indice copia 16:28 Pagina 3 e azion alut per v copia e azion alut per v #LAUDIO#ESA!DRIANO&ABRIS Premessa, p. 5 copia e azion t u l a v per Questioni di fondo 7ALTER*AESCHKE Die Prinzipien des Denkens und des Seins. Hegels System der reinenuVernunft, ione ione p. 13 lutaz l taz a a v v r r pe pe +LAUS$àSING copia copia Paradigmatische Ontologie. Der Weg von der Ontologie zur philosophischen Theologie in Hegels Logik, p. 29 *EAN,OUIS6IEILLARD"ARON Le devenir logique: négativité et contradiction, p. 49zione ta r valu e p a i 'IUSEPPE#ANTILLO cop Il doppio rispecchiamento: ragione e vita nella logica hegeliana, p. 69 ne tazio u l a v per ne tazio Interpretazioni copia u l a v per copia #LAUDIO#ESA Problemi della misura, p. 87 alu &ÏLIX$UQUE per v a i p o Come dare ragione del Principio di ragione, p. 101 c ne 2ICCARDO$OTTORI tazio u l a v Wesen a per als Reflexion. Hermeneutische copiBemerkungen über den Anfang der Logik des Wesens, p. 129 Linguaggio e storia alut per v e azion copia &RANCO#HIEREGHIN Pensiero e linguaggio nella Scienza della logica di Hegel, p. 155 ne tazio 000b_indice_3.qxd 12-06-2013 16:28 4 Pagina 4 INDICE e -ICHELA"ORDIGNON ne azion t u zio179 l ap. a t v Dialectic and Natural Language. Theories of Vagueness, u l r a e v p per copia opia c -ARCELLO-ONALDI La ragione nella storia. Appunti per una rilettura del rapporto tra logica e storia in Hegel, p. 199 copia ne tazio Discussioni u l a v per "ERNARD-ABILLE En quel sens Hegel est-il philosophe de l’identité ?, p. 213 ione ione 0ASQUALINO-ASCIARELLI lutaz lutaz a a v v r r pe pe Hegel abbandonò copia copiala “legge di Leibniz”?, p. 233 2AINER3CHËFER Die syllogistische Genese des Widerspruchs in der absoluten Idee in Hegels Logik, p. 265 e -ASSIMO!DINOLFI azion t u l a Hegel e la costituzione dell’inizio, p. 283pia per v co %LENA&ICARA Hegel Within Contemporary Logic, p. 297 ne tazio u l a v per ne tazio copia u l a v per copia cop e copia zion aluta v r e p copia alut per v e azion r valu ia pe ne tazio 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 297 Hegel Scienza della logica Hegel Within Contemporary Logic Elena Ficara It is usual to think of Hegel’s logic as incompatible with contemporary formal logic1. There are indeed some major resistances to the attempt of considering Hegel’s logic from a formal point of view, or even as belonging to the canon of the philosophy of logic. They are further aggravated by Hegel’s famous observations, according to which considering thought using figures and signs is «useless»2, and formal logic «neither grasps truth nor can be considered as a path towards truth»3. So it is not surprising that in most handbooks of the history and philosophy of logic the Hegelian, and more generally the German classical reflections about logic are not considered4. The only excep1 On the fact that despite our study and knowledge of Hegel have impressively grown, we are still far from a true understanding of what his logic, in particular the dialectical method, is, see H.F. Fulda, Unzulängliche Bemerkungen zur Dialektik, in R.P. Horstmann (ed.), Seminar: Dialektik in der Philosophie Hegels, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M. 1978, pp. 33-69 and H.F. Fulda, Hegels Dialektik als Begriffsbewegung und Darstellungsweise, in R.P. Horstmann (ed.), Seminar: Dialektik in der Philosophie Hegels, cit., pp. 124-74. See also W. Flach, Hegels dialektische Methode, in Hegel-Studien, Beiheft 1, Heidelberger Hegel-Tage 1962, Bouvier, Bonn, pp. 55-64. 2 G.W.F. Hegel, Werke in 20 Bänden. Auf der Grundlage der Werke von 1832-1845 neu edierte Ausgabe, hg. von E. Moldenhauer und K. M. Michel, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M. 1971 (=Hegel, Werke 1-20). Hegel, Werke 6, p. 295. 3 Hegel, Werke 5, p. 36. 4 Or, if they are, they are not free from the suspect of giving a psychologistic account of logic. However, this critique has to be dismissed in advance, as neither Kant nor Hegel intended thought as the psychological activity or process. On the Hegelian meaning of “objective thought” see V. Verra, Introduzione a Hegel, Laterza, Roma-Bari, 19999, pp. 69-74; V. Verra, Su Hegel, Il Mulino, Bologna 2007, pp. 349-370; A. Nuzzo, La logica, in C. Cesa (ed.), Hegel, Laterza, Roma-Bari 1997, pp. 39-82, pp. 43-44; E. Ficara, Ursprünge des Ausdrucks “das Logische” beim frühen Hegel, in: «Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte» 52 (2010), 113-125. On Hegel’s and Frege’s conception of objective thought see F. D’Agostini, Pensare con la propria testa. Problemi di filosofia del pensiero in Hegel e Frege, in N. Vassallo (ed.), La filosofia di Gottlob Frege, Franco Angeli, Milano 2003, pp. 59-94. On the objective meaning of thought in Kant see E. Ficara, Die TEORIA 2013/1 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 298 16:54 Pagina 298 Elena Ficara tions are the reflections linked to the first attempts of formalising dialectical logic started in the 60ties, attempts which, for many reasons, have been either abandoned, or marginalised 5. However, the success that non-classical logics are experiencing in recent years surely is an important aspect, which could possibly help such an endeavour 6. The paper has four parts. In the first part I briefly consider a basic meaning of «logic», as presented by some recent handbooks. In the second I examine Kant’s and Hegel’s views on logic, in particular their approach to the question: what does it mean that in logic (since Aristotle) if some things are supposed, others «follow with necessity»? In the third part, I present Hegel’s theses about the relation between logic and metaphysics, a central topic in order to understand the specific Hegelian idea of logical necessity. In the last part, I conclude hinting at the utility of considering Hegel’s reflections about logic in the perspective of contemporary philosophy of logic, and considering contemporary debates from a Hegelian point of view. 1. What is Logic? In contemporary handbooks, logic is defined as the discipline that inquires into inference, examining «what follows from what»7. In Logical Pluralism JC Beall and Greg Restall write: Logic is about consequence. Logical Consequence is a relation among claims expressed in a language. An account of Logical Consequence is an account about what follows from what8. And Graham Priest in Logic. A Very Short Introduction quotes Tweedledum und Tweedledee in Lewis Carroll’s Through the Looking Glass: Ontologie in der Kritik der reinen Vernunft , Königshausen und Neumann, Würzburg 2006, pp. 163-67 and pp. 187-188. 5 See the critical survey on these attempts developed by D. Marconi, La formalizzazione della dialettica. Hegel, Marx e la logica contemporanea, Rosenberg & Sellier, Torino 1979, pp. 9-84. 6 Among the works that try to re-open the question of the link between the classical German reflection (from Kant to Hegel) and contemporary logic E. Tugendhat, Logisch-semantische Propädeutik, Reclam, Stuttgart 1993; E. Tugendhat, Vorlesungen über die sprachanalytische Philosophie, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M. 1976; F. D’Agostini, From a Continental Point of View. The Role of Logic in the Analytic-Continental Divide in: «International Journal of Philosophical Studies», 9 (2001) n. 3, pp. 349-367; F. D’Agostini, Logica del nichilismo, Laterza, Roma-Bari 2000; F. Berto, Che Cos’è la Dialettica Hegeliana? Un’Interpretazione Analitica del Metodo, Il Poligrafo, Padova 2005 are worth noting. 7 S. Read, Thinking About Logic, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1995, p. 1. 8 JC Beall-G. Restall, Logical Pluralism, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2006, p. 3. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 299 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 299 «I know what you are thinking about», said Tweedledum: «but it isn’t so, nohow». «Contrariwise» continued Tweedledee, «if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be: but as it isn’t, it ain’t. That’s logic». Priest comments: What Tweedledee is doing is reasoning, and that is what logic is about. We all reason. We try to figure out what is so, reasoning on the basis of what we already know9. All these definitions are in substantial continuity with Aristotle’s conception in the Prior Analytics, according to which: A deduction is speech (logos) in which, certain things having been supposed, something different from those supposed results of necessity because of their being so10. Logic is thus the inquiry into what necessarily follows from what. According to Beall and Restall: Necessity is one feature which classically determines logical consequence: the truth of the premises of a valid argument necessitates the truth of the conclusion of the argument. […] Necessity is borne by the transition from the premises to the conclusion. What is necessary, in an argument from A to B, is […] the connection between A and B. The conditional if A then B is true of necessity11. All this stated, some fundamental questions arise: why having supposed certain things, something different necessarily follows from them? And what does it mean that the truth of the premises necessitates the truth of the conclusion? The two notions of validity defined by contemporary logic12 are of a certain relevance in relation to Hegel’s perspective. According to the concept of syntactic validity, a reasoning is valid if it follows the logical rules of the language in which it is formulated. In this sense, necessity is basically linguistic necessity. The normativity of logic is based on the logical constraints produced by logical languages, or systems. In traditional logic, logical constraints (rules) come from thought (are rules of thought). This basically holds also for Kant, and for Hegel (though in a slightly different way). According to the notion of semantic validity, validity is based on truth. In the semantic definition, an inference is valid if given the truth of the premises, also the conclusion is true. This is the so called requisite of truth preserv9 10 11 12 22-28. G. Priest, Logic. A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2000, p. 1. Aristotle, Prior Analytics, I. 2, 24b18-20. J.C. Beall and G. Restall, op. cit., 14-15. See S. Haack, Philosophy of Logic, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1978, pp. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 300 16:54 Pagina 300 Elena Ficara ing, which the definitions of logical necessity considered above refer to. Here the logical constraints come from the world, or from the facts that make true the premises and/or the conclusion. But notably, the formula «if the premises are true also the conclusion is true» does not say anything about the real effective truth, truth with reference to the world in which we live. The expression «given the truth of the premises» means «in any possible world in which the premises are true». The truth presupposed is possible or hypothetical. The two notions are not rival. They simply come from looking at validity from different perspectives. Though, it should be noted that the first notion of validity is established by the axioms or rules of language, so – as it seems – is ontologically neutral; while the second is ontologically committed, with reference to some world. But notably, the world at stake is a possible world (rather: a set of possible worlds). So we can say that in both cases validity is a formal phenomenon, and the enterprise of logic is still to establish validity «in virtue of form», like Sider writes13. Interestingly, also for Kant and for Hegel the connection between form (language) and being (truth) is the fundamental problem of logic, in different ways. 2. Logic and Necessity When Hegel speaks about the idea of logic, and logical consequence (in the Introduction to the Encyclopaedia and in the Vorbegriff to the Logic of the Encyclopaedia) he always uses the formulation: «universality and necessity», a typically Kantian formulation. Kant famously defines «universal and necessary» the field of a priori structures that constitutes the main theme of logic. The formulation «general or formal logic» goes also back to Kant. In the Jäsche Logic we read: Everything in nature [...] takes place according to rules, although we do not always know these rules. Water falls according to laws of gravity [...] the fish in the water, the bird in the air, moves according to rules. All nature, indeed, is nothing but a combination of phenomena which follow rules ; and nowhere is there any irregularity14. 13 See T. Sider, Philosophical Logic, Oxford University Press, Oxford-New York 2010, p. 2. «Alles in der Natur [...] geschieht nach Regeln, ob wir gleich diese Regeln nicht immer kennen. Das Wasser fällt nach Gesetzen der Schwere [...] der Fisch im Wasser, der Vogel in der Luft bewegt sich nach Regeln. Die ganze Natur überhaupt ist eigentlich nichts anderes als ein Zusammenhang von Erscheinungen nach Regeln; und es gibt überall keine Regellosigkeit». I. Kant, Werke in zwölf Bänden, Herausgegeben von Wilhelm Weischedel, Band 2: Schriften zur Metaphysik und Logik, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M. 1996, p. 432. 14 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 301 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 301 Kant underlines then that thought (or: the understanding) as the faculty of discovering and fixing rules, moves according to certain rules. Then he asks: according to which rules does thought itself move? This is the specific question that, according to Kant, gives rise to the logical inquiry. Logic is not the study of particular regularities (those of the fish’s swimming, the bird’s flying or of water’s falling: die Regeln des besonderen Erkenntnisgebrauchs/the rules of thought’s particular use), but the inquiry into the general and universal rules of thought (die Regeln des allgemeinen Erkenntnisgebrauchs/ the rules of thought’s universal use). The latter are common to all thoughts: whatever object we think about, we have to use them; the former concern a limited use of thought, and a limited field of objects. This means that the regularities of thought’s general use are necessary, while particular rules are contingent: If, however, we set aside all knowledge that we can only borrow from objects, and reflect simply on the exercise of thought in general, then we discover those rules which are absolutely necessary, independently of any particular objects of thought, because without them we cannot think at all.15. Similarly, in the Critique of Pure Reason Kant connects the universality of the logical field to its formality, underlying that: General logic abstracts from every content of knowledge and from the differences between objects and only has to do with the mere form of thought16. According to Greg Restall, this Kantian view is fundamental in order to understand what logic (in general and today) is and why it is indispensable for us. He comments: When we do logic we don’t care about what it is that the statements are about, we don’t care that my statements might be about tables and chairs or might be about numbers or about platonic ideas. Logic abstracts away from the identity of the objects, the differences of the objects and only has to do with the structure of thought. In one sense, logic is a very timid enterprise, because it only considers a very re15 «Wenn wir nun aber alle Erkenntnis, die wir bloß von den Gegenständen entlehnen müssen, bei Seite setzen und lediglich auf den Verstandesgebrauch reflektieren: so entdecken wir diejenigen Regeln desselben, die in aller Absicht und unangesehen aller besonderen Objekte des Denkens schlechthin notwendig sind, weil wir ohne sie gar nicht denken würden. Diese Regeln können daher auch a priori, d. i. unabhängig von aller Erfahrung eingesehen werden weil sie, ohne Unterschied der Gegenstände, bloß die Bedingungen des Verstandesgebrauchs überhaupt, er mag rein oder empirisch sein, enthalten» (I. Kant, op. cit., p. 433). 16 «Die allgemeine Logik abstrahiert von allem Inhalt der Erkenntnis und von dem Unterschied der Gegenstände und hat mit nichts anderem zu tun als mit der bloßen Form des Denkens». The Critique of Pure Reason is quoted following the Academy-edition (second edition): I. Kant, Gesammelte Werke, hrsg. von der (Königlichen) Preußischen (später Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. I ff., Berlin 1900 ff. (=B). B 26. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 302 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 302 Elena Ficara stricted domain. But in a sense it is very ambitious, because it considers the structure of absolutely everything that can be thought. So logic is about nothing, in a very important sense, but because it is about nothing it is about anything that can be thought17. Thus – in both Kant’s definition in the Critique of Pure Reason and Restall’s interpretation – logic’s generality (as the characteristic of abstracting away from all particular content) coincides with its formality (as the prerogative of considering the mere structure or form, and not the content, of thought)18. In the Jäsche Logik Kant identifies logic’s generality or formality with its necessity. And, in a similar way, Greg Restall underlines in Logic. An Introduction, that: «The necessity of logic is a matter of its generality»19. Kant’s idea implies that if we consider how we factually reason (that is: derive conclusions from premises), we recognise certain recurrent patterns. For example, I know that if the train to Bochum is late, I won’t catch the connection to Berlin; and this means that if it is true that the train to Bochum is late, it is true that I won’t catch the connecting train to Berlin. In the same way, I know that if the pumpkins are sold out, we won’t have pumpkin soup for dinner; so if it is true that pumpkins are effectively sold out, I know that we most certainly won’t have pumpkin soup for dinner. If I focus on the form of these inferences, letting out their specific contents, I see that in both cases we have a unique form: if p then q, p therefore q. I have thus isolated the contents of the two inferences focussing on their identical form. This form is called modus ponens and is – together with other forms – always active when we speak or think. If we reflect in this way about what we do when we speak or think, we discover that there are (relatively few) fundamental recurrent forms at the basis of our arguments or inferences. At this point, the question is: what does it mean that logical forms are necessary? Kant points out that logic does not tell us how we think, but how we should think20. So the logical forms do not only describe the structure of thought, but, abstracting away from the peculiar contents or circumstances, they also indicate how we ought to think, always and in all circumstances. Insofar as I recognise how I think, how thought works, I also know when it does not work. Thus the valid form is not only the result of the consideration of how 17 G. Restall in interview with Adam Saunders at abc Radio/The Philosopher’s Zone. In the history and philosophy of logic, the question of the connection between formality and generality is controversial. On the difference between “generalisation“ and “formalisation” see E. Tugendhat, Vorlesungen zur Einführung in die sprachanalytische Philosophie, cit., pp. 3951. On the several meanings in which logic is said to be formal see C. Dutilh Novaes, The Different Ways in which Logic is (said to be) Formal, in «History and Philosophy of Logic», 32(2011) n. 4, pp. 303-332. 19 G. Restall, Logic. An Introduction, Routledge, London-New York 2006, p. 215. 20 I. Kant, Schriften zur Metaphysik und Logik, cit., p. 437. 18 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 303 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 303 we factually think (the description of how we validly think), but also the prescription of how we ought to think. The Kantian meaning of logical necessity is thus so explained: that the forms are necessary means that they oblige us to follow them. As soon as we recognise them, we recognise their binding (normative) nature. But what is the reason of logic’s coercitive force? Why are logical forms binding? In Aristotle’s conception, logos (what we say and think) is ultimately rooted in on (being), and this implies that logical rules are binding insofar as they are able to give an account of what really is. For instance, in the Categories Aristotle writes that the truth of what we think or say is rooted in what is: The fact of the being of a man carries with it the truth of the proposition that he is, and the implication is reciprocal: for if a man is, the proposition wherein we allege that he is, is true, and conversely, if the proposition wherein we allege that he is true, then he is. The true proposition, however, is in no way the cause of the being of the man, but the fact of the man’s being does seem somehow to be the cause of the truth of the proposition, for the truth or falsity of the proposition depends on the fact of the man’s being or not being21. From an Aristotelian point of view, the necessity of logical inference is thus grounded in the connection between logos and on: something necessarily follows from something because things are in a certain way, and our sentences and arguments express how things are and behave. However, the Aristotelian connection between logic (formal logic) and being is not explicitly developed by Kant. In the Jäsche Logik, Kant rather suggests that the notion of truth as «correspondence» is purely nominal, and cannot constitute a material criterion of truth22. The logical constraint, in Kant’s view, comes from the structures of thought as they are instantiated by human language, and there is no specific normativity of being. Being, as it is logically relevant, is rather the being of objects already elaborated by thought (phenomena), that is the being of conceptually grasped objects that figure in statements. 3. Logic and Metaphysics Hegel’s reflections on logic and on the necessity of logical principles move along Aristotelian lines23. Also for Hegel, the question of effective truth, in21 Aristotle, Categories, 12, 15-19 (transl. by J. Ackrill, Categories and De Interpretatione, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1963). 22 See I. Kant, Schriften zur Metaphysik und Logik, cit., pp. 476-477. 23 On Hegel’s Aristotelism see V. Verra, Su Hegel, cit. pp. 349-369. On Hegel and Aristotle see A. Ferrarin, Hegel and Aristotle, Cambridge University Press, New York 2001. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 304 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 304 Elena Ficara tended as thought’s relation and correspondence to what is, is fundamental in order to explain the meaning of logical validity and necessity. In particular, Hegel’s reflections on logical necessity involve a consideration about the link between logic and metaphysics. In the Introduction to the Science of Logic Hegel considers the question of the relation between logic and metaphysics in the context of a consideration of the specific logical field, and of a critique of merely formal or subjective conceptions of thought. In this respect, ancient metaphysics had a «higher» conception of thought than modern philosophy. According to it, real is only what is graspable through thought, and thought is the very ground on which we can grasp something as existent. According to Anaxagoras, for instance, nous (i.e. thought) is «the principle of the world, and the essence of the world is to be defined as thought»24. According to Plato, «something has reality only in its concept»25. Hegel also remarks that the objective, and not psychological or subjective conception of thought is already present in our general and common idea of logic. But on the other side, one can appeal to the conceptions of ordinary logic itself; for it is assumed, for example, that the determinations contained in definitions do not belong only to the knower, but are determinations of the object, constituting its innermost essence and its very own nature. Or, if from given determinations others are inferred, it is assumed that what is inferred is not something external and alien to the object, but rather that it belongs to the object itself, that to the thought there is a correspondent being26. According to the ordinary conception of logic, logical rules are not arbitrary, or dependent on who thinks them, they are rather the very expression of the structure of what really is. In other words, when I derive conclusions from premises, saying for example: «all conservative politicians lye, Mitt Romney is a conservative politician therefore Mitt Romney lies», I claim to adequately grasp the object of what I say (in this case Mitt Romney and his truthfulness). 24 «Laut Anaxagoras ist der Nous das Prinzip der Welt und das Wesen der Welt soll als Gedanke bestimmt werden» (Hegel, Werke 5, p. 44). 25 «Laut Platon hat etwas nur in seinem Begriff Wirklichkeit» (Hegel, Werke 5, p. 44). 26 «Man kann sich auf die eigenen Vorstellungen der gewöhnlichen Logik berufen; es wird nämlich angenommen, daß z.B. Definitionen nicht Bestimmungen enthalten, die nur ins erkennende Subjekt fallen, sondern die Bestimmungen des Gegenstandes, welche seine wesentlichste eigenste Natur ausmachen. Oder wenn von gegebenen Bestimmungen auf andere geschlossen wird, wird angenommen, daß das Erschlossene nicht ein dem Gegenstande Äußerliches und Fremdes sei, sondern daß es ihm vielmehr selbst zukomme, daß diesem Denken das Sein entspreche. – Es liegt überhaupt bei dem Gebrauche der Formen des Begriffs, Urteils, Schlusses, Definition, Division usf. zugrunde, daß sie nicht bloß Formen des selbstbewußten Denkens sind, sondern auch des gegenständlichen Verstandes» (Hegel, Werke 5, 45). 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 305 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 305 Consequently, in the Vorbegriff of the Encyclopaedia Logic Hegel calls the logical forms which constitute the subject matter of logic «objective thoughts». With these explanations and qualifications, thoughts may be called objective thoughts – among which are also to be included the forms which are more especially discussed in the common logic, where they are usually treated as forms of conscious thought only. Logic therefore coincides with Metaphysics, the science of things set and held in thoughts – thoughts accredited able to express the essential reality of things27. Logic thus coincides with metaphysics because the forms we use when we think and reason express the very structures of what is. The forms analysed in logic are both determinations of thought (and not of things), and determinations of reality (since thought, according to Hegel who basically follows Aristotle, has the ability to grasp things as they are) and metaphysics – as the science of the essence of things – is one and the same as logic – as the science of the valid inference. Hegel observes that: If thought tries to form a notion of things, this notion (as well as sentences and arguments) cannot be composed of parts and relations which are alien and irrelevant to the things28. All this suggests that Hegel follows the ancient, Aristotelian conception, according to which the necessity of logos is not ontologically neutral. As a matter of fact, we also read that When logic is taken as the science of thinking in general, it is understood that this thinking constitutes the mere form of a cognition that logic abstracts from all content and that the so-called second constituent belonging to knowledge, namely its matter, must come from somewhere else; and that since this matter is absolutely independent of logic, this latter can provide only the formal conditions of genuine cognition and cannot in its own self contain any real truth, not even be the pathway to real truth because just that which is essential in truth, its content, lies outside logic. But in the first place, it is quite inept to say that logic abstracts from all content, that it teaches only the rules of thinking without any reference to what is thought or without being able to consider its nature. For as thinking and the rules of thinking are supposed to 27 «Die Gedanken können nach diesen Bestimmungen objektive Gedanken genannt werden, worunter auch die Formen, die zunächst in der gewöhnlichen Logik betrachtet und nur für Formen des bewussten Denkens genommen zu werden pflegen, zu rechnen sind. Die Logik fällt daher mit der Metaphysik zusammen, der Wissenschaft der Dinge in Gedanken gefasst, welche dafür galten, die Wesenheiten der Dinge auszudrücken» (Hegel, Werke 8, 81). 28 «Indem der Gedanke sich von Dingen einen Begriff zu machen sucht, dieser Begriff [...] nicht aus Bestimmungen und Verhältnissen bestehen kann, welche den Dingen fremd und äußerlich sind» (Hegel, Werke 8, 81). 015_Ficara_297.qxd 306 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 306 Elena Ficara be the subject matter of logic, these directly constitute its peculiar content; in them, logic has that second constituent, a matter, about the nature of which it is concerned29. Here Hegel observes that logic is indeed the science of thought in general (separated from every particular content), the consideration of the mere form of thought, and that this formal character of logic is at the very origin of the common critique according to which logical forms are empty, and have nothing to do with truth30. But this view is wrong, as forms are themselves logic’s specific content and subject matter. Thus logic is not a consideration of empty forms, because the forms it considers are forms of something (thought), and thought is both itself a specific content (the field of the logical theory) and able to express what truly is. Similarly, in the Lectures on Logic and Metaphysics of 1817 he maintains that not only the forms of thought, but also their truth, constitute the research field of logic. This also implies that logical forms are necessarily linked to nature, and natural language. Logic is for us a natural metaphysics. Everyone who thinks has it. Natural logic does not always follow the rules which are established in the logic as theory; these rules often tread down natural logic31. Significantly, Hegel distinguishes between logic as theory and logic as natural logic (or natural metaphysics). In this sense, Hegel seems to develop the Kantian notion of logical necessity in two senses32. First he underlines the role of concrete experience (natural logic and natural metaphysics) for the discovery and fixation of logical rules (the logical theory); second, he understands experience in an enlarged way, as already structured in terms of lan29 «Wenn die Logik als die Wissenschaft des Denkens im allgemeinen angenommen wird, so wird dabei verstanden, daß dies Denken die bloße Form einer Erkenntnis ausmache, daß die Logik von allem Inhalt abstrahiere und das sogenannte zweite Bestandstück, das zu einer Erkenntnis gehöre, die Materie, anderswoher gegeben werden müsse, daß somit die Logik, als von welcher diese Materie ganz und gar unabhängig sei, nur die formalen Bedingungen wahrhafter Erkenntnis angeben, nicht aber reale Wahrheit selbst enthalten, noch auch nur der Weg zu realer Wahrheit sein könne, weil gerade das Wesentliche der Wahrheit, der Inhalt, außer ihr liege» (Hegel, Werke 5, 36). 30 See for instance Kant’s conception of formal logic as the negative condition of, and not the path towards truth (B 84-85). 31 «Die Logik ist für uns eine natürliche Metaphysik. Jeder, der denkt, hat sie. Die natürliche Logik folgt nicht immer den Regeln, die in der Theorie für die Logik aufgestellt werden; diese Regeln zertreten häufig die natürliche Logik» (G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen über Logik und Metaphysik, Heidelberg 1817, herausgegeben von K. Gloy, Meiner, Hamburg 1992, p. 8. Cursives are mine). 32 On the concept of natural logic see A. Nuzzo, La logica, cit., pp. 47-50. Nuzzo explains here (pp. 47-48) that both expressions „natural logic“ and „science of logic“ were originally used by Kant. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 307 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 307 guage and thought (natural logic and natural metaphysics). This conception is perfectly coherent with Hegel’s Aristotelism, as Hegel repeatedly underlines that Aristotle’s empiricism was speculative33. Similarly, in the Preface to the second edition of the Science of Logic, we read that logical rules are sunk in human language and human nature, and that the general task of logic as theory is to become aware of this, making the rules that are implicit in our effective speaking and thinking the thematic field of our inquiry. In other words, when we speak or reason, we use specific patterns, for instance disjunctive syllogism (the door is open or closed, it is not closed, therefore it’s open), without knowing it. In this sense Hegel speaks about natural logic or logic as natural metaphysics (the logical rules are there, but unconsciously). The logical theory («logic» in the common meaning of the word, as referring to the discipline) consists in recognising these patterns, making them the object of inquiry. However, sometimes the logical theory «treads down» logic as natural metaphysics because it fixes rules, taking them as valid for every linguistic context, rules that are nevertheless refuted by the natural logic of language, or the natural metaphysics. For instance, logic finds within the natural logic of language the form of disjunctive syllogism «p or q, not p therefore q» and forgets that it does not lead per se to valid and sound arguments, but that it should be anchored in the analysis of predicates, and in the relation between words and what really is. If the argument34 «the door is open or closed, it is not open, therefore it’s closed» is sound, the argument, which is equally grounded on disjunctive syllogism, «you are either for the Palestinians or for the Israelis, you are not for the Israelis therefore you are for the Palestinians» is not sound, though presenting the form of disjunctive syllogism. The second argument is not sound because the predicates «being for the Palestinians» and «being for the Israelis» behave differently from the predicates «being open» and «being closed», and because it is not true that one is either for the Israelis or for the Palestinians, and that there is not a third possibility. A logic that dogmatically claims that the rules it fixes are the norm of truth, treads down the natural logic and metaphysics because it does not take into any account the meaning words and arguments have in concrete contexts, and their adequacy or inadequacy to express what truly is. 33 V. Verra, Su Hegel, cit., p. 364. There are many examples of the failures of classical logical rules in Hegel’s texts. See for instance Hegel, Werke 2, 575-581, Hegel, Werke 18, 526-538 as well as E. Ficara, Dialectic and Dialetheism, 34 (2013) n. 1, pp. 35-52. This example, which is taken from F. D’Agostini, Verità avvelenata, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino 2010, p. 31, shows quite plainly the limits of logical validity. Other clarifying examples can be found in G. Priest, Logic. A Very Short Introduction, cit., pp. 1-2; G. Restall, Logic, cit., pp. 212-213; S. Read, Thinking About Logic, cit., pp. 36-41. 34 015_Ficara_297.qxd 308 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 308 Elena Ficara Significantly, doubts about disjunctive syllogism, and conditionals, and other devices of classical logic, have led to non-classical logics, where they are interpreted hegelianly, as symptoms of the controversial normativity of logic when referred to natural metaphysic35. In the context of the discussion of Atomism, Hegel observes that one cannot escape metaphysics – which he defines here as merely consisting in tracing nature back to thoughts – by throwing oneself into Atomism’s arms. The atom is in itself a thought and the conception of matter as consisting of atoms is in itself a metaphysical conception. Pure physicians are, as a matter of fact, only the animals, because they do not think, whereby human beings are born metaphysicians. And the question is only if the metaphysics one uses is of the right kind, if we keep with univocal and fixed intellectual determinations as the basis of our theoretical and practical activity, instead of keeping with concrete, logical ideas36. Similarly, in the Naturphilosophie of the Encyclopaedia we read: What distinguishes the philosophy of nature from physics is the kind of metaphysics it adopts. As a matter of fact, metaphysics is nothing else than the range of thought determinations, the network in which we bring every matter and through which we make it understandable. Every educated mind has its metaphysics, the instinctual thought, the absolute power in us over which we become master when we make it the object of our thought37. Metaphysics is thus the structure of thoughts we use in order to grasp what is. If we want it or not, we – as thinking and acting human beings – always think and act according to some orienting general view (the natural, i.e. unconscious metaphysics). What is more, Hegel observes that these general orienting views can be problematic, because they oblige us to think in certain ways and to do certain things. When Hegel points our that the main problem 35 See G. Priest, An Introduction to Non-Classical Logics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 20082. 36 «Reine, pure Physiker sind in der Tat nur die Tiere, da diese nicht denken, wohingegen der Mensch, als ein denkender Wesen, ein geborener Metaphysiker ist. Dabei kommt es dann nur darauf an, ob die Metaphysik, welche man zur Anwendung bringt, von der rechten Art ist, und namentlich, ob es nicht, anstatt der konkreten, logischen Idee, einseitige, vom Verstand fixierte Gedankenbestimmungen sind, an welche man sich hält und welche die Grundlage unseres theoretischen sowohl als unseres praktischen Tuns bilden» (Hegel, Werke 8, 207). 37 «Das, wodurch sich die Naturphilosophie von der Physik unterscheidet, ist näher die Weise der Metaphysik, deren sich beide bedienen; denn Metaphysik heißt nichts anderes als der Umfang der allgemeinen Denkbestimmungen, gleichsam das diamantene Netz, in das wir allen Stoff bringen und dadurch erst verständlich machen. Jedes gebildete Bewußtsein hat seine Metaphysik, das instinktartige Denken, die absolute Macht in uns, über die wir nur Meister werden, wenn wir sie selbst zum Gegenstande unserer Erkenntnis machen» (Hegel, Werke 8, 20). 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 309 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 309 is therefore not if we have a metaphysics (or logic) or not, but if our metaphysics (i.e.: logic) is wide and flexible enough, he also refers to the risks of holding to a too rigid logic or metaphysics. Therefore he says that there is only one right metaphysics, and this is the «concrete, logical idea». By «concrete logical idea» he means dialectical logic, typically defined by Hegel as the logic of «concreteness», that is: «connection». In this sense, dialectical logic appears to be both: – the individuation of the most general patterns of thought (in Kant’s, but also the contemporary meaning of «formal logic»), obtained abstracting away from all content of thought, focussing on the mere form; and: – the critical reflection on these forms, a reflection which brings us to ask about their truth, i.e. their effective ability to grasp what is. For instance, if we assume atomism as our metaphysics, then we have the difficulty of giving an account of phaenomena such as the space-time continuum, which aren’t adequately graspable assuming that matter is constituted by atoms. Thus our logic and metaphysics has to be wide in order to grasp what experience presents us in every case, it must also be flexible, i.e. be ready to discuss its own structures, when they reveal to be inadequate. 4. Conclusion In the context of a consideration of Aristotle’s syllogistic in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Hegel writes: The form of an inference, as also its content, may be absolutely correct, and yet the conclusion arrived at may be untrue, because this form as such has no truth of its own; but from this point of view these forms have never been considered38. This Hegelian statement is a typically non-classical insight, shared by most contemporary philosophers of logic. As a matter of fact, researches in the philosophy of logic39 recognise that, sometimes, classical logical inference patterns are not able to convey truth as they, in principle, should. Read defends for this reason the importance of a critical reflection on basic logical notions. He observes: There are few books on the philosophy of logic. One reason is a widespread but re38 «Die Form eines Schlusses, so wie sein Inhalt, kann ganz richtig sein und doch sein Schlusssatz ohne Wahrheit, weil diese Form als solche für sich keine Wahrheit hat. Von dieser Seite aber sind diese Formen nie betrachtet worden» (Hegel, Werke 19, p. 240). 39 S. Haack, op. cit.; S. Read, op. cit. and see also, more recently, J.C. Beall and G. Restall, op. cit., and, in Italy, F. D’Agostini, I mondi comunque possibili. Logica per la filosofia e il ragionamento comune, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino 2012 and F. Berto, Teorie dell’assurdo, Carocci, Milano 2006. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 310 Pagina 310 Elena Ficara grettable attitude towards logic, one of deference and uncritical veneration. It is based on a mistaken belief that since logic deals with necessities, with how things must be, with what must follow come what may, that in consequence there can be no questioning of its basic principles, no possibility of discussion and philosophical examination of the notions of consequence, logical truth, and correct inference40. While Restall observes that: Logic is not a completed science, and teaching it as it is one gives the mistaken impression that all the important issues have been decided and all of the important questions have been given definitive answers. This is a misrepresentation of the state of the art41. For Read and Restall, as well as for Hegel, logic is not a rigid canon, which has to be accepted as it is once and for all. According to Hegel, logic as theory has to be continuously re-thought in consideration of the natural logic of language, and of our implicit metaphysics. Similarly, according to Haack, thinking about logical necessity involves considerations about implicit epistemological and metaphysical assumptions: The very rigour that is the chief virtue of formal logic is apt, also, to give it an air of authority, as if it were above philosophical scrutiny. And that is a reason, also, why I emphasise the plurality of logical systems; for in deciding between alternatives one is often obliged to acknowledge metaphysical or epistemological preconceptions that might otherwise have remained implicit42. The Hegelian way to deal with the failures of logical necessity seems to imply two kinds of reactions. On the one side, the awareness that logical validity and necessity might fail implies – exactly as in contemporary views – the idea that a critical reflexion about these forms, that is: what today is called «philosophy of logic», as critical enterprise, which is concerned with the limits and resources of (classical) logic, is needed. What is more, what Hegel calls «logic» is both the fixation of the rules of valid inference and the critical reflection upon them. On the other side, referring to Aristotle’s logic, Hegel also claims that: There are a number of kinds of judgment and inferences, each of which is held to be per se valid, and is supposed to have truth so as it is, per se. Thus they are simply content, indifferent, detached content: the famous laws of contradiction, identity etc., the forms of syllogisms etc. […] Thus they are only the material of [the] truth [of thought], the formless content; their deficiency is hence not that they are only forms but rather that form is lacking to them, and that they are in too great a degree content 43. 40 412 42 43 S. Read, op. cit., p. 2. G. Restall, op. cit., 4. S. Haack, op. cit., 10. «Es sind eine Menge Arten des Urteilens und des Schließens, deren jede so für sich gilt 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 311 Hegel Within Contemporary Logic 311 and: The scorn of logic rests simply on the false assumption that there is a lack of content. On the contrary, the error [of logical forms] is that they are in too great a degree content44. These observations imply that, according to Hegel, the problem with logic is not its lack of content (since Kant it is evident that logic has forms as its specific content or subject matter) but its lack of form. In this perspective, Hegel claims that formal logic, as the fixation of forms of valid inferences as it is traditionally conceived and practiced, has not yet a form. Dialectics can thus be plausibly interpreted as the logic that, critically reflecting on classical logical forms (of what we do when we fix forms such as the Law of Non Contradiction, the Law of the Excluded Middle, but also the basic logical operations such as negation, identity, etc.) gives classical logic the form it is lacking. As a matter of fact, the Science of Logic is precisely the critical reflection about logical necessity and logical forms elevated to a form and methodically developed. As far as I know, this insight has not been considered yet in contemporary options. Contemporary philosophers of logic neither explicitly admit that their reflection follows unitary patterns, neither consider their own reflection on classical logic and its possible failures as what gives logic rigour and the status of a science45. In this sense, the Hegelian view on logic not only appears to be perfectly compatible with contemporary philosophy of logic, but it also might constitute a contribute to its self-awareness. In conclusion, what is characteristic for the Hegelian account is the consideration of dialectic as the specific form of the critical reflection upon forms. Thus to the question: «What kind of logic is Hegel’s logic?» is possible to answer: philosophy of logic elevated to a form and methodically developed. In particular, in Hegel as well as in contemporary logic, emerges that the critical reflection upon logic goes hand in hand with the recognition of the failures of validity and necessity of the forms of traditional logic, because sometimes und an und für sich, als solche Wahrheit haben soll. So sind sie eben Inhalt, gleichgültiges, unterschiedenes Sein: die berühmten Gesetze des Widerspruchs usf., die Schlüsse usf. [...] Sie sind nur das Material der Wahrheit, der formlose Inhalt; ihr Fehler ist nicht, daß sie nur Form sind, sondern Form fehlt» (Hegel, Werke 19, p. 239). 44 «Die Verachtung der Logik selbst beruht auf dem falschen Gesichtspunkt des Mangels des Inhalts. Sie [die Formen] haben den Fehler, zu sehr Inhalt zu sein» (Hegel, Werke 19, p. 240). 45 This would require more detailed considerations about the link between dialectics and the concept of scientificity, and the differences between classical and dialectical demonstrations. On the scientific nature of the dialectical proof see H.-G. Gadamer, Hegels Dialektik. Fünf hermeneutische Studien (translated by C. Smith, Yale University Press, New Haven-London, 1976, pp. 6-7 and 30-32). 015_Ficara_297.qxd 312 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 312 Elena Ficara an inference is formally (classically) valid, and the premises are also true in any possible world, but the conclusion is not true. In addition, Hegel sees in dialectics the unitary form of this reflection about classical logic and its possible failures, contributing to establish dialectics as the form of our thinking about forms, and about truth. Abstract In this paper I consider Hegel’s idea of logic in different passages of his work (in the Introduction to the Science of Logic, in the Vorbegriff of the Encyclopaedia Logic, in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy), and I compare it with some contemporary conceptions of logic. In my view, such a comparison is relevant in at least two senses. First, it makes possible to address the controversial question: «what kind of logic is Hegel’s logic?». Second, it allows to locate Hegel’s view within contemporary debates, assessing its actuality. In this perspective, Hegel’s reflections reveal to be crucial in order to deal with some questions at the very core of contemporary debates in the philosophy of logic. 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 313 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 16:54 Pagina 314 Edizioni ETS Piazza Carrara, 16-19, I-56126 Pisa info@edizioniets.com - www.edizioniets.com Finito di stampare nel mese di giugno 2013 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 r va ia pe cop 16:54 Pagina 313 ione lutaz ione lutaz r va ia pe cop ione lutaz a per v a i p o c copi ne tazio valu a per valu a per copi cop copia copia ione lutaz r va ia pe e azion alut per v e azion alut per v copi cop zione cop ta r valu ia pe ne tazio valu a per e azion t u l a rv ia pe n tazio e 015_Ficara_297.qxd 12-06-2013 r va ia pe cop 16:54 Pagina 314 ione lutaz ione lutaz r va ia pe cop ione lutaz a per v a i p o c copi ne tazio valu a per valu a per copi cop copia copia ione lutaz r va ia pe e azion alut per v e azion alut per v copi cop zione aluta v r e ia p Edizioni ETS copPiazza Carrara, 16-19, I-56126 Pisa info@edizioniets.com - www.edizioniets.com Finito di stampare nel mese di giugno 2013 ne tazio valu a per e azion t u l a rv ia pe n tazio e TEORIA «Teoria» è indicizzata ISI e SCOPUS, e ha ottenuto la classificazione “A” per le riviste di filosofia morale. La versione elettronica di questo numero è disponibile sul sito: www.rivistateoria.eu copia one di filosofia taziRivista u l a v fondata da Vittorio Sainati per copia n tazio u l a v per Direzione e Redazione: Dipartimento di Filosofia dell’Università di Pisa, via P. Paoli 15, 56126 Pisa, tel. (050) 2215500 - www.fls.unipi.it Ultimi fascicoli apparsi della Terza serie di «Teoria»: Direttore: Adriano Fabris zione Comitato Scientifico Internazionale: Antonio Autiero (Münster), Damir Barbarić (Zagabria), Vinicius Berlendis de Figueiredo (Curitiba), Bernhard Casper (Freiburg i.B.), Néstor Corona (Buenos Aires), Félix Duque (Madrid), Günter Figal (Freiburg i.B.), Denis Guénoun (Parigi), Dean Komel (Lubiana), Klaus Müller (Münster), Patxi Lanceros (Bilbao), Regina Schwartz (Evanston, Illinois), Ken Seeskin (Evanston, Illinois), Mariano E. Ure (Buenos Aires). copia aluta per v Iscritto al Reg. della stampa presso la Canc. del Trib. di Pisa n° 10/81 del 23.5.1981. Direttore Responsabile: Adriano Fabris. Semestrale. Contiene meno del 70% di pubblicità. © Copyright 1981 by Edizioni ETS, Pisa. I numeri della rivista sono monografici. Gli scritti proposti per la pubblicazione sono peer reviewed. I testi devono essere conformi alle norme editoriali indicate nel sito. «Spinoza nel XXI secolo» XXXI/2012/1 (Terza serie VII/1) e azion t u l a er v XXXI/2011/2 (Terza ioneserie VI/2) lutaz aconoscenza v r «La formazione la ai tempi del web» e p copia XXXI/2011/1 (Terza serie VI/1) p copia «Critica della ragione medica» XXX/2010/2 (Terza serie V/2) ne «La figura e il pensiero di Armando Carlini» valutazio per Amministrazione: EDIZIONI ETS, piazza Carrara 16-19, 56126 Pisa, www.edizioniets.com, info@edizioniets.com tel. (050) 29544-503868 L’indice dei fascicoli di «Teoria» può essere consultato all’indirizzo: www.rivistateoria.eu. Qui è possibile acquistare un singolo articolo o l’intero numero in formato PDF, e anche l’intero numero in versione cartacea. XXXI/2012/2 (Terza serie VII/2) «Conformity and Dissent - Conformità e dissenso» Comitato di Redazione: Eva De Clerq, Annamaria Lossi, Carlo Marletti, Flavia Monceri, Antonia Pellegrino, Stefano Perfetti, Luisa Sassi. Abbonamento 2012: Italia € 0,00, Iva inclusa; estero Ñ0,00, da versare sul c.c.p. 14721567 intestato alle Edizioni ETS. Prezzo di un fascicolo: € 18,00, Iva inclusa. Prezzo di un fascicolo arretrato: € 20,00, Iva inclusa. e copia XXX/2010/1 (Terza serie V/1) «Filosofie dell’immagine» copia e azion alut per v XXIX/2009/2 (Terza serie IV/2) «Metamorphoses of Love - Metamorfosi dell’amore» zione luta a er v XXIX/2009/1 (Terza seriecoIV/1) pia p «Etica della comunicazione tra due continenti» XXVIII/2008/2 (Terza serie III/2) «Eurosofia. La filosofia e l’Europa» cop XXVIII/2008/1 (Terza serie III/1) «Il futuro del ione pensiero”. In dialogo con Franz Rosenzweig» taz“nuovo u l a v per XXVII/2007/2 (Terza serie II/2) copia ione lutaz r va ia pe «Ethicbots - Etica e robotica» XXVII/2007/1 (Terza serie II/1) zione p copia XXVI/2006/2 (Terza serie I/2) luta «Democrazie, appartenenza, valori er v-a Democracies, belonging, values» «Levinas in Italia» XXVI/2006/1 (Terza serie I/1) «L’identità in questione» Teoria_2013-1-cover.indd 2 13/06/13 09.28 zione aluta per v copia copia Scritti di: Claudio Cesa, Walter Jaeschke, Klaus Düsing, Jean-Louis Vieillard-Baron, Giuseppe Cantillo, Félix Duque, Riccardo Dottori, Franco Chiereghin, Michela Bordignon, Marcello Monaldi, Bernard Mabille, Pasqualino Masciarelli, Rainer Schäfer, Massimo zione Adinolfi, Elena Ficara. er valuta p copia copi Hegel Scienza della logica TEORIA Rivista di filosofia fondata da Vittorio Sainati XXXIII/2013/1 (Terza serie VIII/1) ne tazio valu a per e TEORIA XXXIII/2013/1 ISSN 1122-1259 azion alut per v Hegel Scienza della logica I l primo tomo della Wissenschaft der Logik fu pubblicato alla fine di aprile del 1812. Il secondo uscì dalla tipografia nel dicembre dello stesso anno, recando però come data il 1813. e azion alla “Logica oggettiva”. Il terzotavolume Entrambi erano one lutdedicati a v u zi l r a e v p r sullaco“Logica soggettiva”, che Hegel sperava di far peseguire immepia opia diatamente, uscì invece alla fine del 1816. c Siamo quindi a circa duecento anni dalla pubblicazione di quest’opera. Per tale occasione il presente volume di «Teoria», nelle sue varie parti, intende offrire una lettura approfondita di e alcuni del testo hegeliano. Ciò viene compiuto, com’è orionaspetti lutazstile della rivista, avvalendosi dei maggiori esperti a livello a v mai r pe copia internazionale e coinvolgendo nel progetto studiosi affermati di diverse generazioni. copi ne tazio valu a per zione ta r valu ia pe cop azion valut r e p copia e € 18,00 zione ISBN 978-884673663-5 copia Teoria_2013-1-cover.indd 1 aluta per v 9 788846 736635 ETS Edizioni ETS 13/06/13 09.28